메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 106, Issue 1-2, 2001, Pages 1-40

How are objective epistemic reasons possibee?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34247509937     PISSN: 00318116     EISSN: 15730883     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/a:1013141719930     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (82)

References (39)
  • 1
    • 3843082637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Knowledge of Logic
    • P. Boghossian and C. Peacocke (eds.): Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For helpful comments, I would like to thank Christopher Peacocke, Stephen Schiffer, Josh Schechter and the audience at the Pacific APA meetings in Albuquerque, NM in April 2000. I am especially grateful to Crispin Wright for agreeing to comment on that occasion and for numerous stimulating conversations on this and related topics. Some sections of this paper overlap with parts of my "Knowledge of Logic," which appears in P. Boghossian and C. Peacocke (eds.): New Essays on the A Priori (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) New Essays on the a Priori
  • 2
    • 0002667746 scopus 로고
    • The Rule-Following Considerations
    • For discussion, though, see my "The Rule-Following Considerations,' Mind, 1989.
    • (1989) Mind
  • 3
    • 52549126908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle
    • As James van Cleve points out, any epistemic principle has the following form: (EP) If a belief of type B is based on a reason of type R then the belief is justified. On a foundationalist view (and adopting van Cleve's terminology), such principles will include both generation principles and transmission principles. Generation principles specify circumstances under which a belief is justified independently of its logical relations to other beliefs; transmission principles specify under what circumstances the warrant for a given belief transmits to other beliefs. On a coherentist view, epistemic principles will largely consist of some sort of hybrid of these two, assuming the form: If P coheres with the system of propositions accepted by S, then P is justified for S. This is analogous to a generation principle in that its antecedent does not mention any term of epistemic appraisal, but analogous to a transmission principle in that its antecedent specifies relations to other proposition. See can Cleve: "Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle," The Philosophical Review, pp. 55-91. For the sake of concreteness, in this essay I will assume that epistemic principles always take the form characteristic of foundationalism; but the arguments will apply to either type of epistemic system.
    • The Philosophical Review , pp. 55-91
    • Cleve1
  • 4
    • 52549093102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in Boghossian and Peacocke, op. cit
    • For discussion, see my "Knowledge of Eogic" in Boghossian and Peacocke, op. cit.
    • Knowledge of Eogic
  • 5
    • 52549131451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some philosophers distinguish between the activity of giving a justification and the property of being justified. My question involves the latter, more basic, notion: Is it possible for our logical beliefs to have the property of being justified?
  • 6
    • 85045863229 scopus 로고
    • Inductive Evidence
    • "Comments on Salmon's 'Inductive Evidence,' American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (1965), pp. 274-276. It is cited in van Cleve, "Reliability, Justification and Induction," Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science, 1984.
    • (1965) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.2 , pp. 274-276
    • Salmon1
  • 7
    • 0002046135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Eaurence Bonjour, in his In Defense of Pure Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998) attempts to defend a "rational right" view of the a priori.
    • (1998) In Defense of Pure Reason
    • Bonjour, E.1
  • 10
    • 0001451171 scopus 로고
    • Individualism and Self-Knowledge
    • See Tyler Burge: "Individualism and Self-Knowledge," in Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988), 649-663.
    • (1988) Journal of Philosophy , vol.85 , pp. 649-663
    • Burge, T.1
  • 11
    • 52549129531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explaining the a priori
    • Boghossian and Peacocke (eds.)
    • "Explaining the A priori," in Boghossian and Peacocke (eds.), Journal of Philosophy ibid.
    • Journal of Philosophy
  • 12
    • 52549083147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe the term "bad company" to Crispin Wright
    • I owe the term "bad company" to Crispin Wright.
  • 14
    • 52549102112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Due to Marcus Giaquinto
    • Due to Marcus Giaquinto.
  • 15
    • 52549115883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truth by Conventiohn
    • Why not consider instead a relativism or non-factualism about logic itself, rather than about justification? The reason is that these views are well-known to be hopeless. A relativism about logic is just a version of a conventionalism about it, a view decisively defeated in Quine's "Truth by Conventiohn," reprinted in The Ways of Paradox ( ). And as I have argued in "Knowledge of Eogic," those objections carry over straightforwardly to a non-factualist construal of logic.
    • The Ways of Paradox
    • Quine1
  • 16
    • 52549092592 scopus 로고
    • This is simply what I do
    • Oxford: B lackwell, para. 217
    • Some may find this thought expressed in Wittgenstein's remark: "If I have exhausted the justifications I have reached bedrock, and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say: "This is simply what I do." Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: B lackwell, 1953), para. 217.
    • (1953) Philosophical Investigations
  • 17
    • 52549090083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The relativist could also be understood as arguing not that we already speak this way, but that we ought to, if we are to speak cogently.
    • The relativist could also be understood as arguing not that we already speak this way, but that we ought to, if we are to speak cogently.
  • 18
    • 84922404748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • It can be found in Plato's Theaetetus, and in homas Nagel's The Last Word (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) The Last Word
    • Nagel1
  • 21
    • 52549126372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Velleman has emphasized this point to me
    • David Velleman has emphasized this point to me.
  • 24
    • 52549091431 scopus 로고
    • MIND, 1895.
    • (1895) Mind
  • 25
    • 52549118037 scopus 로고
    • Reliability, Justification and Induction
    • James van Cleve also suggests that as the moral of the Eewis Carroll argument; but the argument he outlines is distinct from the one I shall present. See his "Reliability, Justification and Induction," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 1984.
    • (1984) Midwest Studies in Philosophy
  • 26
    • 52549095223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Albuquerque, NM, in April of
    • The objection is from a draft of a commentary on an earlier version of this paper delivered at the Pacific Division meetings of the ARA, Albuquerque, NM, in April of 2000.
    • (2000) Pacific Division Meetings of the ARA
  • 29
    • 84960588748 scopus 로고
    • The Runabout Inference Ticket
    • A. Prior: "The Runabout Inference Ticket," in Analysis 21 (1960-1961), pp. 38-39.
    • (1960) Analysis , vol.21 , pp. 38-39
    • Prior, A.1
  • 30
    • 34248834541 scopus 로고
    • Sense and Justification
    • October
    • Cf. Christopher Peacocke, "Sense and Justification," MIND, October 1992, p. 802.
    • (1992) MIND , pp. 802
    • Peacocke, C.1
  • 31
    • 33748374773 scopus 로고
    • Proof and Truth
    • J. Haldane and C. Wright: Oxford: OUP
    • Christopher Peacocke gives a similar example in "Proof and Truth," in J. Haldane and C. Wright: Reality, Representation and Projection (Oxford: OUP, 1993), pp. 165-190. Peacocke has long urged that a conceptual role semantics be understood in this restrictive thruth-theoretic way. Although my route into these issues is distinct from his, I find myself in agreement with much of Peacocke has to say about the logical constants and the role of meaning in justification.
    • (1993) Reality, Representation and Projection , pp. 165-190
    • Peacocke, C.1
  • 32
    • 52549122662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Analyticity
    • Hale and Wright (eds.): Oxford: Blackwell
    • See my "Analyticity," in Hale and Wright (eds.): A Comparison to the Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).
    • (1997) A Comparison to the Philosophy of Language
  • 33
    • 52549094399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I suspect that it is Wittgenstein's failure to appreciate the point that not every conceptual role determines a meaning that led to the relativistic-sounding passages of the Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics.
  • 35
    • 0042881311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truth by Convention
    • NY: Random House
    • See W. V. O. Quine, "Truth by Convention," reprinted in The Ways of Paradox (NY: Random House, 1996).
    • (1996) The Ways of Paradox
    • Quine, W.V.O.1
  • 36
    • 52549131956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boghossian and Peacocke, op. cit
    • For further discussion, see my "Knowledge of Logic," in Boghossian and Peacocke, op. cit.
    • Knowledge of Logic
  • 38
    • 33746146620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit.
    • In related though distinct contexts, similar points are made both in Alston "Epistemic Circularity," op. cit.,
    • Epistemic Circularity
    • Alston1
  • 39
    • 52549126908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles and the Cartesian Circle
    • January
    • and in James van Cleve "Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles and the Cartesian Circle," Philosophical Review, January 1979.
    • (1979) Philosophical Review
    • Van Cleve, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.