메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 2, Issue 1, 2003, Pages 37-62

Political Obligation and Military Service in Three Countries

Author keywords

fairness; liberalism; military service; political obligation; principle of fairness; state

Indexed keywords


EID: 34248056890     PISSN: 1470594X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/1470594X03002001423     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (50)
  • 1
    • 85004277215 scopus 로고
    • obligation
    • We also generally use the terms and ‘duty’ interchangeably; for discussion of these concepts, see Richard Brandt, ‘The Concepts of Obligation and Duty’, Mind 73: 374-93; James Mish'Alanai, ‘“Duty,” “Obligation,” and “Ought”’, Analysis: 33-41; Herbert L.A. Hart, ‘Legal and Moral Obligation’, in Essays in Moral Philosophy, edited by A.I. Melden (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958). Because we do not construe political obligations as necessarily grounded in voluntary actions, we view strong moral reasons to obey the law as constituting an adequate theory of political obligation, whether or not these reasons stem from ‘obligations’ in the strict sense. For discussion, see A. John Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), Chs 1-2; George Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992), Ch. 1.
    • We treat the question of political obligation as basically interchangeable with why people should obey the law. We also generally use the terms ‘obligation’ and ‘duty’ interchangeably; for discussion of these concepts, see Richard Brandt, ‘The Concepts of Obligation and Duty’, Mind 73 (1964): 374-93; James Mish'Alanai, ‘“Duty,” “Obligation,” and “Ought”’, Analysis 30 (1969): 33-41; Herbert L.A. Hart, ‘Legal and Moral Obligation’, in Essays in Moral Philosophy, edited by A.I. Melden (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958). Because we do not construe political obligations as necessarily grounded in voluntary actions, we view strong moral reasons to obey the law as constituting an adequate theory of political obligation, whether or not these reasons stem from ‘obligations’ in the strict sense. For discussion, see A. John Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), Chs 1-2; George Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992), Ch. 1.
    • (1964) We treat the question of political obligation as basically interchangeable with why people should obey the law , vol.30 , Issue.1969
  • 3
    • 85004355842 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • Leslie Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), Ch. 3.
    • (1988) The Authority of the State , Issue.3
    • Green, L.1
  • 4
    • 85004518510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See John T. Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds, For and Against the State (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield).
    • See Simmons, Moral Principles; Klosko, Principle of Fairness; John T. Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds, For and Against the State (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996).
    • (1996) Simmons, Moral Principles; Klosko, Principle of Fairness
  • 5
    • 85004331810 scopus 로고
    • Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics
    • see A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 47-8. On reflective equilibrium, see Rawls, Theory of Justice, pp. 19–21, 46-53, 578-86; Rawls, Philosophical Review 60: 177-97; Norman Daniels, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics’, Journal of Philosophy 1979: 256-82. For criticisms of reflective equilibrium, see Richard M. Hare, ‘Rawls's Theory of Justice’, in Reading Rawls, edited by N. Daniels (New York: Basic Books, 1974); David Lyons, ‘Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments’, in Reading Rawls; Peter Singer, ‘Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium’, Monist 58 (1974): 490-517. For the resemblances between judicial decision-making and reflective equilibrium, see Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977), Chs 4 and 6.
    • On considered judgments, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 19–20, 47-8. On reflective equilibrium, see Rawls, Theory of Justice, pp. 19–21, 46-53, 578-86; Rawls, ‘Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics’, Philosophical Review 60 (1951): 177-97; Norman Daniels, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics’, Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979): 256-82. For criticisms of reflective equilibrium, see Richard M. Hare, ‘Rawls's Theory of Justice’, in Reading Rawls, edited by N. Daniels (New York: Basic Books, 1974); David Lyons, ‘Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments’, in Reading Rawls; Peter Singer, ‘Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium’, Monist 58 (1974): 490-517. For the resemblances between judicial decision-making and reflective equilibrium, see Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977), Chs 4 and 6.
    • (1951) On considered judgments , vol.76 , pp. 19-20
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 7
    • 84972665331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wide Reflective Equilibrium
    • Daniels
    • Daniels, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium’, p. 258.
  • 8
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Columbia University Press), It is worth noting that, in one respect, the judgments of philosophers may not approximate Rawlsian considered judgments. Philosophers, invested in their own favored theories, may not be disinterested reasoners. We should also note, however, that in other respects (and for other reasons) individual judges are likely not to be disinterested moral reasoners either. Accordingly, in addition to particular judicial decisions, we are interested in how their reasoning stands up over time and is viewed by subsequent courts. We recognize, however, that desires to abide by precedent can complicate matters in this regard (but see note 15, below).
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), pp. 54–8. It is worth noting that, in one respect, the judgments of philosophers may not approximate Rawlsian considered judgments. Philosophers, invested in their own favored theories, may not be disinterested reasoners. We should also note, however, that in other respects (and for other reasons) individual judges are likely not to be disinterested moral reasoners either. Accordingly, in addition to particular judicial decisions, we are interested in how their reasoning stands up over time and is viewed by subsequent courts. We recognize, however, that desires to abide by precedent can complicate matters in this regard (but see note 15, below).
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 54-58
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 10
    • 0032219767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Obligation and the United States Supreme Court
    • Mark Hall and George Klosko, ‘Political Obligation and the United States Supreme Court’, Journal of Politics 60 (1998): 462-80.
    • (1998) Journal of Politics , vol.60 , pp. 462-480
    • Hall, M.1    Klosko, G.2
  • 11
    • 4444316870 scopus 로고
    • The Israeli Legal System: Heritage and Culture
    • second revised edition, translated by Tony Weir (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992). The Israeli legal system inherited its basics from the Mandatory legal system. Since the establishment of the state of Israel, a system has evolved which combines common law as well as some Continental basics and Israeli heritage. See Aharon Barak, Hapraklit. The German BverG often follows previous case law, but is not bound by its previous decisions in the same manner as the US Supreme Court. Accordingly, the repetition of and use by the Court of previous decisions stresses the importance of their arguments. See Hans Boldt, Deutsche Verfassungsgeschichte, 2 Bde. (München: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1990).
    • Konrad Zweigert and Hein Kotz, Introduction to Comparative Law, second revised edition, translated by Tony Weir (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992). The Israeli legal system inherited its basics from the Mandatory legal system. Since the establishment of the state of Israel, a system has evolved which combines common law as well as some Continental basics and Israeli heritage. See Aharon Barak, ‘The Israeli Legal System: Heritage and Culture’, Hapraklit 40 (1992): 197-217. The German BverG often follows previous case law, but is not bound by its previous decisions in the same manner as the US Supreme Court. Accordingly, the repetition of and use by the Court of previous decisions stresses the importance of their arguments. See Hans Boldt, Deutsche Verfassungsgeschichte, 2 Bde. (München: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1990).
    • (1992) Introduction to Comparative Law , vol.40 , pp. 197-217
    • Zweigert, K.1    Kotz, H.2
  • 12
    • 84899259395 scopus 로고
    • Judicial Review Without a Constitution: the Israeli Paradox
    • Amos Shapira, ‘Judicial Review Without a Constitution: the Israeli Paradox’, Temple Law Quarterly 56 (1983): 425.
    • (1983) Temple Law Quarterly , vol.56 , pp. 425
    • Shapira, A.1
  • 13
    • 0032388878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justifications of Conscientious Objection: An Israeli Case Study
    • For Israel, see Yoram Peri, ‘Israel: Conscientious Objection in a Democracy under Siege’, in The New Conscientious Objection: From Sacred to Secular Resistance, edited by C. Moskos and J.C. Whiteclay (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • For Israel, see Michael Keren, ‘Justifications of Conscientious Objection: An Israeli Case Study’, International Journal of the Sociology of Law 26 (1998): 121-37; Yoram Peri, ‘Israel: Conscientious Objection in a Democracy under Siege’, in The New Conscientious Objection: From Sacred to Secular Resistance, edited by C. Moskos and J.C. Whiteclay (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1998) International Journal of the Sociology of Law , vol.26 , pp. 121-137
    • Keren, M.1
  • 14
    • 85004401431 scopus 로고
    • In Defense of Anarchism (New York: Harper and Row); and also Green, Authority of the State.
    • Simmons, Moral Principles; Robert P. Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (New York: Harper and Row, 1970); and also Green, Authority of the State.
    • (1970) Simmons, Moral Principles
    • Wolff, R.P.1
  • 16
    • 52849105609 scopus 로고
    • Parfit's Moral Arithmetic and the Obligation to Obey the Law
    • See (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), Klosko, Principle of Fairness, Ch. 6; for paradoxical cases, see George Klosko, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20
    • See David Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), Ch. 5; Klosko, Principle of Fairness, Ch. 6; for paradoxical cases, see George Klosko, ‘Parfit's Moral Arithmetic and the Obligation to Obey the Law’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (1990): 191-214.
    • (1990) Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism , Issue.5 , pp. 191-214
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 17
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Natural Rights?
    • Herbert L.A. Hart, ‘Are There Any Natural Rights?’, Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 186.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , pp. 186
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 18
    • 85004414057 scopus 로고
    • Playing Fair with Punishment
    • Moral Principles, Klosko, Principle of Fairness; and Richard Dagger, Ethics 103: 473-88. The main criticisms of fairness theories have concerned difficulties in ‘accepting’ public goods; see Rawls, Theory of Justice, Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 93–5; Simmons, Moral Principles, Ch. 5; Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp.192–3; this objection is dealt with in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, Ch. 2. For additional criticisms, see A. John Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), Ch. 8.
    • The main discussions of the principle of fairness and political obligation are Simmons, Moral Principles, Ch. 5; Klosko, Principle of Fairness; and Richard Dagger, ‘Playing Fair with Punishment’, Ethics 103 (1993): 473-88. The main criticisms of fairness theories have concerned difficulties in ‘accepting’ public goods; see Rawls, Theory of Justice, pp. 113–6; Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 93–5; Simmons, Moral Principles, Ch. 5; Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp.192–3; this objection is dealt with in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, Ch. 2. For additional criticisms, see A. John Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), Ch. 8.
    • (1993) The main discussions of the principle of fairness and political obligation are Simmons , Issue.5 , pp. 113-116
  • 19
    • 85004519059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Obligation
    • Hall and Klosko
    • Hall and Klosko, ‘Political Obligation’.
  • 20
    • 77953256781 scopus 로고
    • 88 U.S. 162
    • Minor v. Happersett, 88 U.S. 162 (1875), pp. 165–6.
    • (1875) Minor v. Happersett , pp. 165-166
  • 21
    • 85004519059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Obligation
    • Hall and Klosko
    • Hall and Klosko, ‘Political Obligation’, pp. 474–7.
  • 22
    • 85004213046 scopus 로고
    • 245 U.S. 366
    • Arver v. U.S., 245 U.S. 366 (1918), p. 380.
    • (1918) Arver v. U.S , pp. 380
  • 23
    • 85004359106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1780, Art. 10. Similar language is found in the constitutions of New Hampshire and Vermont; White also cites New York, Delaware, Maryland, Virginia, and Georgia, but we do not find similar language in their constitutions.
    • Massachusetts Bill of Rights, 1780, Art. 10. Similar language is found in the constitutions of New Hampshire and Vermont; White also cites New York, Delaware, Maryland, Virginia, and Georgia, but we do not find similar language in their constitutions.
    • Massachusetts Bill of Rights
  • 25
    • 85004259686 scopus 로고
    • Die preußische Reformzeit-Das Landwehrkonzept
    • twenty-seventh edition (München: C.H. Beck'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung). For background on German laws concerning military service, see Reinhold Zippelius, Allgemeine Staatslehre, eleventh edition (München: C.H. Beck'sche Pub., 1991); Günter Wollstein, in Tradition als Last? Legitimitätsprobleme der Bundeswehr, edited by Klaus M. Kodalle (Köln: Wissenschaft und Politik, 1981); Donald Kommers, The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany (Durham: Duke University Press, 1989).
    • Theodor Maunz and Reinhold Zippelius, Deutsches Staatsrecht, twenty-seventh edition (München: C.H. Beck'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1988). For background on German laws concerning military service, see Reinhold Zippelius, Allgemeine Staatslehre, eleventh edition (München: C.H. Beck'sche Pub., 1991); Günter Wollstein, ‘Die preußische Reformzeit-Das Landwehrkonzept’, in Tradition als Last? Legitimitätsprobleme der Bundeswehr, edited by Klaus M. Kodalle (Köln: Wissenschaft und Politik, 1981); Donald Kommers, The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany (Durham: Duke University Press, 1989).
    • (1988) Deutsches Staatsrecht
    • Maunz, T.1    Zippelius, R.2
  • 26
    • 85004555895 scopus 로고
    • All translations of German and Israeli decisions are by the authors of this article.
    • BVerGE 12 (1960) 50-1. All translations of German and Israeli decisions are by the authors of this article.
    • (1960) BVerGE
  • 27
    • 85004355860 scopus 로고
    • BVerGE 38 (1974) 154.
    • (1974) BVerGE , vol.38 , pp. 154
  • 28
    • 85004355863 scopus 로고
    • BVerGE 48 (1978) 143.
    • (1978) BVerGE , vol.48 , pp. 143
  • 29
    • 85004232230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mit anderen Worten: Individueller grundrechtlicher Schutzanspruch und gemeinschaftsbezongene Pflicht der Bürger eines demokratisch verfassten Staates, zur Sicherung dieser Verfassungsordnung beizutragen, entsprechen einander (vgl. BVerGE 12, 45 [51]; 38, 154 [167]).
    • ‘Mit anderen Worten: Individueller grundrechtlicher Schutzanspruch und gemeinschaftsbezongene Pflicht der Bürger eines demokratisch verfassten Staates, zur Sicherung dieser Verfassungsordnung beizutragen, entsprechen einander (vgl. BVerGE 12, 45 [51]; 38, 154 [167]).’
  • 30
    • 85004259681 scopus 로고
    • BVerGE (1978)
    • (1978) BVerGE
  • 31
    • 85004514004 scopus 로고
    • BVerGE 69 (1985) 1-3.
    • (1985) BVerGE , vol.69 , pp. 1-3
  • 32
    • 85004389052 scopus 로고
    • In der demokratischen Verfassungsordnung des Grundgesetzes entsprechen einander der individuelle grundrechtliche Schutzanspruch und die gemeinschaftsbezogene Pflicht der Bürger, zur Sicherung dieser Verfassungsordnung beizutragen (vgl. BVerGE 48, 127 [161]). Die allgemeine Wehrpflicht ist Ausdruck des allgemeinen Gleichheitsgedankens. Ihre Durchführung steht unter der Herrschaft des Art. 3 Abs. 1 GG (BVerGE 48,127 [162]); ihre Erfülllung ist demokratische Normalität.
    • BVerGE 69 (1985) 22: ‘In der demokratischen Verfassungsordnung des Grundgesetzes entsprechen einander der individuelle grundrechtliche Schutzanspruch und die gemeinschaftsbezogene Pflicht der Bürger, zur Sicherung dieser Verfassungsordnung beizutragen (vgl. BVerGE 48, 127 [161]). Die allgemeine Wehrpflicht ist Ausdruck des allgemeinen Gleichheitsgedankens. Ihre Durchführung steht unter der Herrschaft des Art. 3 Abs. 1 GG (BVerGE 48,127 [162]); ihre Erfülllung ist demokratische Normalität.’
    • (1985) BVerGE , vol.69 , pp. 22
  • 33
    • 85004268544 scopus 로고
    • Das normative Ziel des Art. 12a Abs. 2 Satz 2 GG besteht darin, ein Gleichgewicht der Belastung von Wehr- und Ersatzdienstleistenden sicherzustellen.
    • BVerGE 69 (1985) 30: ‘Das normative Ziel des Art. 12a Abs. 2 Satz 2 GG besteht darin, ein Gleichgewicht der Belastung von Wehr- und Ersatzdienstleistenden sicherzustellen.’
    • (1985) BVerGE , vol.69 , pp. 30
  • 34
    • 85004518815 scopus 로고
    • BVerGE 69 (1985) 47.
    • (1985) BVerGE , vol.69 , pp. 47
  • 35
    • 85004302442 scopus 로고
    • §22 Satz 1 ZDG verstoße gegen das Verfassungsgebot der staatsbürgerlichen Pflichtengleichheit in Gestalt der Wehrgerechtigkeit (Art. 3 Abs. 1 GG), weil er dazu führe, daß gediente Kriegsdienstverweigerer stärker belastet würden als ungediente.
    • BVerGE 78 (1988) 367: ‘§22 Satz 1 ZDG verstoße gegen das Verfassungsgebot der staatsbürgerlichen Pflichtengleichheit in Gestalt der Wehrgerechtigkeit (Art. 3 Abs. 1 GG), weil er dazu führe, daß gediente Kriegsdienstverweigerer stärker belastet würden als ungediente.’
    • (1988) BVerGE , vol.78 , pp. 367
  • 36
    • 85004464176 scopus 로고
    • paragraphs
    • Defense Service Law (1949), paragraphs 11, 12.
    • (1949) Defense Service Law , vol.11 , pp. 12
  • 38
    • 85004418327 scopus 로고
    • (Consolidated Version)
    • Defense Service Law (Consolidated Version) 1986.
    • (1986) Defense Service Law
  • 40
    • 85004418326 scopus 로고
    • 1996.
    • Two less important cases which reached the Supreme Court were Alexander Epstein v. Minister of Defense and Others, 1995, and Sergei Baranowski v. Minister of Defense, 1996.
    • (1995)
  • 41
    • 0346760160 scopus 로고
    • The Elgazi Trials-Selective Conscientious Objection in Israel
    • Yoram Shachar, ‘The Elgazi Trials-Selective Conscientious Objection in Israel’, in Israel Yearbook on Human Rights 12 (1982): 214-58.
    • (1982) Israel Yearbook on Human Rights , vol.12 , pp. 214-258
    • Shachar, Y.1
  • 44
    • 84921967029 scopus 로고
    • Finding an Equilibrium
    • Judith, Karp, ‘Finding an Equilibrium’, in Israeli Democracy (1990), pp. 29–31.
    • (1990) Israeli Democracy , pp. 29-31
    • Karp, J.1
  • 47
    • 85004464186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.C. 953/87, 42 P.D. (2) 309. Poraz, a member of the Tel-Aviv-Jaffa city council, challenged a decision, forced on the city by the Minister of Religious Affairs, not to include women in the selection committee selecting the city's Religious Council. Barak ruled in favor of Poraz and referred to the need to maintain equality between men and women.
    • Poraz v. The Tel-Aviv-Jaffa Municipality, H.C. 953/87, 42 P.D. (2) 309. Poraz, a member of the Tel-Aviv-Jaffa city council, challenged a decision, forced on the city by the Minister of Religious Affairs, not to include women in the selection committee selecting the city's Religious Council. Barak ruled in favor of Poraz and referred to the need to maintain equality between men and women.
    • Poraz v. The Tel-Aviv-Jaffa Municipality
  • 49
    • 84928219263 scopus 로고
    • service conception
    • For the of authority, see Philosophy and Public Affairs
    • For the ‘service conception’ of authority, see Joseph Raz, ‘Authority and Justification’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 3-29.
    • (1985) Authority and Justification , vol.14 , pp. 3-29
    • Raz, J.1
  • 50
    • 85004519059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Obligation
    • See Hall and Klosko
    • See Hall and Klosko, ‘Political Obligation’.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.