메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 7, Issue 3, 2002, Pages 81-104

The living and the dead: Variations on de anima

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34247457455     PISSN: 0969725X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/0969725022000032490     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (19)

References (68)
  • 1
    • 0037713258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Vincenzo Binetti and Cesare Casarino ,Minnesota: U of Minnesota P
    • Means Without End: Notes on Politics, trans. Vincenzo Binetti and Cesare Casarino (Minnesota: U of Minnesota P, 2000) 7.
    • (2000) Means Without End: Notes on Politics , pp. 7
  • 2
    • 33645526372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Absolute Immanence
    • Stanford: Stanford UP
    • "Absolute Immanence" in Potentialities, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford: Stanford UP, 1999) 232.
    • (1999) Potentialities , pp. 232
    • Heller-Roazen, D.1
  • 6
    • 79956480563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Means Without End
    • Means Without End 3.
  • 7
    • 33947421396 scopus 로고
    • History of Sexuality
    • New York: Random
    • History of Sexuality, Volume I: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Random, 1978) 188.
    • (1978) An Introduction , vol.1 , pp. 188
    • Hurley, R.1
  • 8
    • 77953596536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Il faut défendre la societe
    • Paris: Gallimard/Seuil
    • Agamben proposes a very selective reading of Foucault's work on biopower, one that relies heavily on the last part of the History of Sexuality, Volume 1. This chapter is in no way representative of Foucault's seminar work on biopower. To a large extent, I would suggest, Agamben misinterprets Foucault's interrogation of power, though a full exploration of this matter is beyond the scope of the present article. Something of an insight into his misreading can be gleaned from the first chapter of Homo Sacer, where he conflates Foucault's understanding of "political techniques" in general with the sovereign model of constitutional power. He here claims that Foucault's later work pursued two divergent lines of enquiry-the political, totalizing technologies of the state and the individualizing technologies of the self. Yet Foucault was never able to theorize their convergence, he argues. If Foucault contests the traditional approach to the problem of power, which is exclusively based on juridical models ("What legitimates power?") or on institutional models ("What is the State?"), and if he calls for a "liberation from the theoretical privilege of sovereignty" in order to construct an analytic of power that would not take law as its model and code, then where, in the body of power, is the zone of indistinction (or, at least, the point of intersection) at which techniques of individualization and totalizing procedures converge? (Homo Sacer 5-6) As this passage makes clear, Agamben assumes that "totalizing procedures" must be thought according to the juridical model of sovereign power. In the 1976 seminar, however, Foucault defines his task as the elaboration of a model of power that would be at once totalizing and individualizing, and yet irreducible to the premises of sovereign constitutional right. He here defines biopolitics as a " probabilistic" exercise of power that targets the contingent event in a statistical population ("Il faut défendre la societe": Cours au Collège de France (Paris: Gallimard/Seuil, 1997) 213-35).
    • (1997) Cours Au Collège de France , pp. 213-235
  • 12
    • 79956468326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Joël Gayraud , Paris: Rivages
    • Agamben takes up this question again in his latest book: L'Ouvert: De l'homme et de l'animal, trans. Joël Gayraud (Paris: Rivages, 2002) 26-31.
    • (2002) De l'Homme et de l'Animal , pp. 26-31
    • L'Ouvert1
  • 13
    • 79956480522 scopus 로고
    • trans. John H. McMahon New York: Prometheus, trans. modified
    • The Metaphysics 1041a 11, trans. John H. McMahon (New York: Prometheus, 1991) 163-64; trans. modified.
    • (1991) The Metaphysics 1041a , vol.11 , pp. 163-164
  • 14
    • 79956468348 scopus 로고
    • 2 413b, Harmondsworth: Penguin
    • De anima II. 2 413b, trans. Hugh Lawson-Tancred (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986) 160.
    • (1986) De Anima , vol.2 , pp. 160
    • Lawson-Tancred, H.1
  • 15
    • 79956468328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4 416b
    • On self-preservation, see De anima II. 4 416b, 168.
    • De Anima , vol.2 , pp. 168
  • 16
    • 0009877590 scopus 로고
    • De generatione animalium
    • I. 23 730b-731a
    • "De generatione animalium" I. 23 730b-731a in The Works of Aristotle, trans. Arthur Platt (Oxford: Clarendon, 1910).
    • (1910) The Works of Aristotle
    • Platt, A.1
  • 18
    • 79956489672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 426b7
    • De anima III. 2 426b7, 194.
    • De Anima , vol.3 , pp. 194
  • 19
  • 20
  • 22
    • 79956438693 scopus 로고
    • On Sleep and Waking
    • trans. David Gallop , Canada: Broadview,453b 24
    • "On Sleep and Waking" 453b 24 in Aristotle on Sleep and Dreams, trans. David Gallop (Canada: Broadview, 1990) 57.
    • (1990) Aristotle on Sleep and Dreams , pp. 57
  • 24
    • 79956480530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Sleep and Waking
    • "On Sleep and Waking" 454b 23, 63.
    • , vol.454 B , Issue.23 , pp. 63
  • 29
    • 84909944631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Remnants of Auschwitz 154. Throughout Remnants of Auschwitz, Agamben compares the figure of the Muselmann in the Nazi concentration camps to the "neodead" produced by contemporary life-support technologies. "[I]n the camp," he writes, "the Muselmann- like the body of the overcomatose person and the neomort attached to life-support systems today-not only shows the efficacy of biopower, but also reveals its secret cypher, so to speak its arcanum" (156). In this article, I am developing my reading of Agamben's concept of bare life solely in relation to contemporary biomedical technologies. However, it would be possible to pursue the connection Agamben has established here by looking in more detail at the biomedical experiments carried out in the concentration camps. On this subject, see Homo Sacer 154-59. For Agamben's fullest discussion of the concept of brain death, see Homo Sacer 160-65.
    • Remnants of Auschwitz , pp. 154
  • 31
    • 0003435368 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Seuil
    • The juridical philosopher Jean-Pierre Baud, in a study which looks at the paradoxical legal status of the body parts and fluids produced by contemporary biotechnologies, comes to a similar conclusion to Agamben. He argues that in the absence of an intermediate zone between the person (assumed to be whole and not dead) and the thing, the frozen organ or blood sample can only be considered a res nullius in legal terms. See L'affaire de la main volée: Une histoire juridique du corps (Paris: Seuil, 1993).
    • (1993) L'Affaire de la Main Volée: Une Histoire Juridique du Corps
  • 32
    • 33845431512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Potentiality
    • "On Potentiality" in Potentialities 177.
    • Potentialities , pp. 177
  • 33
    • 79956480521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 169
    • De anima 417a 2-5, 169.
    • De Anima , vol.417 A , pp. 2-5
  • 35
    • 79956468301 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on Bodies, Matter and Potentiality
    • Cambridge: Cambridge UP
    • In an essay on potentiality and bodies in Aristotle's thinking, Cynthia A. Freeland operates a similar revision of Aristotle's thought on potential life in relation to contemporary biomedical technologies. She argues that Aristotle's belief that there are no bodies alive purely potentially stems from contingent facts about his world and its technology, and not from logical or conceptual reasons. That is, I do not doubt that he would regard the eye, cornea, heart, or kidney in a donor bank as purely potential organs. So also would frozen sperm (or, for that matter, eggs) count as potential reproductive residues. In the event of advances permitting the deep-freeze of whole persons we could have ice-boxes full of bodies potentially alive. See "Aristotle on Bodies, Matter and Potentiality" in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, eds. A. Gotthelf and J. G. Lennox (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1987) 406.
    • (1987) Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology , pp. 406
    • Gotthelf, A.1    Lennox, J.G.2
  • 36
    • 0004133046 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P
    • The Coming Community, trans. Michael Hardt (Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1993) 35.
    • (1993) The Coming Community , pp. 35
    • Hardt, M.1
  • 38
    • 84907674998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Physica" II 199b.
    • Physica , vol.2
  • 40
    • 84920423515 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Éditions du Cerf
    • For a detailed discussion of the relation between Marx and Aristotle, and the role of Aristotle's discussion of krematistike in the first book of Capital, see Éric Alliez, Les temps capitaux. Tome 1: Récits de la conquête du temps (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1991) 13-58.
    • (1991) Les Temps Capitaux. Tome 1: Récits de la Conquête du Temps , pp. 13-58
    • Alliez, E.1
  • 43
    • 85036737788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 221a
    • "Physica" IV 220b, 221a.
    • Physica , vol.4
  • 47
    • 79956480500 scopus 로고
    • De generatione et corruptione II. 10 338a-338b
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • Such a movement has a truly peripheral or excessive status in Aristotle's thinking. Of the two understandings of the infinite that Aristotle proposes in De generatione et corruptione, for example, neither corresponds to the kind of movement he encounters in exchange-for-interest. The movement of coming-to-be or genesis, he writes, must be infinite and either circular or rectilinear. The most perfect movement is infinite and circular. Less perfect movement, such as the "coming to be" of human generations, the son from the father, is infinite but rectilinear. In both cases, however, movement is essentially limited or centred-an eternal return of sameness ("De generatione et corruptione" II. 10 338a-338b in The Works of Aristotle: Volume II, trans. H. H Joachim (Oxford: Clarendon, 1962)). At issue, then, in Aristotle's discussion of the two kinds of exchange, is the distinction between the "finite-unlimited" and the "limited-infinite," as Deleuze puts it in Difference and Repetition (Gilles Deleuze, Différence et Répétition (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1969) 80). Whereas Aristotle's whole corpus assumes the priority of infinite but limited movement, the finite-unlimited opens up into a very different current of philosophy. It is significant that the Epicurian philosopher Lucretius, who in many ways takes up the art of krematistike as a general theory of creation, insists on the fact that the universe has no limits and is born of the smallest of movements of "excess"-the clinamen.
    • (1962) The Works of Aristotle: II
    • Joachim, H.H.1
  • 48
    • 79956489627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40-1258a10, 14-15
    • Politics: Books 1 and 2 I. 9 1257b 40-1258a10, 14-15.
    • Politics: Books 1 and 2 , vol.1 , Issue.9
  • 50
    • 79956468308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II. 10 336b
    • Such a generation goes counter to all the fundamental premises of "coming to be" as outlined by Aristotle in De generatione et corruptione. According to this treatise, which carefully distinguishes between coming to be (genesis), growth and alteration, the lives of all living things are measured by a certain period (II. 10 336b). Their growth, understood as an expansion of magnitude, is limited in time. It is this limit to growth that introduces the living thing into the successive time of generation, where the perishing of paternal form gives way to the coming-to-be of the same, in the son. The time of generation is necessarily rectilinear and irreversible-"for though your coming-to-be presupposes your father's, his coming-to-be does not presuppose yours" (II. 10 338b). But in the movement of exchange-forinterest, Aristotle comes up against a substance that never stops growing, oblivious to death and generational time. This substance is homogenerative-father and son to itself, though the son has taken on the generative role with respect to the father.
  • 51
    • 79956489629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 165
    • De anima II. 4 416a, 165.
    • De Anima , vol.2 , Issue.4
  • 52
    • 79956468298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Physica" VIII, 205.
    • Physica , vol.8 , pp. 205
  • 54
    • 0003970747 scopus 로고
    • trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling London: Lawrence & Wishart
    • Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1954) 54.
    • (1954) Capital: A Critique of Political Economy , pp. 54
    • Marx, K.1
  • 55
    • 79956438638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Capital 65-66.
    • Capital , pp. 65-66
  • 56
    • 0002342717 scopus 로고
    • trans. C. J. Arthur London: Lawrence & Wishart
    • See Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology: Part 1, trans. C. J. Arthur (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1970) 49-51.
    • (1970) The German Ideology: Part 1 , pp. 49-51
    • Marx, K.1    Engels, F.2
  • 57
    • 79956468296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Capital 152, 153.
    • Capital , vol.152 , pp. 153
  • 59
    • 0003887051 scopus 로고
    • trans. Harry Cleaver, Michael Ryan and Maurizio Viano South Hadly: Bergin & Garvey
    • This is the reading of Marx that has been developed most forcefully by Italian autonomist thinkers. See Antonio Negri, Marx Beyond Marx: Lessons on the Grundrisse, trans. Harry Cleaver, Michael Ryan and Maurizio Viano (South Hadly: Bergin & Garvey, 1984).
    • (1984) Marx beyond Marx: Lessons on the Grundrisse
    • Negri, A.1
  • 60
    • 79956480492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more recent attempt to develop this reading of Marx in light of Foucault's concept of biopower, see Maurizio Lazzarato's analysis of the contemporary media: "Pour une redéfinition du concept de 'biopolitique,' " Futur Antérieur 39-40. 1: 69-84.
    • Futur Antérieur , vol.39-40 , Issue.1 , pp. 69-84
    • Lazzarato, M.1
  • 61
    • 0032491416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Embryonic Stem Cell Lines Derived from Human Blastocysts
    • 6 Nov
    • See James A. Thomson et al. , "Embryonic Stem Cell Lines Derived from Human Blastocysts," Science 282 (6 Nov. 1998): 1145-47.
    • (1998) Science , vol.282 , pp. 1145-1147
    • Thomson, J.A.1
  • 62
    • 0002831692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Embryonic Stem Cells for Medicine
    • Apr
    • For an overview of these, see Roger A. Pederson, "Embryonic Stem Cells for Medicine," Scientific American (Apr. 1999): 44-49.
    • (1999) Scientific American , pp. 44-49
    • Pederson, R.A.1
  • 63
    • 79956489611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics and Embryonic Cells
    • Apr. , 47
    • "Ethics and Embryonic Cells," Scientific American (Apr. 1999): 47.
    • (1999) Scientific American
  • 64
    • 33748819507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Don't Expect Any Miracles: Special Report on Human Cloning
    • 1 Dec
    • On this point, see A. Coghlan, C. Ainsworth and D. Concar, "Don't Expect Any Miracles: Special Report on Human Cloning," New Scientist (1 Dec. 2001): 4-6.
    • (2001) New Scientist , pp. 4-6
    • Coghlan, A.1    Ainsworth, C.2    Concar, D.3
  • 65
    • 0034990667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Not the Usual Suspects: The Unexpected Sources of Tissue Generation
    • June
    • For further detail on this line of research see M. L. Springer et al. , "Not the Usual Suspects: The Unexpected Sources of Tissue Generation," Journal of Clinical Investigation 11 (June 2001): 1355-56.
    • (2001) Journal of Clinical Investigation , vol.11 , pp. 1355-1356
    • Springer, M.L.1
  • 66
    • 79956438631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virgin Embryos
    • 1 Dec
    • Michael Le Page, "Virgin Embryos," New Scientist (1 Dec. 2001): 6.
    • (2001) New Scientist , pp. 6
    • Page, M.L.1
  • 67
    • 79956468210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Thickness of Tissue Engineering: Biopolitics, Biotech and the Regenerative Body
    • 3. 3
    • On this point, see Eugene Thacker, "The Thickness of Tissue Engineering: Biopolitics, Biotech and the Regenerative Body," Theory and Event 3. 3 (1999): 1-16. Thacker writes that tissue engineering (TE), which is closely linked to stem cell technologies, "is in the process of constituting a unique biomedical normativity which is based on the notion of the body as 'regenerative' and as self-healing In TE the biomedical body only returns to itself in a spiral which simultaneously moves upwards (an infinitely reproducible body) and downwards (an expendable body)" (6). He adds that TE involves an "economy of auto-generation (the generation of tissues from one's own cells) that is circular and proliferative" (4).
    • (1999) Theory and Event , pp. 1-16
    • Thacker, E.1
  • 68
    • 0032151803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Homo Economicus: Commercialization of Body Tissue in the Age of Biotechnology
    • Sept.
    • See Dorothy Nelkin and Lori Andrews, "Homo Economicus: Commercialization of Body Tissue in the Age of Biotechnology," The Hastings Center Report (Sept. 1998): 5-6.
    • (1998) The Hastings Center Report , pp. 5-6
    • Nelkin, D.1    Andrews, L.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.