메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 52, Issue 1, 2002, Pages 220-230

Socrates' reverse irony

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33845711300     PISSN: 00098388     EISSN: 14716844     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/cq/52.1.220     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (24)

References (48)
  • 1
    • 85038798747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By 'Socrates' I am referring to the character in Plato's 'early' or 'Socratic' dialogues, consisting of (in alphabetical order): Apology, Crito, Charmides, Euthyphro, Gorgias, Hippias Minor, Ion, Laches, Protagoras, Republic 1
    • By 'Socrates' I am referring to the character in Plato's 'early' or 'Socratic' dialogues, consisting of (in alphabetical order): Apology, Crito, Charmides, Euthyphro, Gorgias, Hippias Minor, Ion, Laches, Protagoras, Republic 1.
  • 4
    • 0004269278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • See C. Kahn, Plato and the Socratic Dialogue (Cambridge, 1996) for a contrasting view. I treat these dialogues as a group because of their similarity in style and substance, rather than because of any firm belief about the order in which they were composed, or indeed even about whether they were all composed earlier than so-called 'middle' or 'late' dialogues.
    • (1996) Plato and the Socratic Dialogue
    • Kahn, C.1
  • 5
    • 63849240048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • J. Cooper ed, Indianapolis, esp
    • On questions of chronology, see also: J. Cooper, 'Introduction' in J. Cooper (ed. ) Plato: Complete Works (Indianapolis, 1997), esp. 12-18
    • (1997) Plato: Complete Works , pp. 12-18
    • Cooper, J.1
  • 6
    • 0004345486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley, chs. 1-3, in particular 219, n. 64
    • and A. Nehamas, Art of Living (Berkeley, 1998), chs. 1-3, in particular 219, n. 64, in response to Cooper. I am making no claims about the historical Socrates. I shall, however, treat the character Socrates 'realistically' - that is, as though there were such a person who had such conversations, and had such and such effects on his society.
    • (1998) Art of Living
    • Nehamas, A.1
  • 7
    • 62449334634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conditional irony in the Socratic dialogues
    • See I. Vasiliou, 'Conditional irony in the Socratic dialogues', CQ 49 (1999), 456-72.
    • (1999) CQ , vol.49 , pp. 456-472
    • Vasiliou, I.1
  • 8
    • 84974070162 scopus 로고
    • Socratic irony
    • Contrast Vlastos's 'complex irony' ([n. 1], ch. 1, originally 'Socratic irony', CQ 37 [1987], 79-96), where in one sense Socrates means what he says, but in another sense does not. See Nehamas (n. 1), ch. 2, and Vasiliou (n. 2), §§2, 4, 5, for detailed discussions of Vlastos's position and additional references.
    • (1987) CQ , vol.37 , pp. 79-96
  • 9
    • 85038735063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The distinction between the inner and outer frame complicates any discussion of the extent to which Socratic irony is deceptive. We must ask, deceptive to whom, Socrates' interlocutors or Plato's readers? See Vasiliou n. 2, esp. §4
    • The distinction between the inner and outer frame complicates any discussion of the extent to which Socratic irony is deceptive. We must ask, 'deceptive to whom?' - Socrates' interlocutors or Plato's readers? See Vasiliou (n. 2), esp. §4.
  • 10
    • 85038666874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have also argued that, contrary to Vlastos, eirôneia does not begin to shift meaning in Plato from 'dissembling' or 'putting someone on' to something more akin to what Vlastos believes is the modern meaning of 'irony, to say the opposite of what one believes without intending to deceive. Socrates engages in conditional irony but is also accused by his interlocutors of engaging in eirôneia; on such occasions he is, according to them, saying something other than what he really means. See Vasiliou (n. 2, §5, 465-8. Nehamas n. 1, 54ff. believes that Vlastos's view that opposites or contraries are necessarily part of irony is too simplistic, and covers only the crudest cases. Vlastos appeals to Cicero's and Quintilian's accounts of irony as part of the justification for his emphasis on opposites, but Nehamas argues that this is not actually warranted by the Latin texts
    • I have also argued that, contrary to Vlastos, eirôneia does not begin to shift meaning in Plato from 'dissembling' or 'putting someone on' to something more akin to what Vlastos believes is the modern meaning of 'irony': to say the opposite of what one believes without intending to deceive. Socrates engages in conditional irony but is also accused by his interlocutors of engaging in eirôneia; on such occasions he is, according to them, saying something other than what he really means. See Vasiliou (n. 2), §5, 465-8. Nehamas (n. 1), 54ff. believes that Vlastos's view that opposites or contraries are necessarily part of irony is too simplistic, and covers only the crudest cases. Vlastos appeals to Cicero's and Quintilian's accounts of irony as part of the justification for his emphasis on opposites, but Nehamas argues that this is not actually warranted by the Latin texts.
  • 11
    • 33645330655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • In the popular G. M. A. Grube translation, included in Cooper (n. 1), the conditional, and therefore the conditional irony, is lost: 'Yet I think it a fine thing to be able to teach people as Gorgias . . . '; not so in D. Gallop's Plato: Defence of Socrates, Euthyphro, Crito (Oxford, 1997).
    • (1997) Plato: Defence of Socrates, Euthyphro, Crito
    • Gallop, D.1
  • 12
    • 85038805608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Not, of course, the logical implication, which would be a simple fallacy. See Vasiliou (n. 2), 462, n. 21.
    • Not, of course, the logical implication, which would be a simple fallacy. See Vasiliou (n. 2), 462, n. 21.
  • 13
    • 85038734882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Vasiliou (n. 2), 461-3 for the importance of contrast in determining whether a claim is ironic.
    • See Vasiliou (n. 2), 461-3 for the importance of contrast in determining whether a claim is ironic.
  • 14
    • 85038703761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Given our knowledge of all the dialogues together - and so the 'experience' of many Socratic conversations - we judge the Sophists' lack of knowledge (by Socrates' lights, at least) to be the truth, against which this remark in the Apology can be understood as ironic. T. Brickhouse and N. Smith, Socrates on Trial (Princeton, 1989), 229, provide internal evidence for the claim that Socrates must not believe that Evenus has this knowledge: if Evenus had such knowledge, he would be wiser than Socrates and so the Oracle would be lying.
    • Given our knowledge of all the dialogues together - and so the 'experience' of many Socratic conversations - we judge the Sophists' lack of knowledge (by Socrates' lights, at least) to be the truth, against which this remark in the Apology can be understood as ironic. T. Brickhouse and N. Smith, Socrates on Trial (Princeton, 1989), 229, provide internal evidence for the claim that Socrates must not believe that Evenus has this knowledge: if Evenus had such knowledge, he would be wiser than Socrates and so the Oracle would be lying.
  • 15
    • 0004056394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • J. Ober, Political Dissent in Democratic Athens (Princeton, 1998), 166-79,esp. 175-6, argues persuasively that Socrates' speech itself involves an 'inversion' of traditional rhetorical tropes I hope to show that reverse irony involves an inversion of a particularly Socratic trope as well: conditional irony.
    • (1998) Political Dissent in Democratic Athens , pp. 166-179
    • Ober, J.1
  • 16
    • 85038683726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus attributions of conditional or reverse irony importantly contrast with accusations of eironeia insofar as the latter are sometimes made by speakers within the 'inner frame, e. g. Thrasymachus at R. 1. 337a4 and, significantly as we shall see, Socrates about himself at Ap. 38a1
    • Thus attributions of conditional or reverse irony importantly contrast with accusations of eironeia insofar as the latter are sometimes made by speakers within the 'inner frame': e. g. Thrasymachus at R. 1. 337a4 and, significantly as we shall see, Socrates about himself at Ap. 38a1.
  • 17
    • 85038677437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 19a2 for some foreshadowing
    • See 19a2 for some foreshadowing.
  • 18
    • 79956433370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Socratic principles, Socratic knowledge
    • In I. Vasiliou, 'Socratic principles, Socratic knowledge', Philosophical Inquiry 21. 3-4 (1999), 43-60, I contend that understanding the nature of SV (which is there called 'the Supremacy of the Ethical [SE]') is critical for a proper understanding of the argument in the Apology and Crito, and that it also allows us to resolve the apparent conflict between Socrates' frequent disavowals of moral knowledge and his occasional avowals.
    • (1999) Philosophical Inquiry , vol.21 , Issue.3-4 , pp. 43-60
    • Vasiliou, I.1
  • 19
    • 85038758864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nehamas (n. 1), 49ff. argues convincingly for a connection between irony and boastfulness, specifically in Socrates' case. Ober (n. 11), 166-79 claims that in such remarks Socrates inverts the typical rhetorical trope of a defendant: instead of claiming to be one of the people, Socrates sets himself apart from the hoi polloi.
    • Nehamas (n. 1), 49ff. argues convincingly for a connection between irony and boastfulness, specifically in Socrates' case. Ober (n. 11), 166-79 claims that in such remarks Socrates inverts the typical rhetorical trope of a defendant: instead of claiming to be one of the people, Socrates sets himself apart from the hoi polloi.
  • 20
    • 85038656141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disputing Socratic principles: Character and argument in the Polus episode of the Gorgias
    • (forthcoming)
    • For elaboration on this and an argument that it is the critical difference between him and Polus in the Gorgias, see I. Vasiliou, 'Disputing Socratic principles: character and argument in the "Polus episode" of the Gorgias', Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie (forthcoming).
    • Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
    • Vasiliou, I.1
  • 21
    • 85038784244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca
    • I am not saying this criterion should necessarily hold for anything one might want to count as irony. Rather it is a restriction I have put on the types of irony I am concerned with in this paper and in Vasiliou (n. 2), the point of which is, in part, to make identification of instances of these types of irony more easily susceptible to rational argumentation on the basis of the text. For similar concerns about irony, and the historical root of those concerns, see H. Tarrant, Plato's First Interpreters (Ithaca, 2000), 108-11.
    • (2000) Plato's First Interpreters , pp. 108-111
    • Tarrant, H.1
  • 22
    • 85038661497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more complicated notions of irony, including Platonic irony, see Nehamas (n. 1), chs. 1-3.
    • For more complicated notions of irony, including Platonic irony, see Nehamas (n. 1), chs. 1-3.
  • 23
    • 85038784519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brickhouse and Smith (n. 9), 214-21.
    • Brickhouse and Smith (n. 9), 214-21.
  • 24
    • 85038741020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The very fact that we must argue that Socrates is serious (as, for example, Brickhouse and Smith do) shows that there is something additional going on here; no one ever needs to argue that Aristotle is serious. See Vasiliou (n. 2), §1.
    • The very fact that we must argue that Socrates is serious (as, for example, Brickhouse and Smith do) shows that there is something additional going on here; no one ever needs to argue that Aristotle is serious. See Vasiliou (n. 2), §1.
  • 25
    • 85038749740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, not necessarily successfully. Socrates' conversations often apparently fail to move their interlocutors. Nevertheless, had Socrates not resorted to conditional irony, we may plausibly suppose that the conversations themselves would have been impossible in many instances
    • Of course, not necessarily successfully. Socrates' conversations often apparently fail to move their interlocutors. Nevertheless, had Socrates not resorted to conditional irony, we may plausibly suppose that the conversations themselves would have been impossible in many instances.
  • 26
    • 0041012919 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • Without looking at irony closely, if at all, many scholars have discussed the reasons why Socrates says what he does in the Apology and Crito. Most now agree that his ethical beliefs substantially commit him to speaking and acting in the ways he does. See, for example, R. Kraut, Socrates and the State (Princeton, 1984);
    • (1984) Socrates and the State
    • Kraut, R.1
  • 27
    • 85038754045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brickhouse and Smith (n. 9);
    • Brickhouse and Smith (n. 9);
  • 29
    • 70450081708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Living freely as a slave of the law. Notes on why Sokrates lives in Athens
    • Copenhagen, argues that Socrates' ethical views make Athens the best place for him to lead a free, consistent, and yet law-abiding life
    • J. Ober, 'Living freely as a slave of the law. Notes on why Sokrates lives in Athens', in Polis and Politics (Copenhagen, 2000), argues that Socrates' ethical views make Athens the best place for him to lead a free, consistent, and yet law-abiding life.
    • (2000) Polis and Politics
    • Ober, J.1
  • 30
    • 85038752655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe this point to Josh Ober
    • I owe this point to Josh Ober.
  • 31
  • 32
    • 85038690093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Vasiliou (n. 13), §5.
    • See Vasiliou (n. 13), §5.
  • 33
    • 85038661965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The third case is Thrasymachus in Republic 1, which would require a separate treatment, and to which the rest of the Republic constitutes the response.
    • The third case is Thrasymachus in Republic 1, which would require a separate treatment, and to which the rest of the Republic constitutes the response.
  • 34
    • 85038707347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Vasiliou (n. 15), §2. 0.
    • See Vasiliou (n. 15), §2. 0.
  • 35
    • 84965969977 scopus 로고
    • Socrates on desire for the good and the involuntariness of wrongdoing: Gorgias 466a-468e
    • See esp. K. McTighe, 'Socrates on desire for the good and the involuntariness of wrongdoing: Gorgias 466a-468e', Phronesis 29 (1984), 193-236
    • (1984) Phronesis , vol.29 , pp. 193-236
    • McTighe, K.1
  • 36
    • 60950541810 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • reprinted in H. Benson (ed. ), Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates (Oxford, 1992), 263-97. Detailing the logical errors in the argument, McTighe maintains a minority view that Socrates does not truly endorse the conclusion, but argues with Polus simply 'destructively', treating him as a hostile witness. Against McTighe (and others), Vlastos (n. 1), ch. 8 and additional note 8. 4, argues that Socrates never 'cheats' - that is, he never knowingly uses false premises or draws fallacious inferences when he is engaged in serious argument. Therefore, Socrates (and Plato, presumably) endorse the argument and are ignorant of any fallacies that may be present. In 'Disputing Socratic principles' (n. 15) I argue that Socrates' engagement with Polus is indeed 'constructive', but not in the way Vlastos thinks.
    • (1992) Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates , pp. 263-297
    • Benson, H.1
  • 37
    • 85038746633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Following Burnet in bracketing tontou prosthen at 467b4.
    • Following Burnet in bracketing tontou prosthen at 467b4.
  • 38
    • 85038741845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument has an advantage over the previous one in that no one doubts that Socrates believes this. If one thinks with McTighe (n. 26) that Socrates does not believe that one can do what one sees fit without doing what one wants, then his earlier enticement of Polus cannot be reverse irony
    • This argument has an advantage over the previous one in that no one doubts that Socrates believes this. If one thinks with McTighe (n. 26) that Socrates does not believe that one can do what one sees fit without doing what one wants, then his earlier enticement of Polus cannot be reverse irony.
  • 39
    • 85038705469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the nature and validity of this argument, see Vasiliou (n. 15), esp. §§3. 0-3. 1.
    • On the nature and validity of this argument, see Vasiliou (n. 15), esp. §§3. 0-3. 1.
  • 40
    • 0041173034 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, 154ff
    • For different interpretations, see T. Irwin, Plato: Gorgias (Oxford, 1979), 154ff. ;
    • (1979) Plato: Gorgias
    • Irwin, T.1
  • 41
    • 34248538778 scopus 로고
    • Drama and dialectic in Plato's Gorgias'
    • C. Kahn, 'Drama and dialectic in Plato's Gorgias', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 1 (1983), 75-121;
    • (1983) Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 75-121
    • Kahn, C.1
  • 43
    • 26244460160 scopus 로고
    • London
    • G. Santas, Socrates (London, 1979), 233-46;
    • (1979) Socrates , pp. 233-246
    • Santas, G.1
  • 45
    • 85038764051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vlastos n. 1, ch. 8, esp. 139-48
    • Vlastos (n. 1), ch. 8, esp. 139-48.
  • 46
    • 85038673605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are Chairephon's only lines in the Gorgias other than the first two Stephanus pages.
    • These are Chairephon's only lines in the Gorgias other than the first two Stephanus pages.
  • 47
    • 85038759124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ober (n. 10), ch. 4; for a contrasting view, see Nehamas (n. 1), esp. ch. 6.
    • See Ober (n. 10), ch. 4; for a contrasting view, see Nehamas (n. 1), esp. ch. 6.
  • 48
    • 85038671910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Alexander Nehamas for discussion about irony and Josh Ober for comments on an earlier version of this paper. In addition, I am especially grateful to the anonymous referee for helpful criticisms and suggestions
    • I thank Alexander Nehamas for discussion about irony and Josh Ober for comments on an earlier version of this paper. In addition, I am especially grateful to the anonymous referee for helpful criticisms and suggestions.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.