메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 117, Issue 1, 2006, Pages 7-31

Compatibilism and contractualism: The possibility of moral responsibility

(1)  Lenman, James a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33846326858     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/508035     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (29)

References (48)
  • 2
  • 3
    • 33846308208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the implication here that the free-will problem is in fact a family of problems, cf. T. M. Scanlon, The Significance of Choice, Tanner Lectures on Human Values 8 (1988): 149-216, lecture 1, sec. 2.
    • On the implication here that the free-will problem is in fact a family of problems, cf. T. M. Scanlon, "The Significance of Choice," Tanner Lectures on Human Values 8 (1988): 149-216, lecture 1, sec. 2.
  • 6
    • 33846297428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The modern locus classicus for this line of argument is Peter van Inwagen, An Essay on Free Will (Oxford: Clarendon, 1983).
    • The modern locus classicus for this line of argument is Peter van Inwagen, An Essay on Free Will (Oxford: Clarendon, 1983).
  • 7
    • 0011373143 scopus 로고
    • The Impossibility of Moral Responsibility
    • See esp
    • See esp. Galen Strawson, "The Impossibility of Moral Responsibility," Philosophical Studies 75 (1994): 5-24.
    • (1994) Philosophical Studies , vol.75 , pp. 5-24
    • Strawson, G.1
  • 8
    • 0742334759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp. chaps. 3 and 4
    • See also Saul Smilansky, Free Will and Illusion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), esp. chaps. 3 and 4.
    • (2000) Free Will and Illusion
    • Smilansky, S.1
  • 10
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 276.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other , pp. 276
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 15
    • 33846268862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We get a clue to Scanlon's motivation for his approach when he writes: Failure to distinguish the conditions of substantive responsibility from those of blameworthiness. on the other hand, leads to the view that if people are responsible, for their actions then they can properly be left to suffer the consequences of these actions, since these are their fault (ibid, 293, Taking holding people responsible as involving the bringing to bear of sanctions does not itself entail that it is not also sometimes appropriate to assist them with the problems from which their behavior stems or to address the social conditions that may contribute to it. Certainly these are inferences that are sometimes made, that are frequently heard in political argument 293, and that may indeed often be deeply unfortunate, but Scanlon offers no clear reason to accept what he says here if by 'leads to' he means 'warrants, There is certainly much to be appalled by in the history of s
    • We get a clue to Scanlon's motivation for his approach when he writes: "Failure to distinguish the conditions of substantive responsibility from those of blameworthiness. on the other hand, leads to the view that if people are responsible . . . for their actions then they can properly be left to suffer the consequences of these actions, since these are their fault" (ibid., 293). Taking holding people responsible as involving the bringing to bear of sanctions does not itself entail that it is not also sometimes appropriate to assist them with the problems from which their behavior stems or to address the social conditions that may contribute to it. Certainly these are inferences that are sometimes made, that are "frequently heard in political argument" (293), and that may indeed often be deeply unfortunate, but Scanlon offers no clear reason to accept what he says here if by 'leads to' he means 'warrants'. There is certainly much to be appalled by in the history of sanctioning behavior, but we may consistently defend the central role of such behavior while condemning its uglier and more excessive manifestations. Indeed my remarks about the strains of commitment in Sec. VII below might plausibly be thought to furnish the beginnings of a contractualist rationale for resisting unduly punitive norms of moral sanction.
  • 16
    • 0004189454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Susan Wolf, Freedom within Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), 44.
    • (1990) Freedom within Reason , pp. 44
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 18
    • 84897479855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Alleged Shallowness of Compatibilism: A Critical Study of Saul Smilansky
    • For a detailed critique of
    • For a detailed critique of Smilansky, see my "On the Alleged Shallowness of Compatibilism: A Critical Study of Saul Smilansky, Free Will and Illusion" Iyyun 51 (2002): 63-79.
    • (2002) Free Will and Illusion Iyyun , vol.51 , pp. 63-79
    • Smilansky1    see my2
  • 20
    • 60949428435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This and the preceding quotation are from Erin Kelly, Doing without Desert, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 2002, 180-205, 188
    • This and the preceding quotation are from Erin Kelly, "Doing without Desert," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2002): 180-205, 188.
  • 21
    • 33846278070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 186-87.
  • 22
    • 33846318986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 190.
  • 23
    • 33846306809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A key aim in this section has been to argue that we need to deepen the account Wallace gives of how it can be fair to hold others responsible in order to address the concerns aired by Kelly and others. Wallace's book is one of what are perhaps the two most impressive defenses of compatibilism in the recent literature, the other being John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, That I have learned much from this book will be evident to any reader familiar with it. But I think the story they tell calls for further development. Their view is that an agent is responsible for actions that issue from what they call a 'reasons-responsive mechanism, providing that the mechanism in question is the agent's own. The latter condition requires that the agent takes responsibility for what they do in virtue of the operations of this mechanism. And a key ingredient of what it is to do this, ac
    • A key aim in this section has been to argue that we need to deepen the account Wallace gives of how it can be fair to hold others responsible in order to address the concerns aired by Kelly and others. Wallace's book is one of what are perhaps the two most impressive defenses of compatibilism in the recent literature, the other being John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998). That I have learned much from this book will be evident to any reader familiar with it. But I think the story they tell calls for further development. Their view is that an agent is responsible for actions that issue from what they call a 'reasons-responsive mechanism', providing that the mechanism in question is the agent's own. The latter condition requires that the agent takes responsibility for what they do in virtue of the operations of this mechanism. And a key ingredient of what it is to do this, according to Fischer and Ravizza, is that the agent should view himself as a fair target for the reactive attitudes where actions that issue from this mechanism are concerned (see esp. 211). But a reader might reasonably be left unsatisfied at not having been told enough about what makes the owner of a reasons-responsive mechanism a fair target for these, and it is this concern I hope the present article will do something to address.
  • 24
    • 33846330697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this methodological approach, compare J. David Velleman, Practical Reflection (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 6.
    • On this methodological approach, compare J. David Velleman, Practical Reflection (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 6.
  • 25
    • 33846328022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Harry Frankfurt, Identification and Wholeheartedness, in his The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 159-76, esp. 165.
    • See Harry Frankfurt, "Identification and Wholeheartedness," in his The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 159-76, esp. 165.
  • 26
    • 33846296008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is a salient characteristic of human beings, one which affects our lives in deep and innumerable ways, that we care about what we are (Frankfurt, Identification and Wholeheartedness, 163).
    • "It is a salient characteristic of human beings, one which affects our lives in deep and innumerable ways, that we care about what we are" (Frankfurt, "Identification and Wholeheartedness," 163).
  • 27
    • 33846275402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scanlon, The Significance of Choice, lecture 2, sec. 1, and What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 6, sec. 2.
    • See Scanlon, "The Significance of Choice," lecture 2, sec. 1, and What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 6, sec. 2.
  • 28
    • 33846299311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • defends something provocatively close to this
    • Kelly, "Doing without Desert," defends something provocatively close to this.
    • Doing without Desert
    • Kelly1
  • 29
    • 33846296716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peter F. Strawson, Freedom and Resentment, in his Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays (London: Methuen, 1974), 1-25, 9.
    • See Peter F. Strawson, "Freedom and Resentment," in his Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays (London: Methuen, 1974), 1-25, 9.
  • 30
    • 33846313288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Joel Feinberg, Action and Responsibility, in his Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), 119-51, esp. 124-28.
    • Compare Joel Feinberg, "Action and Responsibility," in his Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), 119-51, esp. 124-28.
  • 31
    • 33846320556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The point of course again echoes Peter Strawson's Freedom and Resentment. See also Fischer and Ravizza, Responsibility and Control, 219.
    • The point of course again echoes Peter Strawson's "Freedom and Resentment." See also Fischer and Ravizza, Responsibility and Control, 219.
  • 33
    • 33846324471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 6, sec. 4, for a more detailed take on this. My rude/ugly example echoes remarks of his on 272. Compare Scanlon, The Significance of Choice, 171.
    • See Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 6, sec. 4, for a more detailed take on this. My rude/ugly example echoes remarks of his on 272. Compare Scanlon, "The Significance of Choice," 171.
  • 34
    • 33846288411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, 294 (cf. Scanlon, The Significance of Choice, 216).
    • Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, 294 (cf. Scanlon, "The Significance of Choice," 216).
  • 35
    • 33846328092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term 'reflective endorsement' is appropriated from Christine Korsgaard. See her The Sources of Narmativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), esp. lecture 2.
    • The term 'reflective endorsement' is appropriated from Christine Korsgaard. See her The Sources of Narmativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), esp. lecture 2.
  • 36
    • 33846323359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Christine Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends: Reciprocity and Responsibility in Personal Relations, in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 188-221, 210.
    • From Christine Korsgaard, "Creating the Kingdom of Ends: Reciprocity and Responsibility in Personal Relations," in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 188-221, 210.
  • 37
    • 33846285482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Frankfurt's discussion of Aristotle in Identification and Wholeheartedness, 171-72.
    • Compare Frankfurt's discussion of Aristotle in "Identification and Wholeheartedness," 171-72.
  • 38
    • 0041008438 scopus 로고
    • Freewill, Praise, and Blame
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., J. J. C. Smart, "Freewill, Praise, and Blame," Mind 70 (1961): 291-306.
    • (1961) Mind , vol.70 , pp. 291-306
    • Smart, J.J.C.1
  • 39
    • 0345775483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Saving Scanlon: Contractualism and Agent-Relativity
    • For a judicious gloss on 'personal' see
    • For a judicious gloss on 'personal' see Michael Ridge, "Saving Scanlon: Contractualism and Agent-Relativity," Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (2001): 472-81.
    • (2001) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.9 , pp. 472-481
    • Ridge, M.1
  • 41
    • 33846271887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In discussion at a seminar at St. Andrews, February 16, 2000.
    • In discussion at a seminar at St. Andrews, February 16, 2000.
  • 42
    • 14644399965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There could be a social practice according to which people would be subject to scolding and shunning in cases of actions involving no faulty willing or deliberation, but what was expressed by this behavior would not be moral blame
    • Compare Scanlon, "The Significance of Choice," 212: "There could be a social practice according to which people would be subject to scolding and shunning in cases of actions involving no faulty willing or deliberation, but what was expressed by this behavior would not be moral blame."
    • The Significance of Choice , pp. 212
    • Scanlon, C.1
  • 43
    • 0009204695 scopus 로고
    • The Importance of Free Will
    • See
    • See Susan Wolf, "The Importance of Free Will," Mind 90 (1981): 386-405.
    • (1981) Mind , vol.90 , pp. 386-405
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 44
    • 33846272250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As John Hospers argues in Meaning and Free Will.
    • As John Hospers argues in "Meaning and Free Will."
  • 45
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • See, New York: Columbia University Press
    • See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 46
    • 33846319469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bernard Williams, Internal and External Reasons, in his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 101-13.
    • See Bernard Williams, "Internal and External Reasons," in his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 101-13.
  • 47
    • 85007957094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more thoughts on this problem see my Michael Smith and the Daleks: Reason, Morality, and Contingency, Utilitas 11 (1999): 164-77, sec. 6,
    • For more thoughts on this problem see my "Michael Smith and the Daleks: Reason, Morality, and Contingency," Utilitas 11 (1999): 164-77, sec. 6,
  • 48
    • 33846292290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Contracting Responsibility, in Moral Responsibility and Ontology, ed. Ton van den Beld (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 2000), 171-82, sec. 6.
    • and "Contracting Responsibility," in Moral Responsibility and Ontology, ed. Ton van den Beld (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 2000), 171-82, sec. 6.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.