메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 75, Issue 3, 2006, Pages 1229-1253

Legal obligations and the internal aspect of rules

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33846636366     PISSN: 0015704X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (20)

References (55)
  • 3
    • 33846609903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 18-19
    • Id. at 18-19.
  • 4
    • 33846600262 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law, 10
    • Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 458 (1897),
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev , vol.457 , pp. 458
    • Wendell Holmes Jr., O.1
  • 5
    • 33846583910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted in 110 Harv. L. Rev. 991, 992 (1997).
    • reprinted in 110 Harv. L. Rev. 991, 992 (1997).
  • 6
    • 33846588717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 7
    • 33846599158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 210-11
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 210-11.
  • 9
    • 33846636687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart's reference to the puzzled man and the ignorant man in Hart, supra note 1, at 40
    • See Hart's reference to the "puzzled man" and the "ignorant man" in Hart, supra note 1, at 40.
  • 10
    • 33846617594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contra Ronald Dworkin, Hart's Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy, 24 O.J.L.S. 1 (2004) (criticizing Hart's methodology as one aspiring to occupy an Archimedean perspective).
    • Contra Ronald Dworkin, Hart's Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy, 24 O.J.L.S. 1 (2004) (criticizing Hart's methodology as one aspiring to occupy an Archimedean perspective).
  • 11
    • 33846632175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's connection to Oxford's philosophical community is illuminatingly examined in Nicola Lacey, A Life of H.L.A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream (2004) and Neil MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (1981).
    • Hart's connection to Oxford's philosophical community is illuminatingly examined in Nicola Lacey, A Life of H.L.A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream (2004) and Neil MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (1981).
  • 12
    • 33846592165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Frederick Schauer, (Re)Taking Hart, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 852 (2006) (reviewing Nicola Lacey, A Life of H.L.A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream (2004)).
    • See also Frederick Schauer, (Re)Taking Hart, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 852 (2006) (reviewing Nicola Lacey, A Life of H.L.A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream (2004)).
  • 13
    • 33846572179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The analysis offered by MacCormick of Hart on legal obligations and Hart on the internal point of view is nuanced and critical, raising a number of the concerns indicated below. See MacCormick, supra note 10, at 33-40, 55-70
    • The analysis offered by MacCormick of Hart on legal obligations and Hart on the internal point of view is nuanced and critical, raising a number of the concerns indicated below. See MacCormick, supra note 10, at 33-40, 55-70.
  • 14
    • 33846641516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, Michael Martin's analyses of legal obligations and of the internal point of view are very helpful in displaying several of the difficulties and apparent contradictions. See Michael Martin, The Legal Philosophy of H.L.A. Hart: A Critical Appraisal 15-39 (1987).
    • Similarly, Michael Martin's analyses of legal obligations and of the internal point of view are very helpful in displaying several of the difficulties and apparent contradictions. See Michael Martin, The Legal Philosophy of H.L.A. Hart: A Critical Appraisal 15-39 (1987).
  • 15
    • 33846573152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the source of one Dworkin's criticisms of Hart in his chapter The Model of Rules II. See Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 46-80 1977
    • This is the source of one Dworkin's criticisms of Hart in his chapter "The Model of Rules II." See Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 46-80 (1977).
  • 16
    • 33846618556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 90 (The external point of view may very nearly reproduce the way in which the rules function in the lives of certain members of the group ....).
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 90 ("The external point of view may very nearly reproduce the way in which the rules function in the lives of certain members of the group ....").
  • 17
    • 33846597837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 240
    • Id. at 240.
  • 18
    • 33846621350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 102
    • Id. at 102.
  • 19
    • 33846606675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 256-57 distinguishing enacted legal rules from judicial customary legal rules and stating that the practice theory is inapplicable to the former
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 256-57 (distinguishing enacted legal rules from judicial customary legal rules and stating that the practice theory is inapplicable to the former).
  • 20
    • 33846644314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 88
    • Id. at 88.
  • 21
    • 33846634470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 257
    • Id. at 257.
  • 23
    • 33846612573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scott J. Shapiro, The Bad Man and the Internal Point of View, in The Path of the Law and Its Influence: The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., supra, at 197-210.
    • Scott J. Shapiro, The Bad Man and the Internal Point of View, in The Path of the Law and Its Influence: The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., supra, at 197-210.
  • 24
    • 33846616179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 90-91
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 90-91.
  • 25
    • 33846620443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perry, supra note 19, at 162-65
    • Perry, supra note 19, at 162-65.
  • 26
    • 33846614864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 164-65
    • Id. at 164-65.
  • 27
    • 33846639478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 165
    • Id. at 165.
  • 28
    • 33846613064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 165-76
    • Id. at 165-76.
  • 29
    • 33846569279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 191-92
    • Id. at 191-92.
  • 30
    • 33846577177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shapiro, supra note 19, at 203
    • Shapiro, supra note 19, at 203.
  • 31
    • 33846629327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 208-09
    • Id. at 208-09.
  • 32
    • 33846614417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This sentence should not be read to suggest that Shapiro believes Perry's normative turn would be helpful to Hart
    • This sentence should not be read to suggest that Shapiro believes Perry's normative turn would be helpful to Hart.
  • 33
    • 33846645240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 88
    • Hart, supra note 1, at 88.
  • 34
    • 33846562008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Is the Internal Point of View?, 75
    • Scott J. Shapiro, What Is the Internal Point of View?, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 1157, 1166 2006)
    • (2006) Fordham L. Rev , vol.1157 , pp. 1166
    • Shapiro, S.J.1
  • 36
    • 33846639477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's conflation of these closely related ideas is interestingly seen in a passage that Shapiro quotes in his response to Perry: One of the difficulties facing any legal theory anxious to do justice to the complexity of the facts is to remember the presence of both these points of view and not to define one of them out of existence. Perhaps all our criticisms of the predictive theory of obligation may be best summarized as the accusation that this is what it does to the internal aspect of obligatory rules. Hart, supra note 1, at 91 (emphasis added, In the first of the two sentences quoted above, Hart is referring to the difficulty (or challenge) of not defining one of these points of view out of existence. He then concludes by suggesting that his critique of the predictive theory is summarized by saying that this is what it does, presumably to the internal point of view. However the noun phrase at
    • Hart's conflation of these closely related ideas is interestingly seen in a passage that Shapiro quotes in his response to Perry: One of the difficulties facing any legal theory anxious to do justice to the complexity of the facts is to remember the presence of both these points of view and not to define one of them out of existence. Perhaps all our criticisms of the predictive theory of obligation may be best summarized as the accusation that this is what it does to the internal aspect of obligatory rules. Hart, supra note 1, at 91 (emphasis added). In the first of the two sentences quoted above, Hart is referring to the "difficulty" (or challenge) of not defining "one of" these "points of view" out of existence. He then concludes by suggesting that his critique of the predictive theory is summarized by saying that "this is what it does," presumably to "the internal point of view." However the noun phrase at the end of this passage is not "the internal point of view" but "the internal aspect of obligatory rules." Id.
  • 37
    • 33846633547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 27
    • Id. at 27.
  • 38
    • 33846566150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality 153-57 (1979, Raz's argument that Hart needs the notion of a detached statement is supportive of the general approach I am taking, but the notion of a detached statement does not capture what I am referring to, for it (quite expressly) presumes that the speaker is withholding commitment from the internal point of view. What we need here is what is in common between the detached statement and an internal statement. Removing oneself (as opposed to accepting) is a direction to take. Similarly, accepting an assertion and rejecting an assertion are two different responses, but understanding the assertion is common to both. Critical, from a hermeneutic point of view, is grasping that the (putative) legal norm is enjoining conduct and grasping what it is enjoining. The compliant and the manipulative, the good and the bad, and the detached all see this aspect of primary rules
    • See Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality 153-57 (1979). Raz's argument that Hart needs the notion of a detached statement is supportive of the general approach I am taking, but the notion of a detached statement does not capture what I am referring to, for it (quite expressly) presumes that the speaker is withholding commitment from the internal point of view. What we need here is what is in common between the detached statement and an internal statement. Removing oneself (as opposed to accepting) is a direction to take. Similarly, accepting an assertion and rejecting an assertion are two different responses, but understanding the assertion is common to both. Critical, from a hermeneutic point of view, is grasping that the (putative) legal norm is enjoining conduct and grasping what it is enjoining. The compliant and the manipulative, the good and the bad, and the detached all see this aspect of primary rules.
  • 39
    • 0001609162 scopus 로고
    • Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85
    • Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 1089 (1972).
    • (1972) Harv. L. Rev , vol.1089
    • Calabresi, G.1    Douglas Melamed, A.2
  • 40
    • 41549090207 scopus 로고
    • Rethinking the Theory of Legal Rights, 95
    • See
    • See Jules A. Coleman & Jody Kraus, Rethinking the Theory of Legal Rights, 95 Yale L.J. 1335 (1986);
    • (1986) Yale L.J , vol.1335
    • Coleman, J.A.1    Kraus, J.2
  • 41
    • 0347683534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dale A. Nance, Guidance Rules and Enforcement Rules: A Better View of the Cathedral, 83 Va. L. Rev. 837 (1997). This essay builds on my own critique of Calabresi and Melamed, which drew upon a Hartian conception of legal obligation.
    • Dale A. Nance, Guidance Rules and Enforcement Rules: A Better View of the Cathedral, 83 Va. L. Rev. 837 (1997). This essay builds on my own critique of Calabresi and Melamed, which drew upon a Hartian conception of legal obligation.
  • 42
    • 0032350230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights, Wrongs, and Recourse in the Law of Torts, 51
    • See
    • See Benjamin C. Zipursky, Rights, Wrongs, and Recourse in the Law of Torts, 51 Vand. L. Rev. 1, 55-60 (1998).
    • (1998) Vand. L. Rev , vol.1 , pp. 55-60
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 43
    • 33846594618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lacey, supra note 10;
    • See Lacey, supra note 10;
  • 44
    • 33846565225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MacCormick, supra note 10
    • MacCormick, supra note 10.
  • 45
    • 33846591830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor John Goldberg and I have elsewhere offered a Haitian, primary rule-oriented response to the critique of duty in The Path of the Law. John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Seeing Tort Law from the Internal Point of View: Holmes and Hart on Legal Duties, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 1563 2006, Here, I present just our basic story: First, the nature of tort law is to predicate the imposition of liability upon the recognition of a power in the plaintiff, and to predicate the power upon a finding of a breach of a duty of conduct by the defendant. Hence, duties of conduct are critical. The second is that-as Austin himself recognized and as Hart and Raz have both recognized-courts are empowered to articulate law, including the articulation of primary rules of conduct. Third, Hart's rules of recognition render it coherent to suppose that primary rules exist within the law by virtue of being identifiable according to secondary legal rules that courts articulate and util
    • Professor John Goldberg and I have elsewhere offered a Haitian, primary rule-oriented response to the critique of duty in The Path of the Law. John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Seeing Tort Law from the Internal Point of View: Holmes and Hart on Legal Duties, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 1563 (2006). Here, I present just our basic story: First, the nature of tort law is to predicate the imposition of liability upon the recognition of a power in the plaintiff, and to predicate the power upon a finding of a breach of a duty of conduct by the defendant. Hence, duties of conduct are critical. The second is that-as Austin himself recognized and as Hart and Raz have both recognized-courts are empowered to articulate law, including the articulation of primary rules of conduct. Third, Hart's rules of recognition render it coherent to suppose that primary rules exist within the law by virtue of being identifiable according to secondary legal rules that courts articulate and utilize.
  • 46
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Natural Rights?, 64
    • See
    • See H.L.A. Hart, Are There Any Natural Rights?, 64 Phil. Rev. 175 (1955);
    • (1955) Phil. Rev , vol.175
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 47
    • 33846608972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also MacCormick, supra note 10, at 155-58
    • see also MacCormick, supra note 10, at 155-58.
  • 49
    • 33846644313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, supra note 1, at 40 discussing the puzzled man and the ignorant man
    • See Hart, supra note 1, at 40 (discussing the "puzzled man" and the "ignorant man").
  • 50
    • 33846582745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 90
    • Id. at 90
  • 51
    • 33846625469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This leaves open the claim, made most forcefully by Scott Shapiro, that the conception of the internal point of view which entails norm acceptance is fundamental to Hart's treatment of legal officials, which is, in turn, fundamental to his entire explanation of how it is that a legal system could exist as the legal system of a community. Shapiro, supra note 30, at 1169-70
    • This leaves open the claim, made most forcefully by Scott Shapiro, that the conception of the "internal point of view" which entails norm acceptance is fundamental to Hart's treatment of legal officials, which is, in turn, fundamental to his entire explanation of how it is that a legal system could exist as the legal system of a community. Shapiro, supra note 30, at 1169-70.
  • 52
    • 0348194818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral of MacPherson, 146
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733 (1998).
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev , vol.1733
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 54
    • 33846649403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Holmes, supra note 4
    • Holmes, supra note 4.
  • 55
    • 33846647780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part V.C.
    • See supra Part V.C.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.