-
1
-
-
79956600245
-
-
Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy [hereafter, NTP] (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1990), pp. 127, 131
-
Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy [hereafter, NTP] (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1990), pp. 127, 131
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
79956600221
-
-
Brian Leiter, Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals [hereafter, PNGM], in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality [hereafter, NGM], ed. Richard Schacht (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 1994), p. 334. In note 2 on p. 352, Leiter lists alleged adherents to RV, including Kofman, Schrift, Danto, Grimm, Derrida, Magnus, de Man, Nehamas, Strong, Conway, Warnock, Davey
-
Brian Leiter, "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals" [hereafter, "PNGM"], in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality [hereafter, NGM], ed. Richard Schacht (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 1994), p. 334. In note 2 on p. 352, Leiter lists alleged adherents to RV, including Kofman, Schrift, Danto, Grimm, Derrida, Magnus, de Man, Nehamas, Strong, Conway, Warnock, Davey
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
79956659099
-
-
Richard Schacht, Nietzsche [hereafter, N] (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983), pp. 95, 112
-
Richard Schacht, Nietzsche [hereafter, N] (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983), pp. 95, 112
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
79956600243
-
-
Richard Schacht, Making Sense of Nietzsche [hereafter, MSN] (Urbana: Univ. of Illinois Press, 1995)
-
Richard Schacht, Making Sense of Nietzsche [hereafter, MSN] (Urbana: Univ. of Illinois Press, 1995)
-
-
-
-
5
-
-
79956652486
-
128 where Clark claims that
-
is the only statement of Nietzsche's perspectivism in the works I have placed in stage 6 of his history of the 'true world, NTP
-
See NTP 128 where Clark claims that GM III:12 "is the only statement of Nietzsche's perspectivism in the works I have placed in stage 6 of his history of the 'true world' "
-
GM
, vol.3
, pp. 12
-
-
-
6
-
-
79956600215
-
-
NGM in NGM, pp. 334-57, especially page 335 where Leiter endorses Clark's privileging of GM III:12, which falls into what he dubs Stage III works of the mature Nietzsche
-
see also "PNGM" in NGM, pp. 334-57, especially page 335 where Leiter endorses Clark's privileging of GM III:12, which falls into what he dubs "Stage III" works of the "mature Nietzsche."
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
79956659075
-
-
Citations from A, BGE, GM, and TI are from Walter Kaufmann's translations. Citations from D and HH are from the Hollingdale translations; and citations from WP are from the Kaufmann-Hollingdale translation
-
Citations from A, BGE, GM, and TI are from Walter Kaufmann's translations. Citations from D and HH are from the Hollingdale translations; and citations from WP are from the Kaufmann-Hollingdale translation
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
79956637528
-
-
That Nietzsche's parenthetical remark in phase 5 may allude to D is supported both by its epigram from the Rig Veda (there are so many days that have not yet broken) and by the following passages from book 5: 543 (intimating towards perspectivism), 548 (order of rank), 562 (the free spirit), 565 (creation of eyes and ears), and 575 (bird-like distance, also an allusion back to the epigram)
-
That Nietzsche's parenthetical remark in phase 5 may allude to D is supported both by its epigram from the Rig Veda ("there are so many days that have not yet broken") and by the following passages from book 5: 543 (intimating towards perspectivism), 548 (order of rank), 562 (the free spirit), 565 ("creation" of eyes and ears), and 575 (bird-like distance, also an allusion back to the epigram)
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
64949143066
-
-
HH:, where Nietzsche emphasizes the free spirit
-
Cf. EH "Books" HH:1, where Nietzsche emphasizes the free spirit
-
Books
, pp. 1
-
-
EH, C.1
-
10
-
-
79956450865
-
-
E.g., Nietzsche is prepared to give up the subject/object distinction: WP 522 (cf. GS 354)
-
E.g., Nietzsche is prepared to give up the "subject/object" distinction: see WP 522 (cf. GS 354)
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
79956497130
-
-
Nietzsche's critique of the traditional philosopher's faith in opposite values, broached in BGE 2, reiterated in BGE 24, and elaborated in BGE 3, challenges the consciousness/instinctive distinction. Even if one does not place much weight on the Nachlaß, WP 589 lists a series of distinctions that it claims are interpretations, not facts, that are explicitly and implicitly critiqued in the published works: ends/means, cause/effect, subject/object, acting/suffering, thing-in-itself/appearance
-
Nietzsche's critique of the traditional philosopher's faith in opposite values, broached in BGE 2, reiterated in BGE 24, and elaborated in BGE 3, challenges the "consciousness"/"instinctive" distinction. Even if one does not place much weight on the Nachlaß, WP 589 lists a series of distinctions that it claims are interpretations, not facts, that are explicitly and implicitly critiqued in the published works: ends/means, cause/effect, subject/object, acting/suffering, thing-in-itself/appearance
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
64949183239
-
-
Clark (NTP, p. 112) follows Wilcox and relies on HH 9 to claim that Nietzsche does not deny the existence of the true or metaphysical world, but only holds that it has no function to play; but in HH 10 Nietzsche continues by reflecting on how belief in the metaphysical world may become something to be explained psychologically. But Clark's admission that HH 9 supports the claim that the true or metaphysical world has no function to play, and reading HH 9 in conjunction with HH 10, I would claim that these passages more closely fit phase 5's idea [of the 'true world, which has become useless and superfluous, rather than the moment 4's The true world, unattainable? At any rate, unattained. And none of these points supports attributing positivism (in various guises) to HH: Nietzsche in HH does not subscribe to petit faits, to uninterpreted sensory 'givens, to a gra
-
Clark (NTP, p. 112) follows Wilcox and relies on HH 9 to claim that Nietzsche does not deny the existence of the "true" or metaphysical world, but only holds that it "has no function to play"; but in HH 10 Nietzsche continues by reflecting on how belief in the metaphysical world may become something to be explained psychologically. But Clark's admission that HH 9 supports the claim that "the true or metaphysical world has no function to play," and reading HH 9 in conjunction with HH 10, I would claim that these passages more closely fit phase 5's "idea [of the 'true world'] which has become useless and superfluous," rather than the moment 4's "The true world - unattainable? At any rate, unattained." And none of these points supports attributing positivism (in various guises) to HH: Nietzsche in HH does not subscribe to petit faits, to uninterpreted sensory 'givens,' to a grandiose vision of science as the end-all and be-all, or the like
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
64949161918
-
-
NTP, p. 39
-
NTP, p. 39
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
85068755830
-
-
citing Hilary Putnam, Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), p. 1
-
citing Hilary Putnam, Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), p. 1
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
79956442654
-
-
Clark's interpretation has some support from Davidson, but it is later undercut by other remarks by Davidson. In Donald Davidson, A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge [hereafter, CTK], in Reading Rorty [hereafter, RR], ed. Alan Malachowski (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990), p. 122, he writes: truth is correspondence with the way things are. But in Afterthoughts, 1987, in RR, pp. 135-36
-
Clark's interpretation has some support from Davidson, but it is later undercut by other remarks by Davidson. In Donald Davidson, "A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge" [hereafter, "CTK"], in Reading Rorty [hereafter, RR], ed. Alan Malachowski (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990), p. 122, he writes: "truth is correspondence with the way things are." But in "Afterthoughts, 1987," in RR, pp. 135-36
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
79956442706
-
-
Davidson claims that Truth is one of the clearest and most basic we have.... Any further attempt to explain, define, analyse or explicate the concept will be empty or wrong: correspondence theories, coherence theories ... [etc.], all such theories either add nothing to our understanding of truth or have obvious counter-examples. These remarks would also undercut what support Clark can get from Davidson's remark that it is good to be rid of representations, and with them the correspondence theory of truth, for it is thinking that there are representations which engenders thoughts of relativism. Donald Davidson, The Myth of the Subjective, in Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation, ed., Michael Krause (Notre Dame: Notre Dame Univ. Press, 1989), pp. 165-66
-
Davidson claims that "Truth is one of the clearest and most basic we have.... Any further attempt to explain, define, analyse or explicate the concept will be empty or wrong: correspondence theories, coherence theories ... [etc.], all such theories either add nothing to our understanding of truth or have obvious counter-examples." These remarks would also undercut what support Clark can get from Davidson's remark that "it is good to be rid of representations, and with them the correspondence theory of truth, for it is thinking that there are representations which engenders thoughts of relativism." See Donald Davidson, "The Myth of the Subjective," in Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation, ed., Michael Krause (Notre Dame: Notre Dame Univ. Press, 1989), pp. 165-66
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
79956480977
-
-
Later claims by Davidson undercut Clark's construal of him: it is futile either to reject or to accept the idea that the real and the true are 'independent of our beliefs.' The only evident positive sense we can make of this phrase, the only use that derives from the intentions of those who prize it, derives from the idea of correspondence, and that is an idea without content ... though Davidson would hasten to add that this does not require us to reject the platitude that believing something does not in general make it true
-
Later claims by Davidson undercut Clark's construal of him: "it is futile either to reject or to accept the idea that the real and the true are 'independent of our beliefs.' The only evident positive sense we can make of this phrase, the only use that derives from the intentions of those who prize it, derives from the idea of correspondence, and that is an idea without content ..." though Davidson would hasten to add that this does not require us to reject the "platitude" that "believing something does not in general make it true
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
79956490090
-
-
Donald Davidson, The Structure and Content of Truth [hereafter, SCT], The Journal of Philosophy, LXXXVII, No. 6 (June 1990): 279-328, esp. pp. 304-5, 314
-
" See Donald Davidson, "The Structure and Content of Truth" [hereafter, "SCT"], The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. LXXXVII, No. 6 (June 1990): 279-328, esp. pp. 304-5, 314
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
79956475513
-
-
Leiter cites and endorses Davidson's platitude in PNGM, in NGM, p. 349. I would add: accepting Davidson's platitude does not a fortiori commit one to accept any correspondence theory, minimal or otherwise
-
Leiter cites and endorses Davidson's "platitude" in "PNGM," in NGM, p. 349. I would add: accepting Davidson's platitude does not a fortiori commit one to accept any correspondence theory, minimal or otherwise
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
79956475515
-
-
Richard Rorty, Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, 3 [hereafter, TP] (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1998), p. 24
-
See Richard Rorty, Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, Volume 3 [hereafter, TP] (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1998), p. 24
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
79956652466
-
-
Hacking remarks (in discussing Quine, though equally applicable to Davidson) that Good sense (or charity) inclines us to exclude any system of translation that would lead us to infer that the natives assert brief and obvious self-contradictions (p. 152, emphasis added)
-
Hacking remarks (in discussing Quine, though equally applicable to Davidson) that "Good sense (or charity) inclines us to exclude any system of translation that would lead us to infer that the natives assert brief and obvious self-contradictions" (p. 152, emphasis added)
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
79956600224
-
-
One might also raise, against Davidson and Clark, Hacking's objection (pp. 149-50) to principles like those of charity or humanity: There is nothing wrong with the principles of charity and humanity if they are just commonsense rules of thumb that might, like all common sense, sometimes offer bad advice
-
One might also raise, against Davidson and Clark, Hacking's objection (pp. 149-50) to "principles" like those of "charity" or "humanity": "There is nothing wrong with the principles of charity and humanity if they are just commonsense rules of thumb that might, like all common sense, sometimes offer bad advice
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
84994858374
-
-
Michael Forster, On the Very Idea of Denying the Existence of Radically Different Conceptual Schemes, Inquiry 41 June 1998, 155-56, where he points out that Aristotle's interpretation of the pre-Socratics and tragedians illustrate the principle of charity in its necessity of finding, and therefore insisting on identifying, massive agreement between those texts and himself in both concepts and beliefs, And] precisely because he does remain faithful to his theory he gives interpretations of texts in question which are generally bad ones
-
" See also Michael Forster, "On the Very Idea of Denying the Existence of Radically Different Conceptual Schemes," Inquiry 41 (June 1998): 155-56, where he points out that Aristotle's interpretation of the pre-Socratics and tragedians illustrate the "principle of charity" in its "necessity of finding, and therefore insisting on identifying, massive agreement between those texts and himself in both concepts and beliefs ... [And] precisely because he does remain faithful to his theory he gives interpretations of texts in question which are generally bad ones...."
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
79956659057
-
-
rd Ed., ed. A. P. Martinich (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1996), pp. 415-26, esp. pp. 416, 419, 421-25
-
rd Ed., ed. A. P. Martinich (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1996), pp. 415-26, esp. pp. 416, 419, 421-25
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
79956490080
-
-
SCT, note 56, pp. 312-13
-
"SCT," note 56, pp. 312-13
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
79956659073
-
-
Mark Johnson, The Body in the Mind [hereafter, BinM] (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1987), p. 72
-
Cf. Mark Johnson, The Body in the Mind [hereafter, BinM] (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1987), p. 72
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
0003919553
-
-
Rorty's remarks on Davidson's theory of metaphor are correct as to Davidson, a metaphorical utterance as such is like a birdsong, it is a causal stimulus to belief and meaning, but it is not itself meaningful or cognitive. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, note 27, pp 171
-
Rorty's remarks on Davidson's theory of metaphor are correct as to Davidson - a metaphorical utterance as such is like a birdsong, it is a causal stimulus to belief and meaning, but it is not itself meaningful or cognitive. See Richard Rorty, Objectivism, Relativism, and Truth (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1991), p. 169. In note 27, pp. 171-72
-
(1991)
Objectivism, Relativism, and Truth
, pp. 169-172
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
29
-
-
79956490087
-
-
Rorty remarks that Davidson would regard ... Johnson and Lakoff's talk of a 'gestalt' as [one of the] 'dormative power' explanations of 'how metaphors work.' I dissent from Rorty on this issue
-
Rorty remarks that "Davidson would regard ... Johnson and Lakoff's talk of a 'gestalt' as [one of the] 'dormative power' explanations of 'how metaphors work.' " I dissent from Rorty on this issue
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
79956439112
-
-
For Davidson, WMM in PL p. 419: a simile tells us, in part, what a metaphor merely nudges us into noting
-
For Davidson, see "WMM" in PL p. 419: "a simile tells us, in part, what a metaphor merely nudges us into noting"
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
79956439091
-
-
and p. 421: A metaphor directs attention to the same sorts of similarity, if not the same similarities, as the corresponding simile. But contra Davidson George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh [hereafter, PF] (New York: Basic Books, 1999), p. 126
-
and p. 421: "A metaphor directs attention to the same sorts of similarity, if not the same similarities, as the corresponding simile." But contra Davidson see George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh [hereafter, PF] (New York: Basic Books, 1999), p. 126
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
79956468787
-
-
F, p. 124
-
PF, p. 124
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
79956623137
-
-
George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By [hereafter, MWLB] (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1980), pp. 211-18
-
See also George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By [hereafter, MWLB] (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1980), pp. 211-18
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
79956615983
-
-
Sam Wheeler III, True Figures, in The Interpretive Turn [hereafter, IT], ed. David Hiley, James Bohman & Richard Shusterman (Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1991), pp. 195-217, esp. 210-14
-
Sam Wheeler III, "True Figures," in The Interpretive Turn [hereafter, IT], ed. David Hiley, James Bohman & Richard Shusterman (Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1991), pp. 195-217, esp. 210-14
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
79956659030
-
-
BGE
-
See also BGE 24
-
, vol.24
-
-
-
36
-
-
79956631222
-
-
BinM, pp. xxi-xxvi, 190-93
-
See BinM, pp. xxi-xxvi, 190-93
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
79956615976
-
-
186-88, 198-209
-
see also MWLB, pp. 186-88, 198-209
-
-
-
MWLB1
pp2
-
38
-
-
64949113945
-
-
MWLB, pp. 77-96
-
, vol.77-96
-
-
MWLB1
pp2
-
39
-
-
84937317744
-
Literary Theory and its Discontents
-
Summer
-
John Searle, "Literary Theory and its Discontents," in New Literary History, Vol. 25, No. 3 (Summer 1994): 638-39
-
(1994)
New Literary History
, vol.25
, Issue.3
, pp. 638-639
-
-
Searle, J.1
-
40
-
-
79956637511
-
-
Searle cites, on p. 638, Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc. (Evanston: Northwestern Univ. Press, 1988), pp. 123-24, 117, 126
-
Searle cites, on p. 638, Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc. (Evanston: Northwestern Univ. Press, 1988), pp. 123-24, 117, 126
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
64949134567
-
-
BinM, pp. 188
-
BinM, pp. 188
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
79956659060
-
-
BinM, p. 188, citing John Searle, Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1983), p. 149
-
BinM, p. 188, citing John Searle, Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1983), p. 149
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
79956637499
-
-
NGM in PGM, p. 348: Leiter remarks that there is a tension between Wittgenstein's claim that philosophy leaves everything as it is, and his remarks on rule-following [which] seem to alter radically our understanding of meaning, normativity, and objectivity
-
"PNGM" in PGM, p. 348: Leiter remarks that there is a tension between Wittgenstein's claim that philosophy "leaves everything as it is," and "his remarks on rule-following [which] seem to alter radically our understanding of meaning, normativity, and objectivity"
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
79956600171
-
-
Leiter claims that this tension can be resolved by recognizing that the latter can be taken as something like a 'transcendental' condition on notions like meaning.... It is only against a background of such dispositions [to use words in certain way] that it is possible to employ any intelligible idea of a [normative] constraint on meaning
-
Leiter claims that this tension can be resolved by recognizing that the latter can be taken as "something like a 'transcendental' condition on notions like meaning.... It is only against a background of such dispositions [to use words in certain way] that it is possible to employ any intelligible idea of a [normative] constraint on meaning."
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
79956637498
-
-
BinM, p. 188
-
BinM, p. 188
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
64949140226
-
-
on p. 167, Johnson queries: What if, following the consensus of contemporary analytic philosophy, we deny the strict separation of the analytic from the synthetic, the a priori from the a posteriori, and the formal from the material [and, he could have added, of scheme from content]? If we regard these as poles on a continuum, then there is no need to exclude imagination from some supposed pristine realm of 'cognitive content' or 'objective structure.'
-
on p. 167, Johnson queries: "What if, following the consensus of contemporary analytic philosophy, we deny the strict separation of the analytic from the synthetic, the a priori from the a posteriori, and the formal from the material [and, he could have added, of scheme from content]? If we regard these as poles on a continuum, then there is no need to exclude imagination from some supposed pristine realm of 'cognitive content' or 'objective structure.' "
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
79956637494
-
-
True Figures in IT, pp. 204, 210-14
-
See also "True Figures" in IT, pp. 204, 210-14
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
79956652463
-
-
See PF, pp. 26-30
-
, vol.26-30
-
-
PF1
pp2
-
50
-
-
79956659061
-
-
Johnson remarks, in BinM, p. xxxvii, that The method I employ might be called a form of descriptive or empirical phenomenology, in that I will be attempting a kind of 'geography of human experience.' Such a geography seeks to identify the chief contours (structures) and connections that our experience and understanding exhibit. It would explore the emergence of comprehensible form and organization in our experience and the means we have of making sense of it. The test of its success is comprehensiveness, coherence, and explanatory power. The term phenomenography is from Richard Schacht, Hegel and After (Pittsburgh: Univ. of Pittsburgh Press, 1975), p. 227
-
Johnson remarks, in BinM, p. xxxvii, that "The method I employ might be called a form of descriptive or empirical phenomenology, in that I will be attempting a kind of 'geography of human experience.' Such a geography seeks to identify the chief contours (structures) and connections that our experience and understanding exhibit. It would explore the emergence of comprehensible form and organization in our experience and the means we have of making sense of it. The test of its success is comprehensiveness, coherence, and explanatory power." The term "phenomenography" is from Richard Schacht, Hegel and After (Pittsburgh: Univ. of Pittsburgh Press, 1975), p. 227
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
79956600164
-
-
F, pp. 9-15, 74-93. Since in PF Lakoff and Johnson defend and operate with a notion of the cognitive unconscious, their enterprise may be described as a hermeneutic phenomenography
-
See also PF, pp. 9-15, 74-93. Since in PF Lakoff and Johnson defend and operate with a notion of the "cognitive unconscious," their enterprise may be described as a "hermeneutic phenomenography."
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
64949194057
-
-
PF, pp. 72, 128
-
, vol.72
, Issue.128
-
-
PF1
pp2
-
53
-
-
64949179748
-
43: Rorty is citing Hilary Putnam
-
Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 28
-
TP, p. 43: Rorty is citing Hilary Putnam, Realism with a Human Face (Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1990), pp. 20, 28
-
(1990)
Realism with a Human Face
, pp. 20
-
-
TP, P.1
-
54
-
-
79956650934
-
-
Giovanna Borradori, The American Philosopher (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1994), p. 16: Neither language nor the mind organizes perceptible reality according to fixed conceptual schemes, since they and the world are all part of an intersubjective conceptual matrix.... The entire universe, subjective and objective, is trapped in a hermeneutic mesh of signs. Reality itself is nothing other than a coagulation of language and interpretation
-
Cf. Giovanna Borradori, The American Philosopher (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1994), p. 16: "Neither language nor the mind organizes perceptible reality according to fixed conceptual schemes, since they and the world are all part of an intersubjective conceptual matrix.... The entire universe, subjective and objective, is trapped in a hermeneutic mesh of signs. Reality itself is nothing other than a coagulation of language and interpretation."
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
79956652441
-
-
Though the Davidsonian triangulation of subject, intersubjectivity, and world takes intersubjectivity to be the basis of knowledge, and while such assignment of priority would be justifiable as a methodological assumption of a (e.g, Davidson's) specific research program, it is not justifiable tout court, especially epistemologically or ontologically. For, as Rorty points out A large body of Davidsonian doctrine suggests that it is hopeless to assign one apex of this triangle priority over the other two, in respect to basicness or standard-setting. Richard Rorty, Davidson's Mental-Physical Distinction, in The Philosophy of Donald Davidson [hereafter, PDD, The Library of Living Philosophers XXVII Chicago & La Salle: Open Court Publishing Company, 1999, p. 587
-
Though the Davidsonian triangulation of subject, intersubjectivity, and world takes intersubjectivity to be the basis of knowledge, and while such assignment of priority would be justifiable as a methodological assumption of a (e.g., Davidson's) specific research program, it is not justifiable tout court, especially epistemologically or ontologically. For, as Rorty points out "A large body of Davidsonian doctrine suggests that it is hopeless to assign one apex of this triangle priority over the other two, in respect to basicness or standard-setting." See Richard Rorty, "Davidson's Mental-Physical Distinction," in The Philosophy of Donald Davidson [hereafter, PDD], The Library of Living Philosophers Vol. XXVII (Chicago & La Salle: Open Court Publishing Company, 1999), p. 587
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
79956719505
-
-
Afterthoughts, 1987, in RR, p. 135-36
-
"Afterthoughts, 1987," in RR, p. 135-36
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
79956637483
-
-
Here I apply, but also part company, from Lakoff and Johnson, who, though remarking on the metaphoricity of many abstract philosophical concepts, appear to assume that correspondence is entirely literal. MWLB pp. 179-84
-
Here I apply, but also part company, from Lakoff and Johnson, who, though remarking on the metaphoricity of many abstract philosophical concepts, appear to assume that "correspondence" is entirely literal. See MWLB pp. 179-84
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
79956615994
-
-
See PF, pp. 72-73
-
, vol.72-73
-
-
PF1
pp2
-
59
-
-
79956659040
-
-
Clark's Nietzsche cannot allow for the possibility that an epistemically privileged perspective could be false to any extent. But Clark's position does not follow even from Davidson's principle of charity, if charity begins or at least applies at home, and if charity requires attributing mostly true beliefs, then a charitable interpretation of one's own beliefs could involve at least tacitly acknowledging that at least some of one's own beliefs are false. Davidson, CTK, in RR, p. 133: The agent has only to reflect on what a belief is to appreciate that most of his basic beliefs are true, And if Clark would not allow for this possibility e.g, by treating one's perspective as a conjoined set of beliefs, then her position is open to the so-called preface paradox, which, in a nutshell, would maintain, on the basis of past experience, that it is not unreasonable to believe that at least some of one's current beliefs not only may
-
Clark's Nietzsche cannot allow for the possibility that an epistemically privileged perspective could be false to any extent. But Clark's position does not follow even from Davidson's principle of charity - if charity begins or at least applies at home, and if charity requires attributing mostly true beliefs, then a charitable interpretation of one's own beliefs could involve at least tacitly acknowledging that at least some of one's own beliefs are false. See Davidson, "CTK," in RR, p. 133: "The agent has only to reflect on what a belief is to appreciate that most of his basic beliefs are true...." And if Clark would not allow for this possibility (e.g., by treating one's perspective as a conjoined set of beliefs), then her position is open to the so-called preface paradox, which, in a nutshell, would maintain, on the basis of past experience, that it is not unreasonable to believe that at least some of one's current beliefs not only may be, but are or at least are likely false
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
79956652465
-
-
John Dancy & Ernest Sosa Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
-
See Earl Conee, "Preface Paradox" (and the articles in his bibliography) in A Companion to Epistemology, ed. John Dancy & Ernest Sosa (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1993), pp. 357-59
-
(1993)
Preface Paradox
, pp. 357-359
-
-
Conee, E.1
-
61
-
-
79956650932
-
-
See NTP, p. 65
-
, vol.65
-
-
NTP, P.1
-
62
-
-
79956439210
-
-
citing TL. As if echoing Lakoff and Johnson, Schacht remarks that A natural language, consisting of the 'flexible army of metaphors, metonymies, anthropomorphisms,' that has become 'fixed, canonical and binding' for a linguistic community, fleshes out the syntactic and logical-categorial skeleton which structures our experience, articulating the world as we apprehend it (N, p. 75; emphasis added)
-
citing TL. As if echoing Lakoff and Johnson, Schacht remarks that "A natural language, consisting of the 'flexible army of metaphors, metonymies, anthropomorphisms,' that has become 'fixed, canonical and binding' for a linguistic community, fleshes out the syntactic and logical-categorial skeleton which structures our experience, articulating the world as we apprehend it" (N, p. 75; emphasis added)
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
79956468866
-
-
WP 552: 'Truth' is therefore not something there, that might be found or discovered - but something that must be created and that gives a name to a process, or rather the will to overcome that has in itself no end - introducing truth, as a process in infinitum, an active determining - not a becoming-conscious of something that is in itself firm and determined. It is a word for the 'will to power.' My use of en procès follows that of Julia Kristeva, The Subject in Process [le sujet en procès], trans. Patrick ffrench, in The Tel Quel Reader, ed. Patrick ffrench & Roland- François Lack (London: Routledge, 1998)
-
See WP 552: "'Truth' is therefore not something there, that might be found or discovered - but something that must be created and that gives a name to a process, or rather the will to overcome that has in itself no end - introducing truth, as a process in infinitum, an active determining - not a becoming-conscious of something that is in itself firm and determined. It is a word for the 'will to power.'" My use of "en procès" follows that of Julia Kristeva, "The Subject in Process" [le sujet en procès], trans. Patrick ffrench, in The Tel Quel Reader, ed. Patrick ffrench & Roland-François Lack (London: Routledge, 1998)
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
79956481054
-
-
Schacht, in N, cites WP 560, 556, 555 on p. 100
-
Schacht, in N, cites WP 560, 556, 555 on p. 100
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
79956627125
-
-
his main citations invoking justice are WP 259 on p. 102 & GS 333 on p. 103
-
his main citations invoking justice are WP 259 on p. 102 & GS 333 on p. 103
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
79956465863
-
-
he goes on to discuss GM III:12, GS 373, 374
-
he goes on to discuss GM III:12, GS 373, 374
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
79956491122
-
-
and BGE 22, 23 on pp. 104-6
-
and BGE 22, 23 on pp. 104-6
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
79956650876
-
-
in MSN Schacht cites HH P6
-
in MSN Schacht cites HH P6
-
-
-
-
69
-
-
79956631209
-
-
Kofman, like Schacht, ascribes knowledge as justice in interpretation to Nietzsche, and in her main discussion she offers few pertinent citations: BGE 22, GS 301, 374 in Nietzsche and Metaphor, trans. Duncan Large (London: Althone Press, 1993), pp. 140-43
-
Kofman, like Schacht, ascribes knowledge as justice in interpretation to Nietzsche, and in her main discussion she offers few pertinent citations: BGE 22, GS 301, 374 in Nietzsche and Metaphor, trans. Duncan Large (London: Althone Press, 1993), pp. 140-43
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
79956615925
-
-
earlier, on p. 111 she cites HH 107, which does include the phrase the sense for truth and justice in knowledge
-
earlier, on p. 111 she cites HH 107, which does include the phrase "the sense for truth and justice in knowledge."
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
0003939914
-
-
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Comany
-
See Nelson Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Comany, 1978), p. 18
-
(1978)
Ways of Worldmaking
, pp. 18
-
-
Goodman, N.1
-
72
-
-
79956623117
-
-
Catherine Z. Elgin, Considered Judgment [hereafter, CJ], (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1996), p. 123: 'Objects in a vacuum fall toward the Earth at a rate of 32 ft/sec' is not strictly true since it neglects the gravitational attraction of everything except the Earth
-
See also Catherine Z. Elgin, Considered Judgment [hereafter, CJ], (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1996), p. 123: '"Objects in a vacuum fall toward the Earth at a rate of 32 ft/sec' is not strictly true since it neglects the gravitational attraction of everything except the Earth."
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
79956650896
-
-
NGM in NGM, p. 351: Leiter is citing, and endorsing, (see note 39, p. 357)
-
"PNGM" in NGM, p. 351: Leiter is citing, and endorsing, (see note 39, p. 357)
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
79956623125
-
-
Wittgenstein, as Leiter (not atypically) interprets him, leaves matters ambiguous whether the transcendental conditions on meaning truth and knowledge are non-cognitive common dispositions or normative or both, and this would also apply, by analogy, to Leiter's Nietzsche. PNGM in PGM, pp. 348-50, esp. p. 348. Contrast True Figures in IT, p. 199
-
Wittgenstein, as Leiter (not atypically) interprets him, leaves matters ambiguous whether the "transcendental conditions" on meaning truth and knowledge are non-cognitive common dispositions or normative or both, and this would also apply, by analogy, to Leiter's Nietzsche. See "PNGM" in PGM, pp. 348-50, esp. p. 348. Contrast "True Figures" in IT, p. 199
-
-
-
-
77
-
-
79956615932
-
-
John McDowell, Scheme-Content Dualism and Empricism, in PDD, pp. 87-88
-
See John McDowell, "Scheme-Content Dualism and Empricism," in PDD, pp. 87-88
-
-
-
-
78
-
-
79956615963
-
-
McDowell cites Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1929), A51/B75. note 24
-
McDowell cites Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1929), A51/B75. See also note 24
-
-
-
-
79
-
-
79956650912
-
-
N, p. 62
-
N, p. 62
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
64949097829
-
-
NTP, pp. 128, 135
-
, vol.128
, Issue.135
-
-
NTP1
pp2
-
81
-
-
79956615955
-
-
NGM in NGM, p. 351
-
"PNGM" in NGM, p. 351
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
79956631191
-
-
Nancy Fraser, Solidarity or Singularity?, in RR, pp. 302-11 for a helpful survey and critique of Rorty's views as they developed on this issue
-
See Nancy Fraser, "Solidarity or Singularity?," in RR, pp. 302-11 for a helpful survey and critique of Rorty's views as they developed on this issue
-
-
-
-
83
-
-
79956650926
-
-
e.g., GS 333. The current conceptions of reflective equilibrium in analytical philosophy originate with Goodman in some remarks on logic, and then get highly developed by Rawls, Daniels and Dworkin in ethical and legal theory, and then by Elgin in her constructionalist reconception of epistemology. For Goodman, Fact, Fiction and Forecast (Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1955), pp. 65-68
-
See, e.g., GS 333. The current conceptions of reflective equilibrium in analytical philosophy originate with Goodman in some remarks on logic, and then get highly developed by Rawls, Daniels and Dworkin in ethical and legal theory, and then by Elgin in her "constructionalist" reconception of epistemology. For Goodman, see Fact, Fiction and Forecast (Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1955), pp. 65-68
-
-
-
-
84
-
-
79956650927
-
-
for Rorty, Objectivism, Relativism, and Truth, p. 137, also pp. 66-67, 98-103
-
for Rorty, see Objectivism, Relativism, and Truth, p. 137, cf. also pp. 66-67, 98-103
-
-
-
-
85
-
-
64949175947
-
Ravvl's, see Norman Daniels
-
for both, own views and, Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
-
for both Daniels' own views and Ravvl's, see Norman Daniels, Justice and Justification (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1996)
-
(1996)
Justice and Justification
-
-
Daniels1
-
86
-
-
79956513189
-
-
for Dworkin's views (in contrast to Rawls's), Taking Rights Seriously, esp. Chapter 6
-
for Dworkin's views (in contrast to Rawls's), see Taking Rights Seriously, esp. Chapter 6
-
-
-
-
87
-
-
79956513210
-
-
for Elgin, CJ, 101-45
-
for Elgin, see CJ, 101-45
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
79956691777
-
-
By offering equilibrium in place of Zusammenklang, I am not simply abandoning the latter notion, for equilibrium theorists in a variety of fields often invoke the notions of accord, consonance, and harmony (all of which are standard translations of Zusammenklang): e.g., Gunnar Myrdal, An American Dilemma: The Negro Problem and Modern Democracy (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), APPENDIX 2, Section 3, Note on Facts and Valuations, p. 1055, where he discusses harmony and equilibirum
-
By offering "equilibrium" in place of "Zusammenklang, " I am not simply abandoning the latter notion, for equilibrium theorists in a variety of fields often invoke the notions of "accord," "consonance," and "harmony" (all of which are standard translations of Zusammenklang): see, e.g., Gunnar Myrdal, An American Dilemma: The Negro Problem and Modern Democracy (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), APPENDIX 2, Section 3, "Note on Facts and Valuations," p. 1055, where he discusses "harmony" and "equilibirum."
-
-
-
-
89
-
-
79956613526
-
-
Elgin in CJ writes the following (my emphasis added): Clearly such [additional] judgments should be consonant with the ones we already hold. But what makes for consonance? (p. 103)
-
Elgin in CJ writes the following (my emphasis added): "Clearly such [additional] judgments should be consonant with the ones we already hold. But what makes for consonance?" (p. 103)
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
79956691795
-
-
we might compromise, modifying a variety of commitments to bring them into accord (p. 132)
-
"we might compromise, modifying a variety of commitments to bring them into accord" (p. 132)
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
79956623107
-
-
Revisions reverberate (p. 132)
-
"Revisions reverberate" (p. 132)
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
79956615938
-
-
Moreover, Stich, in effect, challenges the very notion of reflective equilibrium as being an uncashable and useless metaphor
-
Moreover, Stich, in effect, challenges the very notion of "reflective equilibrium" as being an "uncashable and useless metaphor"
-
-
-
-
94
-
-
64949111367
-
-
While I think Stich's challenge can be met, I also take his challenge to evince that the philosophical employment of the notion of equilibrium is an employment of a conceptual metaphor, equilibrium operates as a rigorous exact mathematical model in thermodynamics, in chemistry, and in biology, but it is not at all clear it so operates in the analytical philosophical notion of reflective equilibrium or in my adjudicative equilibrium. That, however, does not make it uncashable and useless: its usefulness and cashability must be proven out in whether it enhances our knowledge or understanding, and whether it allows more justice in adjudication to be done
-
While I think Stich's challenge can be met, I also take his challenge to evince that the philosophical employment of the notion of equilibrium is an employment of a conceptual metaphor - "equilibrium" operates as a rigorous exact mathematical model in thermodynamics, in chemistry, and in biology, but it is not at all clear it so operates in the analytical philosophical notion of "reflective equilibrium" or in my "adjudicative equilibrium." That, however, does not make it "uncashable and useless": its usefulness and "cashability" must be proven out in whether it enhances our knowledge or understanding, and whether it allows more justice in adjudication to be done
-
-
-
|