-
2
-
-
85038774092
-
Sex and Death
-
Chicago: University Press
-
Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology (Chicago: University Press, 1999), p. 196
-
(1999)
An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology
, pp. 196
-
-
-
3
-
-
0002124490
-
Cladistic Theory
-
Peter L. Forey, Christopher J. Humphries, Ian J. Kitching, Robert W. Scotland, Darrell J. Siebert, and David M. Williams, eds. (New York: Oxford), at p. 3.
-
I quote from Robert W. Scotland, "Cladistic Theory," in Peter L. Forey, Christopher J. Humphries, Ian J. Kitching, Robert W. Scotland, Darrell J. Siebert, and David M. Williams, eds., Cladistics: A Practical Course in Systematics (New York: Oxford, 1992), pp. 3-13, at p. 3
-
(1992)
Cladistics: A Practical Course in Systematics
, pp. 3-13
-
-
Scotland, R.W.1
-
4
-
-
79958397686
-
-
Ridley, ed., Evolution (New York: Oxford)
-
Ridley, "Can Classification Do Without Evolution?," in Ridley, ed., Evolution (New York: Oxford, 1997), pp. 196-206; this citation is from p. 202
-
(1997)
Can Classification Do Without Evolution?
, pp. 196-206
-
-
Ridley1
-
5
-
-
79958393813
-
Ridley is always reminding his many readers, is widely accepted: Evolution and Classification
-
(New York: Longman)
-
That cladism "allows only one classification: the classification defined by the hierarchy of phylogenetic branching," as Ridley is always reminding his many readers, is widely accepted: Evolution and Classification: The Reformation of Cladism (New York: Longman, 1986), p. 46
-
(1986)
The Reformation of Cladism
, pp. 46
-
-
-
6
-
-
0001685234
-
Cladistic Classification and Functional Explanation
-
at p, 207
-
See Griffiths, "Cladistic Classification and Functional Explanation," Philosophy of Science, LXI (1994): 206-27, at p. 207
-
(1994)
Philosophy of Science
, vol.61
, pp. 206-227
-
-
Griffiths1
-
7
-
-
0042092606
-
The Role of Theories in Biological Systematics, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part C:
-
at p. 224
-
David Hull, "The Role of Theories in Biological Systematics," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, XXXII (2001): 221-38, at p. 224
-
(2001)
Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences
, vol.32
, pp. 221-238
-
-
Hull, D.1
-
8
-
-
0003149624
-
The Limits of Cladism
-
at pp. 437-38
-
"The Limits of Cladism," Systematic Zoology, XXVIII (1979): 416-40, at pp. 437-38
-
(1979)
Systematic Zoology
, vol.28
, pp. 416-440
-
-
-
10
-
-
0024873017
-
The Cladistic Solution to the Species Problem
-
"The Cladistic Solution to the Species Problem," Biology and Philosophy, IV (1989): 1-16
-
(1989)
Biology and Philosophy
, vol.4
, pp. 1-16
-
-
-
12
-
-
67651149188
-
Cladism or Gradism?: A Reply to Ernst Mayr
-
at pp, 447-448
-
Donn Eric Rosen, "Cladism or Gradism?: A Reply to Ernst Mayr," Systematic Zoology, XXIII (1974): 446-51, at pp. 447-48
-
(1974)
Systematic Zoology
, vol.23
, pp. 446-451
-
-
Eric Rosen, D.1
-
13
-
-
14844332774
-
-
Lanham, MD: Lexington
-
David N. Stamos, The Species Problem: Biological Species, Ontology, and the Metaphysics of Biology (Lanham, MD: Lexington, 2003), p. 265
-
(2003)
The Species Problem: Biological Species, Ontology, and the Metaphysics of Biology
, pp. 265
-
-
Stamos, D.N.1
-
15
-
-
0014853540
-
Rainbow's End: The Quest for an Optimal Taxonomy
-
at p. 231
-
Foreshadows of the problems that I raise may be found, in some measure or other, in L.A.S. Johnson, "Rainbow's End: The Quest for an Optimal Taxonomy," Systematic Zoology, XIX (1970): 203-39, at p. 231
-
(1970)
Systematic Zoology
, vol.19
, pp. 203-239
-
-
Johnson, L.A.S.1
-
16
-
-
12044255162
-
Systematic Generalization, Historical Fate, and the Species Problem
-
at pp, 232-233
-
Robert O'Hara, "Systematic Generalization, Historical Fate, and the Species Problem," Systematic Biology, XLII (1993): 231-16, at pp. 232-33
-
(1993)
Systematic Biology
, vol.42
, pp. 231-316
-
-
O'Hara, R.1
-
17
-
-
0038214625
-
The Nature of Species
-
at p, 17
-
and Sterelny, "The Nature of Species," Philosophical Books, XXXV (1994): pp. 9-20 at p. 17
-
(1994)
Philosophical Books
, vol.35
, pp. 9-20
-
-
Sterelny1
-
18
-
-
0004275113
-
-
who appears since to have had a change of heart (cf. Griffiths and Sterelny, Sex and Death, pp. 194-97): in section v, I indicate that there is something importantly right in each position
-
Sex and Death
, pp. 194-197
-
-
Griffiths1
Sterelny2
-
19
-
-
0002425667
-
The Biological Species Concept
-
Quentin D. Wheeler and Rudolf Meier, eds. (New York: Columbia), cited at p. 17.
-
Mayr, "The Biological Species Concept," in Quentin D. Wheeler and Rudolf Meier, eds., Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory (New York: Columbia, 2000), pp. 17-29, cited at p. 17
-
(2000)
Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory
, pp. 17-29
-
-
Mayr1
-
20
-
-
0004110029
-
-
Cambridge: Harvard
-
This is a typical statement of the biological species concept. It is repeated word for word in several places: Evolution and the Diversity of Life: Selected Essays (Cambridge: Harvard, 1976), p. 518
-
(1976)
Evolution and the Diversity of Life: Selected Essays
, pp. 518
-
-
-
23
-
-
0036095630
-
Ernst Mayr through Time on the Biological Species Concept: A Conceptual Analysis
-
Still
-
Still, the biological species concept has undergone change over Mayr's many active decades: see Peter Beurton, "Ernst Mayr through Time on the Biological Species Concept: A Conceptual Analysis," Theory in Biosciences, CXXI (2002): 81-98
-
(2002)
Theory in Biosciences
, vol.121
, pp. 81-98
-
-
Beurton, P.1
-
24
-
-
33847096583
-
Comments by Ernst Mayr
-
and Mayr, "Comments by Ernst Mayr," Theory in Biosciences, CXXI (2002): 99-100
-
(2002)
Theory in Biosciences
, vol.121
, pp. 99-100
-
-
Mayr1
-
25
-
-
0020869892
-
Species Concepts and Speciation Analysis
-
R.F. Johnston, ed. (New York: Plenum), cited at p. 170.
-
Cracraft, "Species Concepts and Speciation Analysis," in R.F. Johnston, ed., Current Ornithology (New York: Plenum, 1983), pp. 159-87, cited at p. 170
-
(1983)
Current Ornithology
, pp. 159-187
-
-
Cracraft1
-
26
-
-
0002815874
-
Species Concepts in Systematics and Conservation Biology: An Ornithological Viewpoint
-
M. Claridge, H. Dawah, and M. R. Wilson, eds, New York: Chapman and Hall, 331
-
Cracraft, "Species Concepts in Systematics and Conservation Biology: An Ornithological Viewpoint," in M. Claridge, H. Dawah, and M. R. Wilson, eds., Species: The Units of Biodiversity (New York: Chapman and Hall, 1997), pp. 325-39, p. 331
-
(1997)
Species: The Units of Biodiversity
, pp. 325-339
-
-
Cracraft1
-
27
-
-
0029926109
-
Birds in Double Trouble
-
Graham Martin, "Birds in Double Trouble," Nature, CCCLXXX (1996): 666-67
-
(1996)
Nature
, vol.380
, pp. 666-667
-
-
Martin, G.1
-
30
-
-
1642563044
-
-
Wheeler and Meier, p. 164
-
This sort of budding from a parental species that survives without much change is probably common: most speciation events probably start with small, isolated founder populations: Mayr, "A Defense of the Biological Species Concept," in Wheeler and Meier, eds., pp. 161-66, p. 164
-
A Defense of the Biological Species Concept
, pp. 161-166
-
-
Mayr1
-
33
-
-
85038771552
-
The Cladistic Solution
-
5-6, 8
-
Ridley, "The Cladistic Solution," pp. 3, 5-6, 8
-
-
-
Ridley1
-
34
-
-
0002943910
-
-
Wheeler and Meier, eds, at p. 86;
-
Objection: the issue has been misconceived. The real issue is not whether Cracraft is wrong to name his narrower groups. One can apply names as one fancies. The real issue is whether Cracraft's use of 'species' breaks from traditional use. If there is a break from traditional use, then Cracraft errs in supposing that he is talking about species; he is talking about some other kind of group to which he has applied the name. Reply: traditional use does not settle in favor of any rival of the phylogenetic species concept. The tradition has long been shared by "lumpers" and "splitters." Both persuasions are reasonable. Over generations, workers of different persuasions have treated the same lineages differently: for examples, see Wiley and Richard L. Mayden, "The Evolutionary Species Concept," in Wheeler and Meier, eds., pp. 70-89, at p. 86
-
The Evolutionary Species Concept
, pp. 70-89
-
-
Wiley1
Mayden, R.L.2
-
36
-
-
79958378571
-
-
Including an Autobiographical Chapter, 2, ed. (London: John Murray)
-
The tradition has also long been characterized by different measures to delimit species, including patterns of resemblance, as Darwin indicates in a famous passage: It is really laughable to see what different ideas are prominent in various naturalists' minds, when they speak of "species"; in some, resemblance is everything and descent of little weight - in some, resemblance seems to go for nothing, and Creation the reigning idea - in some, sterility an unfailing test, with others it is not worth a farthing. It all comes, I believe, from trying to define the indefinable (The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, Including an Autobiographical Chapter, Volume 2, F. Darwin, ed. (London: John Murray, 1887), p.88)
-
(1887)
The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin
, pp. 88
-
-
Darwin, F.1
-
37
-
-
0027338764
-
Permanent Splits as Speciation Events: A Formal Reconstruction of the Internodal Species Concept
-
Even the tradition of cladism fails to settle upon a single species concept. Hennig dodges the issue: see section VI. Hennig's most stalwart followers fail to agree on a single concept: cf. D. J. Kornet, "Permanent Splits as Speciation Events: A Formal Reconstruction of the Internodal Species Concept," Journal of Theoretical Biology, CLXIV (1993): 407-35
-
(1993)
Journal of Theoretical Biology
, vol.164
, pp. 407-435
-
-
Kornet, D.J.1
-
41
-
-
0002983450
-
The Meaning of Species and Speciation: A Genetic Perspective
-
Marc Ereshefsky, ed, Cambridge: MIT, 174
-
Alan Templeton, "The Meaning of Species and Speciation: A Genetic Perspective," in Marc Ereshefsky, ed., The Units of Evolution (Cambridge: MIT, 1992), pp. 159-83, p. 174
-
(1992)
The Units of Evolution
, pp. 159-183
-
-
Templeton, A.1
-
42
-
-
2342580020
-
Ecological Species, Multispecies, and Oaks
-
72-73
-
L. Van Valen, "Ecological Species, Multispecies, and Oaks," in Ereshefsky, pp. 69-77, pp. 72-73
-
Ereshefsky
, pp. 69-77
-
-
Van Valen, L.1
-
43
-
-
0036498251
-
When Is a Parasite Species a Species?
-
Werner Kunz, "When Is a Parasite Species a Species?," Trends in Parasitology, XVIII (2002): 121-24
-
(2002)
Trends in Parasitology
, vol.18
, pp. 121-124
-
-
Kunz, W.1
-
45
-
-
0025673531
-
The Driving Force: Species Concepts and Ecology
-
L. Andersson, "The Driving Force: Species Concepts and Ecology," Taxon, XXXIX (1990): 375-82
-
(1990)
Taxon
, vol.39
, pp. 375-382
-
-
Andersson, L.1
-
46
-
-
0141941120
-
Understanding and Confronting Species Uncertainty in Biology and Conservation
-
599
-
Jody Hey, Robin S. Waples, Michael L. Arnold, Roger K. Butlin, and Richard G. Harrison, "Understanding and Confronting Species Uncertainty in Biology and Conservation," Trends in Ecology and Evolution, XVIII (2003): 597-603, p. 599
-
(2003)
Trends in Ecology and Evolution
, vol.18
, pp. 597-603
-
-
Hey, J.1
Waples, R.S.2
Arnold, M.L.3
Butlin, R.K.4
Harrison, R.G.5
-
48
-
-
0006689406
-
The Evolution of Citrus Species: Methods to Develop New Sweet Orange Cultivars
-
1-3
-
A limited amount of hybridization is common among recognized species of both plants and animals: for discussion of examples, see C. J. Hearn, "The Evolution of Citrus Species: Methods to Develop New Sweet Orange Cultivars," Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Florida State Horticultural Society, CVII (1994): 1-3, p. 2
-
(1994)
Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Florida State Horticultural Society
, vol.107
, pp. 2
-
-
Hearn, C.J.1
-
49
-
-
0037141198
-
Defining the Sources of Paradox: DNA Sequence Markers for North American Walnut (Juglans L.) Species and Hybrids
-
Daniel Potter, Fangyou Gao, Scott Baggett, James R. McKenna, and Gale H. McGranahan, "Defining the Sources of Paradox: DNA Sequence Markers for North American Walnut (Juglans L.) Species and Hybrids," Scientia Horticulturae, XCIV (2002): 157-70
-
(2002)
Scientia Horticulturae
, vol.94
, pp. 157-170
-
-
Potter, D.1
Gao, F.2
Baggett, S.3
McKenna, J.R.4
McGranahan, G.H.5
-
51
-
-
79958415969
-
-
R.C. Stauffer, ed. (New York: Cambridge)
-
The problem of drawing a line at some point has long been recognized: "the infertility of species when crossed graduates away so insensibly that the two most experienced observers who ever lived have come to diametrically opposite results when experimentising on the same forms," Darwin writes (Charles Darwin's Natural Selection: Being the Second Part of His Big Species Book Written From 1856 to 1858), R.C. Stauffer, ed. (New York: Cambridge, 1975), p. 165)
-
(1975)
Natural Selection: Being the Second Part of His Big Species Book Written from 1856 to 1858
, pp. 165
-
-
Darwin, C.1
-
56
-
-
84890987894
-
Species Concepts: A Case for Pluralism
-
495
-
B. Mishler and M. Donoghue, "Species Concepts: A Case for Pluralism," Systematic Zoology, xxxi (1982): 491-503, p. 495
-
(1982)
Systematic Zoology
, vol.31
, pp. 491-503
-
-
Mishler, B.1
Donoghue, M.2
-
58
-
-
85038656583
-
-
Cf. Meier and Willmann, "A Defense." This suggestion raises the possibility that the term 'species' be given by stipulation a new use that would make tree construction a repeatable enterprise. Occasions of discord could be reduced in this way: even stipulating the biological species concept over the phylogenetic species concept is an improvement. But there is little value in going to drastic measures in this direction to describe a kind of group that, however quirky or biologically meaningless, allows for repeatable ordering. Nor would any algorithm generating an ordering of quirky groups show that there is a repeatable account of the hierarchy of species; at best, such an algorithm would show that there is a repeatable account of the hierarchy of some new kind of group deserving a new name. Observe that just as 'species' might be given an artificial, stipulated use that approximates to some extent ordinary use in order to allow for repeatable groupings, so might 'similarity': tellingly, cladists find this trick for achieving repeatability to be arbitrary and to preclude the kind of objectivity in ordering that cladism is supposed to enjoy (Ridley, "Can Classification Do Without Evolution?," p. 199)
-
Can Classification Do Without Evolution?
, pp. 199
-
-
Ridley1
-
60
-
-
0011312557
-
Some Puzzles about Species
-
Michael Ruse, ed, Boston: Kluwer, 197-198
-
Philip Kitcher, "Some Puzzles about Species," in Michael Ruse, ed., What the Philosophy of Biology Is: Essays Dedicated to David Hull (Boston: Kluwer, 1989), pp. 183-208, pp. 197-98
-
(1989)
What the Philosophy of Biology Is: Essays Dedicated to David Hull
, pp. 183-208
-
-
Kitcher, P.1
-
64
-
-
19644400576
-
Little Lady of Flores Forces Rethink of Human Evolution
-
Homo neanderthalensis is typically thought to be around 400,000 years old and Homo sapiens around 200,000 years old. Homo floresiensis may be as young as 70,000 years, as preliminary dating for the species indicates, but it could also be much older, perhaps 800,000 years old: Rex Dalton, "Little Lady of Flores Forces Rethink of Human Evolution," Nature, CDXXXI (2004): 1029
-
(2004)
Nature
, vol.431
, pp. 1029
-
-
Dalton, R.1
-
65
-
-
7744247111
-
Palaeoanthropology: Human Evolution Writ Small
-
at p, 1043
-
see also Marta Mirazón Lahr and Robert Foley, " Palaeoanthropology: Human Evolution Writ Small," Nature, CDXXXI (2004): 1043-44, at p. 1043
-
(2004)
Nature
, vol.431
, pp. 1043-1044
-
-
Lahr, M.M.1
Foley, R.2
-
66
-
-
0038113195
-
Human Evolution: Out of Ethiopia
-
693
-
If the earlier date is accurate, Homo floresiensis may still be younger than Homo neanderthalensis, whose roots may lie further back in Africa than the date of origin just mentioned: Chris Stringer, "Human Evolution: Out of Ethiopia," Nature, CDXXIII (2003): 692-95, p. 693
-
(2003)
Nature
, vol.423
, pp. 692-695
-
-
Stringer, C.1
-
67
-
-
16544391237
-
Hobbits of the South Pacific
-
(November 8), at p. 52)
-
Further information might, of course, reveal that the order in which the three species in question emerged is not as I have assumed. But even if my example becomes outdated for this reason, minor alterations could probably render it historically accurate: some other lineage could be substituted in place of Homo floresiensis to the same effect. As one of the team leaders responsible for finding Homo floresiensis indicates, Homo floresiensis was probably one of many species to arise during human history from populations isolated on islands: "I think we're going to have a plethora of new human species showing up," Michael Morwood says (quoted in Michael Lemonick, "Hobbits of the South Pacific," Time (November 8, 2004): 50-52, at p. 52)
-
(2004)
Time
, pp. 50-52
-
-
Lemonick, M.1
-
68
-
-
7744243968
-
A New Small-Bodied Hominin from the Late Pleistocene of Flores, Indonesia
-
at p, 1061
-
the same claim is made by P. Brown, T. Sutikna, M. J. Morwood, R. P. Soejono, Jatmiko, E. Wayhu Saptomo, Rokus Awe Due, "A New Small-Bodied Hominin from the Late Pleistocene of Flores, Indonesia," Nature, CDXXXI (2004): 1055-61, at p. 1061
-
(2004)
Nature
, vol.431
, pp. 1055-1061
-
-
Brown, P.1
Sutikna, T.2
Morwood, M.J.3
Soejono, R.P.4
Jatmiko5
Saptomo, E.W.6
Due, R.A.7
-
69
-
-
33745287794
-
-
Chantilly, VA: Teaching Co, 170;
-
Barbara King, Biological Anthropology: An Evolutionary Perspective, Part I (Chantilly, VA: Teaching Co., 2002), pp. 164, 170
-
(2002)
Biological Anthropology: An Evolutionary Perspective, Part i
, pp. 164
-
-
King, B.1
-
73
-
-
2642522696
-
The Evolution of Modern Humans: Where Are We Now?
-
at p, 3
-
Stringer, "The Evolution of Modern Humans: Where Are We Now?," General Anthropology, VII (2001): 1-5, at p. 3
-
(2001)
General Anthropology
, vol.7
, pp. 1-5
-
-
Stringer1
-
80
-
-
85038671686
-
-
"A Defense," p. 164
-
A Defense
, pp. 164
-
-
-
81
-
-
85038723632
-
Acknowledge this, citing species of freshwater gastropods
-
Wheeler and Meier, eds., p. 105
-
Meier and Willmann acknowledge this, citing species of freshwater gastropods: " A Critique from the Hennigian Species Concept Perspective," in Wheeler and Meier, eds., pp. 101-18, p. 105
-
A Critique from the Hennigian Species Concept Perspective
, pp. 101-118
-
-
Meier1
Willmann2
|