메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 102, Issue 7, 2005, Pages 357-374

Is there a single objective, evolutionary tree of life?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33847150986     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2005102717     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (16)

References (82)
  • 2
    • 85038774092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sex and Death
    • Chicago: University Press
    • Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology (Chicago: University Press, 1999), p. 196
    • (1999) An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology , pp. 196
  • 3
    • 0002124490 scopus 로고
    • Cladistic Theory
    • Peter L. Forey, Christopher J. Humphries, Ian J. Kitching, Robert W. Scotland, Darrell J. Siebert, and David M. Williams, eds. (New York: Oxford), at p. 3.
    • I quote from Robert W. Scotland, "Cladistic Theory," in Peter L. Forey, Christopher J. Humphries, Ian J. Kitching, Robert W. Scotland, Darrell J. Siebert, and David M. Williams, eds., Cladistics: A Practical Course in Systematics (New York: Oxford, 1992), pp. 3-13, at p. 3
    • (1992) Cladistics: A Practical Course in Systematics , pp. 3-13
    • Scotland, R.W.1
  • 4
    • 79958397686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ridley, ed., Evolution (New York: Oxford)
    • Ridley, "Can Classification Do Without Evolution?," in Ridley, ed., Evolution (New York: Oxford, 1997), pp. 196-206; this citation is from p. 202
    • (1997) Can Classification Do Without Evolution? , pp. 196-206
    • Ridley1
  • 5
    • 79958393813 scopus 로고
    • Ridley is always reminding his many readers, is widely accepted: Evolution and Classification
    • (New York: Longman)
    • That cladism "allows only one classification: the classification defined by the hierarchy of phylogenetic branching," as Ridley is always reminding his many readers, is widely accepted: Evolution and Classification: The Reformation of Cladism (New York: Longman, 1986), p. 46
    • (1986) The Reformation of Cladism , pp. 46
  • 6
    • 0001685234 scopus 로고
    • Cladistic Classification and Functional Explanation
    • at p, 207
    • See Griffiths, "Cladistic Classification and Functional Explanation," Philosophy of Science, LXI (1994): 206-27, at p. 207
    • (1994) Philosophy of Science , vol.61 , pp. 206-227
    • Griffiths1
  • 7
    • 0042092606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Role of Theories in Biological Systematics, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part C:
    • at p. 224
    • David Hull, "The Role of Theories in Biological Systematics," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, XXXII (2001): 221-38, at p. 224
    • (2001) Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences , vol.32 , pp. 221-238
    • Hull, D.1
  • 8
    • 0003149624 scopus 로고
    • The Limits of Cladism
    • at pp. 437-38
    • "The Limits of Cladism," Systematic Zoology, XXVIII (1979): 416-40, at pp. 437-38
    • (1979) Systematic Zoology , vol.28 , pp. 416-440
  • 10
    • 0024873017 scopus 로고
    • The Cladistic Solution to the Species Problem
    • "The Cladistic Solution to the Species Problem," Biology and Philosophy, IV (1989): 1-16
    • (1989) Biology and Philosophy , vol.4 , pp. 1-16
  • 12
    • 67651149188 scopus 로고
    • Cladism or Gradism?: A Reply to Ernst Mayr
    • at pp, 447-448
    • Donn Eric Rosen, "Cladism or Gradism?: A Reply to Ernst Mayr," Systematic Zoology, XXIII (1974): 446-51, at pp. 447-48
    • (1974) Systematic Zoology , vol.23 , pp. 446-451
    • Eric Rosen, D.1
  • 15
    • 0014853540 scopus 로고
    • Rainbow's End: The Quest for an Optimal Taxonomy
    • at p. 231
    • Foreshadows of the problems that I raise may be found, in some measure or other, in L.A.S. Johnson, "Rainbow's End: The Quest for an Optimal Taxonomy," Systematic Zoology, XIX (1970): 203-39, at p. 231
    • (1970) Systematic Zoology , vol.19 , pp. 203-239
    • Johnson, L.A.S.1
  • 16
    • 12044255162 scopus 로고
    • Systematic Generalization, Historical Fate, and the Species Problem
    • at pp, 232-233
    • Robert O'Hara, "Systematic Generalization, Historical Fate, and the Species Problem," Systematic Biology, XLII (1993): 231-16, at pp. 232-33
    • (1993) Systematic Biology , vol.42 , pp. 231-316
    • O'Hara, R.1
  • 17
    • 0038214625 scopus 로고
    • The Nature of Species
    • at p, 17
    • and Sterelny, "The Nature of Species," Philosophical Books, XXXV (1994): pp. 9-20 at p. 17
    • (1994) Philosophical Books , vol.35 , pp. 9-20
    • Sterelny1
  • 18
    • 0004275113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • who appears since to have had a change of heart (cf. Griffiths and Sterelny, Sex and Death, pp. 194-97): in section v, I indicate that there is something importantly right in each position
    • Sex and Death , pp. 194-197
    • Griffiths1    Sterelny2
  • 19
    • 0002425667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Biological Species Concept
    • Quentin D. Wheeler and Rudolf Meier, eds. (New York: Columbia), cited at p. 17.
    • Mayr, "The Biological Species Concept," in Quentin D. Wheeler and Rudolf Meier, eds., Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory (New York: Columbia, 2000), pp. 17-29, cited at p. 17
    • (2000) Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory , pp. 17-29
    • Mayr1
  • 20
    • 0004110029 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard
    • This is a typical statement of the biological species concept. It is repeated word for word in several places: Evolution and the Diversity of Life: Selected Essays (Cambridge: Harvard, 1976), p. 518
    • (1976) Evolution and the Diversity of Life: Selected Essays , pp. 518
  • 23
    • 0036095630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ernst Mayr through Time on the Biological Species Concept: A Conceptual Analysis
    • Still
    • Still, the biological species concept has undergone change over Mayr's many active decades: see Peter Beurton, "Ernst Mayr through Time on the Biological Species Concept: A Conceptual Analysis," Theory in Biosciences, CXXI (2002): 81-98
    • (2002) Theory in Biosciences , vol.121 , pp. 81-98
    • Beurton, P.1
  • 24
    • 33847096583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comments by Ernst Mayr
    • and Mayr, "Comments by Ernst Mayr," Theory in Biosciences, CXXI (2002): 99-100
    • (2002) Theory in Biosciences , vol.121 , pp. 99-100
    • Mayr1
  • 25
    • 0020869892 scopus 로고
    • Species Concepts and Speciation Analysis
    • R.F. Johnston, ed. (New York: Plenum), cited at p. 170.
    • Cracraft, "Species Concepts and Speciation Analysis," in R.F. Johnston, ed., Current Ornithology (New York: Plenum, 1983), pp. 159-87, cited at p. 170
    • (1983) Current Ornithology , pp. 159-187
    • Cracraft1
  • 26
    • 0002815874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Species Concepts in Systematics and Conservation Biology: An Ornithological Viewpoint
    • M. Claridge, H. Dawah, and M. R. Wilson, eds, New York: Chapman and Hall, 331
    • Cracraft, "Species Concepts in Systematics and Conservation Biology: An Ornithological Viewpoint," in M. Claridge, H. Dawah, and M. R. Wilson, eds., Species: The Units of Biodiversity (New York: Chapman and Hall, 1997), pp. 325-39, p. 331
    • (1997) Species: The Units of Biodiversity , pp. 325-339
    • Cracraft1
  • 27
    • 0029926109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Birds in Double Trouble
    • Graham Martin, "Birds in Double Trouble," Nature, CCCLXXX (1996): 666-67
    • (1996) Nature , vol.380 , pp. 666-667
    • Martin, G.1
  • 30
    • 1642563044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wheeler and Meier, p. 164
    • This sort of budding from a parental species that survives without much change is probably common: most speciation events probably start with small, isolated founder populations: Mayr, "A Defense of the Biological Species Concept," in Wheeler and Meier, eds., pp. 161-66, p. 164
    • A Defense of the Biological Species Concept , pp. 161-166
    • Mayr1
  • 33
    • 85038771552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Cladistic Solution
    • 5-6, 8
    • Ridley, "The Cladistic Solution," pp. 3, 5-6, 8
    • Ridley1
  • 34
    • 0002943910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wheeler and Meier, eds, at p. 86;
    • Objection: the issue has been misconceived. The real issue is not whether Cracraft is wrong to name his narrower groups. One can apply names as one fancies. The real issue is whether Cracraft's use of 'species' breaks from traditional use. If there is a break from traditional use, then Cracraft errs in supposing that he is talking about species; he is talking about some other kind of group to which he has applied the name. Reply: traditional use does not settle in favor of any rival of the phylogenetic species concept. The tradition has long been shared by "lumpers" and "splitters." Both persuasions are reasonable. Over generations, workers of different persuasions have treated the same lineages differently: for examples, see Wiley and Richard L. Mayden, "The Evolutionary Species Concept," in Wheeler and Meier, eds., pp. 70-89, at p. 86
    • The Evolutionary Species Concept , pp. 70-89
    • Wiley1    Mayden, R.L.2
  • 36
    • 79958378571 scopus 로고
    • Including an Autobiographical Chapter, 2, ed. (London: John Murray)
    • The tradition has also long been characterized by different measures to delimit species, including patterns of resemblance, as Darwin indicates in a famous passage: It is really laughable to see what different ideas are prominent in various naturalists' minds, when they speak of "species"; in some, resemblance is everything and descent of little weight - in some, resemblance seems to go for nothing, and Creation the reigning idea - in some, sterility an unfailing test, with others it is not worth a farthing. It all comes, I believe, from trying to define the indefinable (The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, Including an Autobiographical Chapter, Volume 2, F. Darwin, ed. (London: John Murray, 1887), p.88)
    • (1887) The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin , pp. 88
    • Darwin, F.1
  • 37
    • 0027338764 scopus 로고
    • Permanent Splits as Speciation Events: A Formal Reconstruction of the Internodal Species Concept
    • Even the tradition of cladism fails to settle upon a single species concept. Hennig dodges the issue: see section VI. Hennig's most stalwart followers fail to agree on a single concept: cf. D. J. Kornet, "Permanent Splits as Speciation Events: A Formal Reconstruction of the Internodal Species Concept," Journal of Theoretical Biology, CLXIV (1993): 407-35
    • (1993) Journal of Theoretical Biology , vol.164 , pp. 407-435
    • Kornet, D.J.1
  • 41
    • 0002983450 scopus 로고
    • The Meaning of Species and Speciation: A Genetic Perspective
    • Marc Ereshefsky, ed, Cambridge: MIT, 174
    • Alan Templeton, "The Meaning of Species and Speciation: A Genetic Perspective," in Marc Ereshefsky, ed., The Units of Evolution (Cambridge: MIT, 1992), pp. 159-83, p. 174
    • (1992) The Units of Evolution , pp. 159-183
    • Templeton, A.1
  • 42
    • 2342580020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ecological Species, Multispecies, and Oaks
    • 72-73
    • L. Van Valen, "Ecological Species, Multispecies, and Oaks," in Ereshefsky, pp. 69-77, pp. 72-73
    • Ereshefsky , pp. 69-77
    • Van Valen, L.1
  • 43
    • 0036498251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When Is a Parasite Species a Species?
    • Werner Kunz, "When Is a Parasite Species a Species?," Trends in Parasitology, XVIII (2002): 121-24
    • (2002) Trends in Parasitology , vol.18 , pp. 121-124
    • Kunz, W.1
  • 45
    • 0025673531 scopus 로고
    • The Driving Force: Species Concepts and Ecology
    • L. Andersson, "The Driving Force: Species Concepts and Ecology," Taxon, XXXIX (1990): 375-82
    • (1990) Taxon , vol.39 , pp. 375-382
    • Andersson, L.1
  • 46
    • 0141941120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding and Confronting Species Uncertainty in Biology and Conservation
    • 599
    • Jody Hey, Robin S. Waples, Michael L. Arnold, Roger K. Butlin, and Richard G. Harrison, "Understanding and Confronting Species Uncertainty in Biology and Conservation," Trends in Ecology and Evolution, XVIII (2003): 597-603, p. 599
    • (2003) Trends in Ecology and Evolution , vol.18 , pp. 597-603
    • Hey, J.1    Waples, R.S.2    Arnold, M.L.3    Butlin, R.K.4    Harrison, R.G.5
  • 48
    • 0006689406 scopus 로고
    • The Evolution of Citrus Species: Methods to Develop New Sweet Orange Cultivars
    • 1-3
    • A limited amount of hybridization is common among recognized species of both plants and animals: for discussion of examples, see C. J. Hearn, "The Evolution of Citrus Species: Methods to Develop New Sweet Orange Cultivars," Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Florida State Horticultural Society, CVII (1994): 1-3, p. 2
    • (1994) Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Florida State Horticultural Society , vol.107 , pp. 2
    • Hearn, C.J.1
  • 49
    • 0037141198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defining the Sources of Paradox: DNA Sequence Markers for North American Walnut (Juglans L.) Species and Hybrids
    • Daniel Potter, Fangyou Gao, Scott Baggett, James R. McKenna, and Gale H. McGranahan, "Defining the Sources of Paradox: DNA Sequence Markers for North American Walnut (Juglans L.) Species and Hybrids," Scientia Horticulturae, XCIV (2002): 157-70
    • (2002) Scientia Horticulturae , vol.94 , pp. 157-170
    • Potter, D.1    Gao, F.2    Baggett, S.3    McKenna, J.R.4    McGranahan, G.H.5
  • 51
    • 79958415969 scopus 로고
    • R.C. Stauffer, ed. (New York: Cambridge)
    • The problem of drawing a line at some point has long been recognized: "the infertility of species when crossed graduates away so insensibly that the two most experienced observers who ever lived have come to diametrically opposite results when experimentising on the same forms," Darwin writes (Charles Darwin's Natural Selection: Being the Second Part of His Big Species Book Written From 1856 to 1858), R.C. Stauffer, ed. (New York: Cambridge, 1975), p. 165)
    • (1975) Natural Selection: Being the Second Part of His Big Species Book Written from 1856 to 1858 , pp. 165
    • Darwin, C.1
  • 56
    • 84890987894 scopus 로고
    • Species Concepts: A Case for Pluralism
    • 495
    • B. Mishler and M. Donoghue, "Species Concepts: A Case for Pluralism," Systematic Zoology, xxxi (1982): 491-503, p. 495
    • (1982) Systematic Zoology , vol.31 , pp. 491-503
    • Mishler, B.1    Donoghue, M.2
  • 58
    • 85038656583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Meier and Willmann, "A Defense." This suggestion raises the possibility that the term 'species' be given by stipulation a new use that would make tree construction a repeatable enterprise. Occasions of discord could be reduced in this way: even stipulating the biological species concept over the phylogenetic species concept is an improvement. But there is little value in going to drastic measures in this direction to describe a kind of group that, however quirky or biologically meaningless, allows for repeatable ordering. Nor would any algorithm generating an ordering of quirky groups show that there is a repeatable account of the hierarchy of species; at best, such an algorithm would show that there is a repeatable account of the hierarchy of some new kind of group deserving a new name. Observe that just as 'species' might be given an artificial, stipulated use that approximates to some extent ordinary use in order to allow for repeatable groupings, so might 'similarity': tellingly, cladists find this trick for achieving repeatability to be arbitrary and to preclude the kind of objectivity in ordering that cladism is supposed to enjoy (Ridley, "Can Classification Do Without Evolution?," p. 199)
    • Can Classification Do Without Evolution? , pp. 199
    • Ridley1
  • 64
    • 19644400576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Little Lady of Flores Forces Rethink of Human Evolution
    • Homo neanderthalensis is typically thought to be around 400,000 years old and Homo sapiens around 200,000 years old. Homo floresiensis may be as young as 70,000 years, as preliminary dating for the species indicates, but it could also be much older, perhaps 800,000 years old: Rex Dalton, "Little Lady of Flores Forces Rethink of Human Evolution," Nature, CDXXXI (2004): 1029
    • (2004) Nature , vol.431 , pp. 1029
    • Dalton, R.1
  • 65
    • 7744247111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Palaeoanthropology: Human Evolution Writ Small
    • at p, 1043
    • see also Marta Mirazón Lahr and Robert Foley, " Palaeoanthropology: Human Evolution Writ Small," Nature, CDXXXI (2004): 1043-44, at p. 1043
    • (2004) Nature , vol.431 , pp. 1043-1044
    • Lahr, M.M.1    Foley, R.2
  • 66
    • 0038113195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Evolution: Out of Ethiopia
    • 693
    • If the earlier date is accurate, Homo floresiensis may still be younger than Homo neanderthalensis, whose roots may lie further back in Africa than the date of origin just mentioned: Chris Stringer, "Human Evolution: Out of Ethiopia," Nature, CDXXIII (2003): 692-95, p. 693
    • (2003) Nature , vol.423 , pp. 692-695
    • Stringer, C.1
  • 67
    • 16544391237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbits of the South Pacific
    • (November 8), at p. 52)
    • Further information might, of course, reveal that the order in which the three species in question emerged is not as I have assumed. But even if my example becomes outdated for this reason, minor alterations could probably render it historically accurate: some other lineage could be substituted in place of Homo floresiensis to the same effect. As one of the team leaders responsible for finding Homo floresiensis indicates, Homo floresiensis was probably one of many species to arise during human history from populations isolated on islands: "I think we're going to have a plethora of new human species showing up," Michael Morwood says (quoted in Michael Lemonick, "Hobbits of the South Pacific," Time (November 8, 2004): 50-52, at p. 52)
    • (2004) Time , pp. 50-52
    • Lemonick, M.1
  • 68
    • 7744243968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A New Small-Bodied Hominin from the Late Pleistocene of Flores, Indonesia
    • at p, 1061
    • the same claim is made by P. Brown, T. Sutikna, M. J. Morwood, R. P. Soejono, Jatmiko, E. Wayhu Saptomo, Rokus Awe Due, "A New Small-Bodied Hominin from the Late Pleistocene of Flores, Indonesia," Nature, CDXXXI (2004): 1055-61, at p. 1061
    • (2004) Nature , vol.431 , pp. 1055-1061
    • Brown, P.1    Sutikna, T.2    Morwood, M.J.3    Soejono, R.P.4    Jatmiko5    Saptomo, E.W.6    Due, R.A.7
  • 73
    • 2642522696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Evolution of Modern Humans: Where Are We Now?
    • at p, 3
    • Stringer, "The Evolution of Modern Humans: Where Are We Now?," General Anthropology, VII (2001): 1-5, at p. 3
    • (2001) General Anthropology , vol.7 , pp. 1-5
    • Stringer1
  • 80
    • 85038671686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "A Defense," p. 164
    • A Defense , pp. 164
  • 81
    • 85038723632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Acknowledge this, citing species of freshwater gastropods
    • Wheeler and Meier, eds., p. 105
    • Meier and Willmann acknowledge this, citing species of freshwater gastropods: " A Critique from the Hennigian Species Concept Perspective," in Wheeler and Meier, eds., pp. 101-18, p. 105
    • A Critique from the Hennigian Species Concept Perspective , pp. 101-118
    • Meier1    Willmann2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.