메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 1, 2000, Pages 29-44

Can humanity learn to become civilized? The crisis of science without civilization

(1)  Maxwell, Nicholas a  

a NONE   (United Kingdom)

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33845481088     PISSN: 02643758     EISSN: 14685930     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1468-5930.00138     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (28)

References (54)
  • 1
    • 84928195910 scopus 로고
    • St. Albans, Triad/Panther Books
    • A. Huxley (1980) The Human Situation (St. Albans, Triad/Panther Books), pp. 21-22.
    • (1980) The Human Situation , pp. 21-22
    • Huxley, A.1
  • 3
    • 0039409633 scopus 로고
    • The best overall account of the Enlightenment that I know of is still, London, Wildwood House
    • The best overall account of the Enlightenment that I know of is still: P. Gay (1973) The Enlightenment: An interpretation (London, Wildwood House).
    • (1973) The Enlightenment: An Interpretatio
    • Gay, P.1
  • 7
    • 0003849084 scopus 로고
    • London, Hogarth Press
    • I. Berlin (1980) Against the Current (London, Hogarth Press), pp. 1-24.
    • (1980) Against the Current , pp. 1-24
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 10
    • 0004077754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences
    • P. Gross et al. (1996), (Eds.) The Flight from Science and Reason (New York, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences);
    • (1996) The Flight from Science and Reason
    • Gross, P.1
  • 12
    • 4744356063 scopus 로고
    • The philosophes of the Enlightenment tended to assume that the triumph of Newtonian science over Cartesian science meant also the triumph of Newtonian inductivist methodology over Cartesian rationalism. They tended to espouse the extreme empiricism of Bacon and Locke, rejecting the rationalism of Descartes. But it is perhaps oversimplistic to interpret all the philosophes as upholding one or other version of standard empiricism. Kant hardly fits into such a picture. More to the point, d’Alembert asserted that “The universe, if we may be permitted to say so, would only be one fact and one great truth for whoever knew how to embrace it from a single point of view”, New York, Bobbs-Merrill, (originally published in 1751). This is perhaps compatible with, but hardly conforms to the spirit of standard empiricism
    • The philosophes of the Enlightenment tended to assume that the triumph of Newtonian science over Cartesian science meant also the triumph of Newtonian inductivist methodology over Cartesian rationalism. They tended to espouse the extreme empiricism of Bacon and Locke, rejecting the rationalism of Descartes. But it is perhaps oversimplistic to interpret all the philosophes as upholding one or other version of standard empiricism. Kant hardly fits into such a picture. More to the point, d’Alembert asserted that “The universe, if we may be permitted to say so, would only be one fact and one great truth for whoever knew how to embrace it from a single point of view”; J. d’Alembert (1963) Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot (New York, Bobbs-Merrill), p. 29, (originally published in 1751). This is perhaps compatible with, but hardly conforms to the spirit of standard empiricism.
    • (1963) Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot , pp. 29
    • D’Alembert, J.1
  • 16
    • 0003580846 scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that Newton upheld a conception of natural philosophy (natural science) that is, in important respects, more sophisticated than standard empiricism, presupposed by so many twentieth century scientists and philosophers of science. Newton formulates three of his four rules of reasoning in such a way that it is clear that these rules make assumptions about the nature of the universe. Thus rule 1 asserts: “We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.” And Newton adds: “To this purpose the philosophers say that nature does nothing in vain, and more is in vain when less will serve; for Nature is pleased with simplicity, and affects not the pomp of superfluous causes.”, Berkeley, University of California Press, Newton understood that persistently preferring simple theories means that Nature herself is being persistently assumed to be simple (which violates standard empiricism)
    • It is worth noting that Newton upheld a conception of natural philosophy (natural science) that is, in important respects, more sophisticated than standard empiricism, presupposed by so many twentieth century scientists and philosophers of science. Newton formulates three of his four rules of reasoning in such a way that it is clear that these rules make assumptions about the nature of the universe. Thus rule 1 asserts: “We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.” And Newton adds: “To this purpose the philosophers say that nature does nothing in vain, and more is in vain when less will serve; for Nature is pleased with simplicity, and affects not the pomp of superfluous causes.” See I. Newton (1962) Principia (Berkeley, University of California Press), vol. 2, p. 398. Newton understood that persistently preferring simple theories means that Nature herself is being persistently assumed to be simple (which violates standard empiricism).
    • (1962) Principia , vol.2 , pp. 398
    • Newton, I.1
  • 17
    • 85037721640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a much more detailed refutation of standard empiricism, bare and dressed, Berkeley, University of California Press
    • For a much more detailed refutation of standard empiricism, bare and dressed, see Maxwell, Principia (Berkeley, University of California Press)., chs. 1-2.
    • Principia , pp. 1-2
    • Maxwell1
  • 18
    • 85037721640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a much more detailed exposition and defence of aim-oriented empiricism, and an account of the way aim-oriented empiricism solves long-standing problems in the philosophy of science such as problems of simplicity, induction and verisimilitude, Berkeley, University of California Press
    • For a much more detailed exposition and defence of aim-oriented empiricism, and an account of the way aim-oriented empiricism solves long-standing problems in the philosophy of science such as problems of simplicity, induction and verisimilitude, see Maxwell, Principia (Berkeley, University of California Press)., chs. 1 and 3-6.
    • Principia , pp. 3-6
    • Maxwell1
  • 19
    • 85037723825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley, University of California Press
    • Popper Principia (Berkeley, University of California Press)., chs. 1 and 3-6.
    • Principia , pp. 3-6
    • Popper1
  • 21
    • 85037717786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inter-subjective testing is merely a very important aspect of the more general idea of inter-subjective criticism, or in other words, of the idea of mutual rational control by critical discussion
    • “inter-subjective testing is merely a very important aspect of the more general idea of inter-subjective criticism, or in other words, of the idea of mutual rational control by critical discussion”, Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery., p. 44, n *1.
    • The Logic of Scientific Discovery , Issue.1 , pp. 44
    • Popper1
  • 22
    • 0003432081 scopus 로고
    • London, Routledge and Kegan Paul
    • K. Popper (1963) Conjectures and Refutations (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul), pp. 193-200;
    • (1963) Conjectures and Refutations , pp. 193-200
    • Popper, K.1
  • 23
    • 0003640541 scopus 로고
    • Glasgow, Fontana
    • K. Popper (1976) Unended Quest (Glasgow, Fontana), pp. 115-6;
    • (1976) Unended Quest , pp. 115-116
    • Popper, K.1
  • 24
    • 0003696915 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • K. Popper (1972) Objective Knowledge (Oxford, Oxford University Press), p. 119-243.
    • (1972) Objective Knowledge , pp. 119-243
    • Popper, K.1
  • 25
    • 0005451589 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Blackwell), especially chs. 5 and 8
    • N. Maxwell (1984) From Knowledge to Wisdom (Oxford, Blackwell), especially chs. 5 and 8.
    • (1984) From Knowledge to Wisdom
    • Maxwell, N.1
  • 27
    • 85037737557 scopus 로고
    • What’s Wrong With Science? Towards a people’s rational science of delight and compassion (Frome, Bran’s Head Books)
    • Maxwell, N.: (1976) What's Wrong With Science? Towards a people's rational science of delight and compassion (Frome, Bran's Head Books) pp. 9 + 260; (1980) Science, reason, knowledge and wisdom: a critique of specialism, Inquiry, 23, pp. 19-81; (1984) From knowledge to wisdom: guiding choices in scientific research, Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society, 4, pp. 316-34; (1985) From knowledge to wisdom: the need for an intellectual revolution, The Fate of the Enlightenment: reply to Kekes, Inquiry, 29, pp. 79-82; (1987) Wanted: a new way of thinking, New Scientist, 14 May, p. 63; (1991) How can we build a better world?: in J. Mittelstrass (Ed.) Einheit der Wissenschaften: Internationales Kolloquium der Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, 25-27 June 1990 (Berlin, Walter de Gruyter), pp. 388-427; (1992) What kind of inquiry can best help us create a good world?, Science, Technology and Human Values, 17, pp. 205-27; (1992) What the task of creating civilization has to learn from the success of modern science: towards a new enlightenment, Reflections on Higher Education, 4, pp. 47-69; (1993) Can academic inquiry help humanity become civilized?, Philosophy Today, 13, May, pp. 1-3; (1997) Science and the environment: a new enlightenment, Science and Public Affairs, Spring, pp. 50-56
    • See also Maxwell, N.: (1976) What’s Wrong With Science? Towards a people’s rational science of delight and compassion (Frome, Bran’s Head Books), pp. 9 + 260; (1980) Science, reason, knowledge and wisdom: a critique of specialism, Inquiry, 23, pp. 19-81; (1984) From knowledge to wisdom: guiding choices in scientific research, Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society, 4, pp. 316-34; (1985) From knowledge to wisdom: the need for an intellectual revolution, Science, Technology and Society Newsletter, 21, pp. 55-63;(1986) The Fate of the Enlightenment: reply to Kekes, Inquiry, 29, pp. 79-82; (1987) Wanted: a new way of thinking, New Scientist, 14 May, p. 63; (1991) How can we build a better world?: in J. Mittelstrass (Ed.) Einheit der Wissenschaften: Internationales Kolloquium der Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, 25-27 June 1990 (Berlin, Walter de Gruyter), pp. 388-427; (1992) What kind of inquiry can best help us create a good world?, Science, Technology and Human Values, 17, pp. 205-27; (1992) What the task of creating civilization has to learn from the success of modern science: towards a new enlightenment, Reflections on Higher Education, 4, pp. 47-69; (1993) Can academic inquiry help humanity become civilized?, Philosophy Today, 13, May, pp. 1-3; (1997) Science and the environment: a new enlightenment, Science and Public Affairs, Spring, pp. 50-56.
    • (1976) Science, Technology and Society Newsletter , vol.21 , pp. 55-63
    • Maxwell, N.1
  • 34
  • 35
    • 0004078652 scopus 로고
    • London, Routledge and Kegan Paul
    • K. Popper (1974) The Poverty of Historicism (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul), pp. 64-92.
    • (1974) The Poverty of Historicism , pp. 64-92
    • Popper, K.1
  • 36
    • 85037717974 scopus 로고
    • London, Routledge and Kegan Paul
    • Maxwell (1984) The Poverty of Historicism (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul)., pp. 189-198.
    • (1984) The Poverty of Historicism , pp. 189-198
    • Maxwell1
  • 43
    • 0004187130 scopus 로고
    • (London, Verso) and (1987) Farewell to Reason (London, Verso)
    • P. Feyerabend (1978) Against Method (London, Verso) and (1987) Farewell to Reason (London, Verso);
    • (1978) Against Method
    • Feyerabend, P.1
  • 45
    • 85037742777 scopus 로고
    • London, Picador), pp. 85-91 and pp. 117-118, for further discussion of this issue
    • Maxwell (1984) Understanding the Present: Science and the Soul of Modern Man (London, Picador)., pp. 63-4, pp. 85-91 and pp. 117-118, for further discussion of this issue.
    • (1984) Understanding the Present: Science and the Soul of Modern Man , pp. 63-64
    • Maxwell1
  • 46
    • 70350282923 scopus 로고
    • (Frome, Bran’s Head Books), especially chs. 1 and 8-10
    • N. Maxwell (1976) What’s Wrong With Science? (Frome, Bran’s Head Books), especially chs. 1 and 8-10.
    • (1976) What’s Wrong with Science?
    • Maxwell, N.1
  • 48
    • 0001817653 scopus 로고
    • Relativism, rationalism and the sociology of knowledge
    • M. Hollis and S. Lukes (Eds.), Oxford, Blackwell
    • B. Barnes and D. Bloor (1981) Relativism, rationalism and the sociology of knowledge: in M. Hollis and S. Lukes (Eds.) Rationality and Relativism (Oxford, Blackwell), pp. 21-47;
    • (1981) Rationality and Relativism , pp. 21-47
    • Barnes, B.1    Bloor, D.2
  • 49
    • 84936823853 scopus 로고
    • Milton Keynes, Open University Press
    • B. Latour (1987) Science in Action (Milton Keynes, Open University Press);
    • (1987) Science in Action
    • Latour, B.1
  • 50
    • 85037737212 scopus 로고
    • Milton Keynes, Open University Pressand (1987) These authors might protest that they do not deny scientific knowledge, method, progress or rationality as such, but deny, merely, that the sociology of knowledge can legitimately appeal to such things, or deny extravagant claims made on behalf of these things. See, however, the sparkling criticism by Sokal and Bricmont, ch. 4
    • Feyerabend (1978) Science in Action (Milton Keynes, Open University Press). and (1987) These authors might protest that they do not deny scientific knowledge, method, progress or rationality as such, but deny, merely, that the sociology of knowledge can legitimately appeal to such things, or deny extravagant claims made on behalf of these things. See, however, the sparkling criticism by Sokal and Bricmont, ch. 4.
    • (1978) Science in Action
    • Feyerabend1
  • 53
    • 0346265539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Public Affairs, Spring
    • J. Durant (1997) Beyond the scope of science, Science and Public Affairs, Spring, pp. 56–57.
    • (1997) Beyond the Scope of Science , pp. 56-57
    • Durant, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.