메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 30, Issue 6, 2004, Pages 745-768

Apathy: The democratic disease

Author keywords

Achilles; apathy; democracy; egalitarianism; isonomia; Plato; political participation

Indexed keywords


EID: 34248060010     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0191453704045763     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (6)

References (53)
  • 2
    • 84884062670 scopus 로고
    • Domination consists in institutional conditions which inhibit or prevent people from participating in determining their actions or the conditions of their actions
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990), p. 38. (‘Domination consists in institutional conditions which inhibit or prevent people from participating in determining their actions or the conditions of their actions.’)
    • (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference , pp. 38
    • Young, I.M.1
  • 3
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 130
    • Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), pp. 120, 130.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms , pp. 120
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 5
    • 0003212016 scopus 로고
    • The United States
    • ed. Michel Crozier, Samuel P. Huntington, and Joji Watanuki (New York: New York University Press
    • Samuel P. Huntington, ‘The United States’, in The Crisis of Democracy, ed. Michel Crozier, Samuel P. Huntington, and Joji Watanuki (New York: New York University Press, 1975), pp. 113–15.
    • (1975) The Crisis of Democracy , pp. 113-115
    • Huntington, S.P.1
  • 6
    • 77749291467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • L'instant qu'un peuple se donne des représentants, il n'est plus libre
    • Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract, III.15; ‘L'instant qu'un peuple se donne des représentants, il n'est plus libre’.
    • The Social Contract , vol.3 , pp. 15
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 7
    • 84998088820 scopus 로고
    • We see our choice as a choice between being citizens or being slaves
    • See, for example, 4th edn (Berkeley: University of California Press
    • See, for example, Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy, 4th edn (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), p. 91 (‘We see our choice as a choice between being citizens or being slaves’);
    • (1984) Strong Democracy , pp. 91
    • Barber, B.1
  • 8
    • 84998186923 scopus 로고
    • The illiberal and, indeed, antidemocratic propensity of ordinary men and women is an undeniable fact that must be confronted
    • (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press)
    • Peter Bachrach and Aryeh Botwinick, Power and Empowerment (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1992), pp. 32–3 (‘The illiberal and, indeed, antidemocratic propensity of ordinary men and women is an undeniable fact that must be confronted’).
    • (1992) Power and Empowerment , pp. 32-33
    • Bachrach, P.1    Botwinick, A.2
  • 9
    • 0010198406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, estimates that in 4th-century Athens, only 6,000–8,000 attended the Assembly out of a civic body of about 30,000; see his, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Josiah Ober, for example, estimates that in 4th-century Athens, only 6,000–8,000 attended the Assembly out of a civic body of about 30,000; see his The Athenian Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), p. 23.
    • (1996) The Athenian Revolution , pp. 23
    • Ober, J.1
  • 10
    • 84935594342 scopus 로고
    • provides additional evidence supporting the suggestion that ‘there are grounds for believing that only a rather small minority of citizens attended the meetings of the Assembly’; see his, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 345
    • Robert Dahl provides additional evidence supporting the suggestion that ‘there are grounds for believing that only a rather small minority of citizens attended the meetings of the Assembly’; see his Democracy and Its Critics (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1989), pp. 11, 345.
    • (1989) Democracy and Its Critics , pp. 11
    • Dahl, R.1
  • 12
    • 84941925059 scopus 로고
    • see, ed. Andrew A. Lipscomb (Washington, DC
    • see The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, ed. Andrew A. Lipscomb (Washington, DC: 1904), vol. 14, pp. 421–3.
    • (1904) The Writings of Thomas Jefferson , vol.14 , pp. 421-423
  • 14
    • 84972707413 scopus 로고
    • Justice: On Relating Private and Public
    • For an example of a political theorist leveling the charge of emptiness against defenders of an abstract participatory politics, see
    • For an example of a political theorist leveling the charge of emptiness against defenders of an abstract participatory politics, see Hannah Pitkin, ‘Justice: On Relating Private and Public’, Political Theory 9 (1981): 327–52.
    • (1981) Political Theory , vol.9 , pp. 327-352
    • Pitkin, H.1
  • 15
    • 84997852480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans
    • Homer, The Iliad, I, 490–2; trans.
    • The Iliad , vol.1 , pp. 490-492
    • Homer1
  • 16
    • 84998187033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • A. T. Murray, rev. William F. Wyatt (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), vol. 1, pp. 49–51.
    • (1999) , vol.1 , pp. 49-51
    • Murray, A.T.1    Wyatt, W.F.2
  • 17
    • 84998091308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Twice in the first four lines of his re—emergence in Book Nine, Achilles is described as ‘being delighted’ (terpomenon) — a clear contrast to the rage and dissatisfaction that had characterized his initial conduct in Book One
    • A. T. Murray, rev. William F. Wyatt, 1999), IX, 186–9. Twice in the first four lines of his re—emergence in Book Nine, Achilles is described as ‘being delighted’ (terpomenon) — a clear contrast to the rage and dissatisfaction that had characterized his initial conduct in Book One.
    • (1999) , vol.9 , pp. 186-189
    • Murray, A.T.1    Wyatt, W.F.2
  • 18
    • 84997864060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • XI, 784
    • Homer, Iliad, IX, 427; XI, 784.
    • Iliad , vol.9 , pp. 427
    • Homer1
  • 19
    • 84998149570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ιση μοιρα μενοντι, και ει μαλα τις πολεμιζοι. εν δε ιη τιμη ημεν κακος ηδε και εσθλος. κατθαν ομως ο τ'αεργος ανηρ ο τε πολλα εοργως
    • Homer, Iliad, IX, 318–20. ιση μοιρα μενοντι, και ει μαλα τις πολεμιζοι. εν δε ιη τιμη ημεν κακος ηδε και εσθλος. κατθαν ομως ο τ'αεργος ανηρ ο τε πολλα εοργως.
    • Iliad , vol.9 , pp. 318-320
    • Homer1
  • 20
    • 84998147127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If the longing for fame were to be banished from life, what would be left worth having?
    • The centrality of the pursuit of fame to Greek culture persisted well beyond the archaic Greek civilization and the time of Homer. Solon was only expressing the norm when he wondered
    • The centrality of the pursuit of fame to Greek culture persisted well beyond the archaic Greek civilization and the time of Homer. Solon was only expressing the norm when he wondered: ‘If the longing for fame were to be banished from life, what would be left worth having?’ Lucian, Anacharsis, 15f.;
    • Anacharsis , pp. 15f
    • Lucian1
  • 21
    • 84998160321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cit., ed. Oswyn Murray, trans. Sheila Stern (New York: St Martin's Press, n. 37
    • cit. Jacob Burckhardt, The Greeks and Greek Civilization, ed. Oswyn Murray, trans. Sheila Stern (New York: St Martin's Press, 1998), pp. 389–90, n. 37.
    • (1998) The Greeks and Greek Civilization , pp. 389-390
    • Burckhardt, J.1
  • 22
    • 84998043181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • XI, 784. Both Glaucus and Achilles are sent to war by their fathers with these words. Numerous commentators have identified this line as the most fundamental principle of Greek life. See, for example
    • Homer, The Iliad, VI, 208; XI, 784. Both Glaucus and Achilles are sent to war by their fathers with these words. Numerous commentators have identified this line as the most fundamental principle of Greek life. See, for example
    • The Iliad , vol.6 , pp. 208
    • Homer1
  • 24
    • 0004152399 scopus 로고
    • (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press)
    • Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1958), p. 41.
    • (1958) The Human Condition , pp. 41
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 25
    • 84997980642 scopus 로고
    • rev. and re-presented Trevor J. Saunders (London: Penguin), 1253a7
    • T. A. Sinclair, rev. and re-presented Trevor J. Saunders (London: Penguin, 1992), p. 60, 1253a7.
    • (1992) , pp. 60
    • Sinclair, T.A.1
  • 26
    • 84997914964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, limits her conception of agonistic politics to the self-oriented pursuits of display, the drive for recognition and immortalization, and the performance of great words and speeches. She suggests that legislation is somehow non-agonistic. She speaks, for instance, of the tremendous influence within Greek antiquity of ‘the so-called agonal spirit, the passionate drive to show one's self in measuring up against others that underlies the concept of politics prevalent in the city-states. An outstanding symptom of this prevailing influence is that the Greeks, in distinction from all later developments, did not count legislating among the political activities’, Against Arendt, I suggest that legislation is a modern—day example of the agonal spirit, perhaps a more sublimated form than the pursuit of glory, but an intensely competitive practice nonetheless
    • Arendt, for example, limits her conception of agonistic politics to the self-oriented pursuits of display, the drive for recognition and immortalization, and the performance of great words and speeches. She suggests that legislation is somehow non-agonistic. She speaks, for instance, of the tremendous influence within Greek antiquity of ‘the so-called agonal spirit, the passionate drive to show one's self in measuring up against others that underlies the concept of politics prevalent in the city-states. An outstanding symptom of this prevailing influence is that the Greeks, in distinction from all later developments, did not count legislating among the political activities’ (Human Condition, p. 194). Against Arendt, I suggest that legislation is a modern—day example of the agonal spirit, perhaps a more sublimated form than the pursuit of glory, but an intensely competitive practice nonetheless.
    • Human Condition , pp. 194
    • Arendt1
  • 27
    • 0000365342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy
    • As an example of the search for a non-agonistic brand of politics, see, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
    • As an example of the search for a non-agonistic brand of politics, see Iris Marion Young, ‘Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy’, in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), pp. 120–35.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political , pp. 120-135
    • Young, I.M.1
  • 28
    • 0003872957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Politics of Friendship
    • trans. George Collins (London: Verso)
    • Jacques Derrida, Politics of Friendship, trans. George Collins (London: Verso, 1997), p. 104.
    • (1997) , pp. 104
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 29
    • 0001845081 scopus 로고
    • Politics as a Vocation
    • in H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (eds), (New York: Oxford University Press, 125
    • Max Weber, ‘Politics as a Vocation’, in H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (eds), From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), pp. 115, 125.
    • (1946) From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology , pp. 115
    • Weber, M.1
  • 30
    • 84998096821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Homer, Iliad, IV, 186, 209.
    • Iliad , vol.4 , Issue.186 , pp. 209
    • Homer1
  • 31
    • 84998033287 scopus 로고
    • 34:, ed. and trans. Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Solon, W 34: Early Greek Political Thought from Homer to the Sophists, ed. and trans. Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 27.
    • (1995) Early Greek Political Thought from Homer to the Sophists , pp. 27
    • Solon, W.1
  • 32
    • 0004281448 scopus 로고
    • 561c-d. Here I follow the translation of G. M. A. Grube and C. D. C. Reeve (Indianapolis: Hackett, These lines recall Achilles. In his apathy in Book Nine, Achilles drinks and plays the lyre. At other times, he is engaged as a soldier committed to a life of struggle, striving for distinction on the public stage. Sometimes he plays the role of a politician, participating in assemblies, and deliberating over the common good. Like the democratic person, Achilles fluctuates endlessly in his commitments. At one moment, Achilles chooses the short life of glory, then he rejects this choice, then he returns again to battle. Achilles wavers between going home and staying at Troy, an uncertainty that leaves him in a nether—region of idleness and neglect. Sometimes he speaks of the equality of all humans — rejecting the distinction between Greek and Trojan, the brave and the cowardly, the honored and the low—while at other times the reality of these divisions propels him to action. The one difference is that Achilles seems to have avoided the pleasant happiness which Plato assigns to the democratic individual
    • Plato, Republic, 561c-d. Here I follow the translation of G. M. A. Grube and C. D. C. Reeve (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1992), p. 232. These lines recall Achilles. In his apathy in Book Nine, Achilles drinks and plays the lyre. At other times, he is engaged as a soldier committed to a life of struggle, striving for distinction on the public stage. Sometimes he plays the role of a politician, participating in assemblies, and deliberating over the common good. Like the democratic person, Achilles fluctuates endlessly in his commitments. At one moment, Achilles chooses the short life of glory, then he rejects this choice, then he returns again to battle. Achilles wavers between going home and staying at Troy, an uncertainty that leaves him in a nether—region of idleness and neglect. Sometimes he speaks of the equality of all humans — rejecting the distinction between Greek and Trojan, the brave and the cowardly, the honored and the low—while at other times the reality of these divisions propels him to action. The one difference is that Achilles seems to have avoided the pleasant happiness which Plato assigns to the democratic individual.
    • (1992) Republic , pp. 232
    • Plato1
  • 34
    • 84998099630 scopus 로고
    • Is “Live Unknown” a Wise Precept?
    • in Moralia, trans. Benedict Einarson and Phillip H. De Lacy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1128–30. Plutarch says, ‘But not even the author of the precept wished to be unknown, as he made the very statement to escape from being unknown, dishonestly courting fame as a person of no ordinary wisdom by his advice to seek obscurity’; 1128B
    • Plutarch, ‘Is “Live Unknown” a Wise Precept?’, in Moralia, trans. Benedict Einarson and Phillip H. De Lacy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1967), vol. 14, p. 232, 1128–30. Plutarch says, ‘But not even the author of the precept wished to be unknown, as he made the very statement to escape from being unknown, dishonestly courting fame as a person of no ordinary wisdom by his advice to seek obscurity’; 1128B.
    • (1967) , vol.14 , pp. 232
    • Plutarch1
  • 35
    • 0347151585 scopus 로고
    • The remnants of Seneca's treatise stand as an extended version of Epicurus' short phrase and, as such, journey into the paradoxical realm of anti-politics. Seneca embraces retirement from public life so that one can concern oneself fully with the more significant and valuable matters of philosophy. In retirement, the wise man will investigate ‘what lies beyond this world’ and seek ‘knowledge of things immortal’. Yet, if the value of what lies beyond the world, and thus beyond politics, is what leads the philosopher away from politics, Seneca cannot persist in the unworldliness of what he describes, and he goes on to justify the retreat from public life on the basis of its public benefit. Seneca introduces the usefulness of political silence. ‘What is required, you see, of any man is that he should be of use to other men — if possible, to many; failing that, to a few; failing that, to those nearest him; failing that, to himself.’ By this, Seneca means not only to justify political silence on the basis of the corruption of political regimes, but also to demand of retirement from public life that it produce advantages for the common good. Retirement, Seneca says, has a duty to display itself, thus recalling the agonal urge to distinguish oneself in public that is central to war and politics alike. ‘Virtue is an incomplete and feeble good when wasted on a retirement without activity never displaying what it has learned.’ When he cites the philosophers Zeno and Chrysippus, who accomplished more in retirement than they would have done had they ‘commanded armies, held public office, and passed laws’, Seneca at once de-values public service in comparison with the private pursuit of philosophy yet relies on a notion of the common good to explain what makes philosophy superior to politics. Seneca supports retirement from political life not out of an incapacity to think in terms of benefit and harm, but because the common advantage can be secured by such a retreat, (eds), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • The remnants of Seneca's treatise stand as an extended version of Epicurus' short phrase and, as such, journey into the paradoxical realm of anti-politics. Seneca embraces retirement from public life so that one can concern oneself fully with the more significant and valuable matters of philosophy. In retirement, the wise man will investigate ‘what lies beyond this world’ and seek ‘knowledge of things immortal’. Yet, if the value of what lies beyond the world, and thus beyond politics, is what leads the philosopher away from politics, Seneca cannot persist in the unworldliness of what he describes, and he goes on to justify the retreat from public life on the basis of its public benefit. Seneca introduces the usefulness of political silence. ‘What is required, you see, of any man is that he should be of use to other men — if possible, to many; failing that, to a few; failing that, to those nearest him; failing that, to himself.’ By this, Seneca means not only to justify political silence on the basis of the corruption of political regimes, but also to demand of retirement from public life that it produce advantages for the common good. Retirement, Seneca says, has a duty to display itself, thus recalling the agonal urge to distinguish oneself in public that is central to war and politics alike. ‘Virtue is an incomplete and feeble good when wasted on a retirement without activity never displaying what it has learned.’ When he cites the philosophers Zeno and Chrysippus, who accomplished more in retirement than they would have done had they ‘commanded armies, held public office, and passed laws’, Seneca at once de-values public service in comparison with the private pursuit of philosophy yet relies on a notion of the common good to explain what makes philosophy superior to politics. Seneca supports retirement from political life not out of an incapacity to think in terms of benefit and harm, but because the common advantage can be secured by such a retreat. John M. Cooper and J. F. Procope (eds), Seneca: Moral and Political Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 172–80.
    • (1995) Seneca: Moral and Political Essays , pp. 172-180
    • Cooper, J.M.1    Procope, J.F.2
  • 36
    • 0347536757 scopus 로고
    • trans. Robin Hard (London: Everyman, 250 [IV.4.i, ii, xxiii]
    • Epictetus, The Discourses, trans. Robin Hard (London: Everyman, 1995), pp. 248, 250 [IV.4.i, ii, xxiii].
    • (1995) The Discourses , pp. 248
    • Epictetus1
  • 37
    • 0347068643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • however, does refer to the threefold distinction between the rule of the one, the few, and the many
    • Pindar, however, does refer to the threefold distinction between the rule of the one, the few, and the many. Pythian Odes, 2.86–8.
    • Pythian Odes , pp. 2.86-2.88
    • Pindar1
  • 41
    • 0038617524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ober, for example, locates a key source of democratic power in the popular control of public speech and places great emphasis on the fact that elites operating within the Athenian Assembly could always be shouted down by the assembled citizens (The
    • Ober, for example, locates a key source of democratic power in the popular control of public speech and places great emphasis on the fact that elites operating within the Athenian Assembly could always be shouted down by the assembled citizens (The Athenian Revolution, pp. 23–4).
    • Athenian Revolution , pp. 23-24
  • 42
    • 0004159762 scopus 로고
    • Also see, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chapter 4, for the argument that the Assembly maintained true sovereignty under the Athenian democracy
    • Also see R. K. Sinclair, Democracy and Participation in Athens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), chapter 4, for the argument that the Assembly maintained true sovereignty under the Athenian democracy.
    • (1988) Democracy and Participation in Athens
    • Sinclair, R.K.1
  • 43
    • 0004032769 scopus 로고
    • Some commentators have suggested that the polis was in fact understood to represent the character of the people. Hansen, for example, claims that ‘in a democratic polis, especially Athens, government and citizens largely coincided, primarily through the institution of the Assembly of the People, and the dominant ideology was that the polis was the people (demos): it manifests itself, for example, in all surviving treaties, where the state of Athens is called ho demos ho Athenaion, “the people of the Athenians”.’, trans. J. A. Crook (Oxford: Blackwell), This view does nothing to challenge the fact that individuals were not understood to embody the interests or character of the people and that politics, insofar as it is devoted to the selection of leaders, was not conceived as representative in the most literal sense of the word
    • Some commentators have suggested that the polis was in fact understood to represent the character of the people. Hansen, for example, claims that ‘in a democratic polis, especially Athens, government and citizens largely coincided, primarily through the institution of the Assembly of the People, and the dominant ideology was that the polis was the people (demos): it manifests itself, for example, in all surviving treaties, where the state of Athens is called ho demos ho Athenaion, “the people of the Athenians”.’ Mogens Herman Hansen, The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes, trans. J. A. Crook (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), p. 59. This view does nothing to challenge the fact that individuals were not understood to embody the interests or character of the people and that politics, insofar as it is devoted to the selection of leaders, was not conceived as representative in the most literal sense of the word.
    • (1991) The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes , pp. 59
    • Hansen, M.H.1
  • 44
    • 84998131555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, 1. Ober, however, downplays the significance of the popularly elected military and financial officers: ‘Although annually elected (rather than lotteried) generals (in the fifth century) and elected financial magistrates (in the fourth century) were indeed important players in the government, they had limited decisionmaking power.’ Athenian Revolution, p. 25
    • See, for example, Aristotle, Athenian Constitution, XLIV.4, LXI.1. Ober, however, downplays the significance of the popularly elected military and financial officers: ‘Although annually elected (rather than lotteried) generals (in the fifth century) and elected financial magistrates (in the fourth century) were indeed important players in the government, they had limited decisionmaking power.’ Athenian Revolution, p. 25.
    • Athenian Constitution , vol.44 , Issue.4 , pp. LXI
    • Aristotle1
  • 45
    • 84998089130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle reports that in the time of Solon all magistrates were chosen by lot from an elected short list (Athenian Constitution, VIII.1) and that from the period between 487 and 403 BC archons were selected by lot from an elected short list (Athenian Constitution, XXII.5)
    • Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, II.37. Aristotle reports that in the time of Solon all magistrates were chosen by lot from an elected short list (Athenian Constitution, VIII.1) and that from the period between 487 and 403 BC archons were selected by lot from an elected short list (Athenian Constitution, XXII.5).
    • History of the Peloponnesian War , vol.2 , pp. 37
    • Thucydides1
  • 46
    • 84998076744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • individual merit was undoubtedly a factor in the advance screening of candidates for selection
    • note that, in their
    • Moreover, Gagarin and Woodruff note that ‘individual merit was undoubtedly a factor in the advance screening of candidates for selection’ in their Early Greek Political Thought, p. 94.
    • Early Greek Political Thought , pp. 94
    • Moreover, G.1
  • 47
    • 0013490039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And Hansen reports that in Athens ‘after selection [by lot] the candidates all had to undergo dokimasia, which, after 403/2, was reformed so as to give the People's Court the opportunity to reject on the spot anyone who might be suspected of oligarchic tendencies’
    • And Hansen reports that in Athens ‘after selection [by lot] the candidates all had to undergo dokimasia, which, after 403/2, was reformed so as to give the People's Court the opportunity to reject on the spot anyone who might be suspected of oligarchic tendencies’; Athenian Democracy, pp. 236–7.
    • Athenian Democracy , pp. 236-237
  • 49
    • 84997980662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Old Oligarch
    • Here I follow the translation of Gagarin and Woodruff in
    • ‘Old Oligarch’, I, 2. Here I follow the translation of Gagarin and Woodruff in Early Greek Political Thought, p. 134.
    • Early Greek Political Thought , vol.1 , Issue.2 , pp. 134
  • 50
    • 84998099761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thucydides, for example, notes the tendency of party leaders engaged in factional strife to rely upon the ‘fair-sounding names’ of isonomy and aristocracy to designate what was really democracy and oligarchy
    • Thucydides, for example, notes the tendency of party leaders engaged in factional strife to rely upon the ‘fair-sounding names’ of isonomy and aristocracy to designate what was really democracy and oligarchy. History of the Peloponnesian War, III.82.8.
    • History of the Peloponnesian War , vol.3 , Issue.82 , pp. 8
  • 51
    • 0003827187 scopus 로고
    • Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, no. 51 [James Madison]
    • The Federalist Papers, ed. Jacob E. Cooke (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 1961), no. 51 [James Madison].
    • (1961) The Federalist Papers
    • Cooke, J.E.1
  • 52
    • 0003700672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, worries that contemporary American democracy suffers from ‘the fear that, individually and collectively, we are losing control of the forces that govern our lives’, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Michael Sandel, for example, worries that contemporary American democracy suffers from ‘the fear that, individually and collectively, we are losing control of the forces that govern our lives’. Democracy's Discontent (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. 1.
    • (1996) Democracy's Discontent , pp. 1
    • Sandel, M.1
  • 53
    • 84874587393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1133a, Aristotle remarks that a political or commercial association ‘is formed not from two doctors but from a doctor and a farmer, and in general from parties that are different and not equal, but which must be equated’. Aristotle at once recognizes the fundamental importance of equality to the political enterprise, yet also that this equality is of a limited nature, for it depends on preserving the significance of inequality outside the realm of law. It is precisely this extra—nomotic inequality that the apathetic Achilles cannot recognize and which, consequently, de-motivates his interest in politics
    • Aristotle, Ethics, 1133a.13–31. Aristotle remarks that a political or commercial association ‘is formed not from two doctors but from a doctor and a farmer, and in general from parties that are different and not equal, but which must be equated’. Aristotle at once recognizes the fundamental importance of equality to the political enterprise, yet also that this equality is of a limited nature, for it depends on preserving the significance of inequality outside the realm of law. It is precisely this extra—nomotic inequality that the apathetic Achilles cannot recognize and which, consequently, de-motivates his interest in politics.
    • Ethics , pp. 13-31
    • Aristotle1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.