메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 4, 2003, Pages 387-412

The democracy/contractualism analogy

(1)  Estlund, David a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34248047208     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2003.00387.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (15)

References (39)
  • 1
    • 78751663592 scopus 로고
    • famous phrase appears (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics,) (, ch. 1)
    • Adam Smith's famous phrase appears in A Theory of the Moral Sentiments (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 19821, p. 185 (part IV, ch. 1).
    • (1982) A Theory of the Moral Sentiments , Issue.PART IV , pp. 185
    • Smith'S, A.1
  • 2
    • 0002161865 scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
    • (London: Basil Blackwell, ), (hereafter, DDL)
    • "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity (London: Basil Blackwell, 1989), p. 20 (hereafter, DDL).
    • (1989) The Good Polity , pp. 20
  • 3
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press
    • What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1998), p. 153.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other , pp. 153
  • 4
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • (New York Columbia University Press,), e.g., (here-after, PL)
    • See Political Liberalism (NewYork Columbia University Press, igg3), e.g., p. 137 (here-after, PL).
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 137
  • 5
    • 0040436576 scopus 로고
    • Theoretical foundations of liberalism
    • Jeremy Waldron is an example, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,)
    • Jeremy Waldron is an example. See "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism," in Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 56-57.
    • (1993) Liberal Rights , pp. 56-57
  • 6
    • 78751661932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will use "outcome" and "decision" interchangeably, but "outcome" is less ambiguous as between process and product
    • I will use "outcome" and "decision" interchangeably, but "outcome" is less ambiguous as between process and product.
  • 7
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • PL, p. 330, emphasis added. Here Rawls echoes a point from (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, )
    • PL, p. 330, emphasis added. Here Rawls echoes a point from A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 221-22.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 221-222
  • 8
    • 78751672179 scopus 로고
    • (London: Routledge,), (hereafter, OJD)
    • On Justifying Democracy (London: Routledge, 1980), p. 101 (hereafter, OJD).
    • (1980) On Justifying Democracy , pp. 101
  • 9
    • 78751653835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DDL, p. 22.
    • DDL , pp. 22
  • 10
    • 0002805654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedure and substance in deliberative democracy
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Jess Benhabib (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), p. 101.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference , pp. 101
    • Benhabib, J.1
  • 11
    • 0003555163 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press, ), (hereafter, JAI)
    • Justice As Impartiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), p. 100 (hereafter, JAI).
    • (1995) Justice As Impartiality , pp. 100
  • 12
    • 78751675795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JAI, p. 104.
    • JAI , pp. 104
  • 13
    • 78751674231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • JAI, Ibid., p. 277, n. 36.
    • JAI , Issue.36 , pp. 277
  • 14
    • 78751676497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid
    • See JAI, ibid., p. 2.
    • JAI , pp. 2
  • 15
    • 78751658972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PL, p. 219.
    • PL , pp. 219
  • 16
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Jürgen Habermas's view, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press,)
    • For Jürgen Habermas's view, see Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms
  • 17
    • 0012164935 scopus 로고
    • Freedom and needs
    • 10 & 17 January
    • "Freedom and Needs," The New Republic, 10 & 17 January 1994, 31-38.
    • (1994) The New Republic , pp. 31-38
  • 18
    • 0004333573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his discussion of animals (), Scanlon allows contractors to represent the interests of certain noncontractors. Since animals are not present in either the hypothetical or the real choice contexts, there is no violation of analogy. But the same strategy is not available for the constituencies I mention in the text. They must apparently be participants in the hypothetical choice but not in the real democratic choice. This is a profound disanalogy whose normative damage can only be undone by giving actual participants motivations crucially different from those of the hypothetical contractors. The problem is much the same as the central one I am pressing: no plausible democratic institutions can really be modeled on the hypothetical contractualist situation because the motives there are too thin to promote justice in real contexts
    • In his discussion of animals (What We Owe, pp. 177-87), Scanlon allows contractors to represent the interests of certain noncontractors. Since animals are not present in either the hypothetical or the real choice contexts, there is no violation of analogy. But the same strategy is not available for the constituencies I mention in the text. They must apparently be participants in the hypothetical choice but not in the real democratic choice. This is a profound disanalogy whose normative damage can only be undone by giving actual participants motivations crucially different from those of the hypothetical contractors. The problem is much the same as the central one I am pressing: no plausible democratic institutions can really be modeled on the hypothetical contractualist situation because the motives there are too thin to promote justice in real contexts.
    • What We Owe , pp. 177-187
  • 19
    • 0242440593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberative democracy: A sympathetic comment
    • See Samuel Freeman's instructive discussion of this point as it figures in the views of
    • See Samuel Freeman's instructive discussion of this point as it figures in the views of Cohen and Habermas, in "Deliberative Democracy: A Sympathetic Comment," Philosophy & Public Affairs 29 (2000): 371-418.
    • (2000) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.29 , pp. 371-418
    • Cohen1    Habermas2
  • 20
    • 78751651255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • especially
    • OJD, especially pp. 111-18.
    • OJD , pp. 111-118
  • 21
    • 78751675328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • OJD, p. 119.
    • OJD , pp. 119
  • 22
    • 78751678437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philip Pettit observes that when we, actual moral agents, justify our actions to others, "we suppose in the very act of trying to justify ourselves . . . that there is an independent sense of right." This supposition is not available to the hypothetical contractors, which marks a decisive disanalogy
    • Philip Pettit observes that when we, actual moral agents, justify our actions to others, "we suppose in the very act of trying to justify ourselves . . . that there is an independent sense of right." This supposition is not available to the hypothetical contractors, which marks a decisive disanalogy.
  • 23
    • 0141568643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doing unto others
    • 25 June
    • See Pettit, "Doing Unto Others," Times Literary Supplement, 25 June 1999,7-8.
    • (1999) Times Literary Supplement , pp. 7-8
    • Pettit1
  • 24
    • 0003362723 scopus 로고
    • Fairness to goodness
    • Rawls writes that the point of the original position is to understand our conception of justice.. . by seeing how this conception is limited by and can be constructed from other notions that it is natural to think of as more basic and abstract. . . . This is the reason for bracketing conceptions of the right in the construction of the original position
    • Rawls writes that "the point of the original position is to understand our conception of justice.. . by seeing how this conception is limited by and can be constructed from other notions that it is natural to think of as more basic and abstract. . . . This is the reason for bracketing conceptions of the right in the construction of the original position." "Fairness to Goodness," Philosophical Review 84 (1975)
    • (1975) Philosophical Review , vol.84
  • 25
    • 0005386778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • reprinted in John Rawls: Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999) , p. 269.
    • (1999) John Rawls: Collected Papers , pp. 269
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 26
    • 0345775483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Debate: Saving scanlon: Contractualism and agent-relativity
    • Michael Ridge instructively defends Scanlon against these charges in. My interpretation of Scanlon is indebted to Ridge's article
    • Michael Ridge instructively defends Scanlon against these charges in "Debate: Saving Scanlon: Contractualism and Agent-Relativity," Journal ofPolitica1 Philosophy9 (2001): 472-81. My interpretation of Scanlon is indebted to Ridge's article.
    • (2001) Journal of Politica1 Philosophy , vol.9 , pp. 472-481
  • 27
    • 0004333573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If we were to appeal to a prior notion of rightness to tell us which considerations are morally relevant and which are entitled to prevail in cases of conflict, then the contractualist framework would be unnecessary, since all the work would already have been done by this prior notion
    • "If we were to appeal to a prior notion of rightness to tell us which considerations are morally relevant and which are entitled to prevail in cases of conflict, then the contractualist framework would be unnecessary, since all the work would already have been done by this prior notion" (What We Owe, p. 213).
    • What We Owe , pp. 213
  • 28
    • 78751651254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also page 214, where he says it would be circular to appeal to a "non-contractualist theory of right." On the other hand, he also says at page 5 that the parties are "moved by the aim of finding principles that others, similarly motivated, could not reasonably reject." This seems to give them the primary question: what principles are beyond reasonable rejection? The difficulty is similar to what it would be if the parties to Rawls's original position were themselves to ask, what principles would be unanimously agreed to behind the veil of ignorance? The exegetical problem raised by these quotes in Scanlon cannot be pursued here
    • See also page 214, where he says it would be circular to appeal to a "non-contractualist theory of right." On the other hand, he also says at page 5 that the parties are "moved by the aim of finding principles that others, similarly motivated, could not reasonably reject." This seems to give them the primary question: what principles are beyond reasonable rejection? The difficulty is similar to what it would be if the parties to Rawls's original position were themselves to ask, what principles would be unanimously agreed to behind the veil of ignorance? The exegetical problem raised by these quotes in Scanlon cannot be pursued here.
  • 29
    • 0004333573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon resists the complaint that the theory has little value unless all this content is made explicit so results can be cranked out mechanically (). This is not my complaint. The objection I raise in the text is about the structure of the account regardless of what particular content is given to the key ideas such as reasonableness
    • Scanlon resists the complaint that the theory has little value unless all this content is made explicit so results can be cranked out mechanically (What We Owe, pp. 217-18). This is not my complaint. The objection I raise in the text is about the structure of the account regardless of what particular content is given to the key ideas such as reasonableness.
    • What We Owe , pp. 217-218
  • 30
    • 78751659127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There would be no circularity in a contractor persuading others of a certain subsidiary matter: that the others could not reject certain proposals without thwarting their reasonably self-serving motives. This again suggests similarities with democratic discourse. But such communication would be superfluous to the contractualist theory of right, since we could just as well model the acquisition of such information in some other way. The fact remains that the decision whether to reject must be reasonably self-serving, and that is sufficient to refute the democracy/contractualism analogy
    • There would be no circularity in a contractor persuading others of a certain subsidiary matter: that the others could not reject certain proposals without thwarting their reasonably self-serving motives. This again suggests similarities with democratic discourse. But such communication would be superfluous to the contractualist theory of right, since we could just as well model the acquisition of such information in some other way. The fact remains that the decision whether to reject must be reasonably self-serving, and that is sufficient to refute the democracy/contractualism analogy.
  • 32
    • 0004333573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • What We Owe, Ibid., pp. 218-23.
    • What We Owe , pp. 218-223
  • 33
    • 0004333573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • What We Owe, Ibid., p. 5.
    • What We Owe , pp. 5
  • 34
    • 78751651935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barry explicitly rejects veto power for individuals or minorities despite noting that this is suggested by his democracy/contractualism analogy
    • Barry explicitly rejects veto power for individuals or minorities despite noting that this is suggested by his democracy/contractualism analogy.
  • 35
    • 78751668641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JAL, p. 107
    • JAL , pp. 107
  • 36
    • 78751652399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 6
    • See Nelson, OJD, ch. 6.
    • OJD
    • Nelson1
  • 37
    • 78751650972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen says that when properly conducted, then democratic politics involves public deliberation focused on the common good
    • Cohen says that "when properly conducted, then democratic politics involves public deliberation focused on the common good" (DDL, p. 19)
    • DDL , pp. 19
  • 38
    • 78751675174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe Barry's idea of an "empirical approximation" of a Scanlonian original position conflates outcome similarity and procedural similarity
    • I believe Barry's idea of an "empirical approximation" of a Scanlonian original position conflates outcome similarity and procedural similarity.
  • 39
    • 78751668199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, where "circumstances of impartiality," are glossed as referring to empirical conditions that approximate those of a Scanlonian original position," but are also defined as "the conditions under which the substantive rules of justice of a society will tend actually to be just
    • See JAI, page 100, where "circumstances of impartiality," are glossed as referring to "empirical conditions that approximate those of a Scanlonian original position," but are also defined as "the conditions under which the substantive rules of justice of a society will tend actually to be just."
    • JAI , pp. 100


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.