메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 29, Issue , 2004, Pages 173-190

Acceptance and deciding to believe

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33845290597     PISSN: 10538364     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jpr_2004_17     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (27)

References (45)
  • 2
    • 0040414265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agency and Mental Action
    • See Alfred R. Mele, "Agency and Mental Action," Philosophical Perspectives 11 (1997): 231-249
    • (1997) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.11 , pp. 231-249
    • Mele, A.R.1
  • 3
    • 2342495489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deciding to Act
    • and "Deciding to Act," Philosophical Studies 100 (2000): 81-108 for accounts of mental action from a causalist perspective
    • (2000) Philosophical Studies , vol.100 , pp. 81
  • 4
    • 0942269519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • For a non-causalist, volitionist theory of mental action see Hugh McCann, The Works of Agency: On Human Action, Will, and Freedom (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1998), especially chap. 8
    • (1998) The Works of Agency: On Human Action, Will, and Freedom
    • McCann1
  • 5
    • 1142263139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical Reasoning and Acceptance in a Context
    • 1992
    • I am here indebted to Michael Bratman's discussion of the differences in his, "Practical Reasoning and Acceptance in a Context," Mind 101 (1992): 1-15, especially 2-9
    • Mind , vol.101 , pp. 1-15
  • 7
    • 85000203414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Belief versus Acceptance
    • and Raimo Tuomela, "Belief versus Acceptance," Philosophical Explorations 3 (2000): 122-137. "Acceptance" as I am using the term comes closest to what Engel and Tuomela call "pragmatic acceptance."
    • (2000) Philosophical Explorations , vol.3 , pp. 122-137
    • Tuomela, R.1
  • 9
    • 33645144015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ethics of Belief: Off the Wrong Track
    • especially 268-270
    • Like Wedgewood, he emphasizes the normativity of the content of beliefs. Velleman, however, takes belief to be a species of acceptance, one that is truth-directed. I believe this feature of his account is incompatible with what I argue for in this essay. See also Jonathan E. Adler, "The Ethics of Belief: Off the Wrong Track," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23 (1999): 267-285, especially 268-270
    • (1999) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.23 , pp. 267-285
    • Adler, J.E.1
  • 10
    • 0010110035 scopus 로고
    • Deciding to Believe, in Williams
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, "Deciding to Believe," in Williams, Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), 136-151, especially 137
    • (1973) Problems of the Self , pp. 136-151
    • Williams, B.1
  • 11
    • 0345837156 scopus 로고
    • Truth, Reason, and the Regulation of Belief
    • 71-93
    • Peter Railton, "Truth, Reason, and the Regulation of Belief," Philosophical Issues 5 (1994): 71-93, 74
    • (1994) Philosophical Issues , vol.5 , pp. 74
    • Railton, P.1
  • 12
    • 0004123974 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See William G. Lycan, Judgement and Justification (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 136-137, for similar reasons in defense of the claim that to believe that p is to believe that p is true
    • (1988) Judgement and Justification , pp. 136-137
    • Lycan, W.G.1
  • 13
    • 0039916493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical Reasons for Belief?
    • See Eddy M. Zemach, "Practical Reasons for Belief?" Nous 31 (1997): 525-527, for a critical treatment of the role of practical reasons in epistemic justification
    • (1997) Nous , vol.31 , pp. 525-527
    • Zemach, E.M.1
  • 14
    • 52549085225 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic Reasons for Belief
    • ed. J. Jordan Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield
    • See also Richard Foley, "Pragmatic Reasons for Belief," in Gambling on God: Essays on Pascal's Wager, ed. J. Jordan (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 1994), 31-46, for an argument for affording pragmatic reasons an occasional role as relevant to the rationality of belief
    • (1994) Gambling on God: Essays on Pascal's Wager , pp. 31-46
    • Foley, R.1
  • 15
    • 61049368349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic Arguments and Belief
    • See Jeff Jordan, "Pragmatic Arguments and Belief," American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1996): 409-120, for a case for the rational and moral permissibility of forming beliefs based on pragmatic reasons without adequate evidence
    • (1996) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.33 , pp. 409-120
    • Jordan, J.1
  • 16
    • 79958593975 scopus 로고
    • trans. H. Levi, ed. A. Levi (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Blaise Pascal, Pensees and Other Writings, trans. H. Levi, ed. A. Levi (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 155-156
    • (1995) Pensees and Other Writings , pp. 155-156
    • Pascal, B.1
  • 19
    • 26444580783 scopus 로고
    • Belief and Acceptance
    • 367-389
    • L. Jonathan Cohen, "Belief and Acceptance" Mind 98 (1989): 367-389, 368
    • (1989) Mind , vol.98 , pp. 368
    • Jonathan Cohen, L.1
  • 20
    • 85016086841 scopus 로고
    • Bogdan, ed, Belief: Form, Content, and Function Oxford: Clarendon
    • This is an incomplete and simplistic description of what I take a belief to be. For a very attractive account of belief, but one I find problematic in some of its details, see Radu J. Bogdan, "The Manufacture of Belief," in Bogdan, ed., Belief: Form, Content, and Function (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986), 149-184
    • (1986) The Manufacture of Belief , pp. 149-184
    • Bogdan, R.J.1
  • 21
    • 33746158374 scopus 로고
    • Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe
    • especially 424
    • Audi, "Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe," Nous 28 (1994): 419-434, especially 424
    • (1994) Nous , vol.28 , pp. 419-434
    • Audi1
  • 23
    • 0004216998 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell especially 47
    • I owe this analogy to John Heil, "Belief," in A Companion to Epistemology, ed. J. Dancy and E. Sosa (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), 45-48, especially 47
    • (1992) A Companion to Epistemology , pp. 45-48
    • Dancy, J.1    Sosa, E.2
  • 24
    • 0038881250 scopus 로고
    • Events as Property Exemplifications
    • ed. M. Brand and D. Walton Dordrecht: D. Reidel
    • See Jaegwon Kim, "Events as Property Exemplifications." in Action Theory, ed. M. Brand and D. Walton (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976), 159-177
    • (1976) Action Theory , pp. 159-177
    • Kim, J.1
  • 25
    • 0003496589 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Ginet, On Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 13
    • (1990) On Action , pp. 13
    • Ginet1
  • 26
    • 0040373496 scopus 로고
    • I like to think what I am offering is roughly in the spirit of Paul Grice's proposed method in "Method In Philosophical Psychology (From the Banal to the Bizarre)," Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48 (1975): 23-53
    • (1975) Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association , vol.48 , pp. 23-53
  • 27
    • 60949245891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Acceptance and Belief Revisited
    • ed, Dordrecht: Kluwer, especially 209
    • Keith Lehrer, "Acceptance and Belief Revisited," in Believing and Accepting, ed. Pascal Engel (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2000), 209-220, especially 209
    • (2000) Believing and Accepting , pp. 209-220
    • Lehrer, K.1
  • 28
    • 0012893323 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Harry Frankfurt, "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person," reprinted in Free Will, ed. Gary Watson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), 81-95, 83
    • (1982) Free Will , vol.81 , pp. 83
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 30
    • 0001691297 scopus 로고
    • Free Agency
    • and Gary Watson. "Free Agency," Journal of Philosophy 72 (1975): 205-220, among others
    • (1975) Journal of Philosophy , vol.72 , pp. 205-220
    • Watson, G.1
  • 32
    • 61949229574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Valuing and the Will
    • especially 258
    • Bratman, "Valuing and the Will," Philosophical Perspectives 14 (2000): 249-265, especially 258
    • (2000) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.14 , pp. 249-265
    • Bratman1
  • 35
    • 4243982254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Impact of Metacognitive Reflection on Cognitive Control
    • ed. G. Mazzoni and T. O. Nelson (London: Lawrence Erlbaum
    • See Cesare Cornoldi, "The Impact of Metacognitive Reflection on Cognitive Control," in, Metacognition and Cognitive Neuropsychology: Monitoring and Control Processes, ed. G. Mazzoni and T. O. Nelson (London: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1998), 139-159, especially 156
    • (1998) Metacognition and Cognitive Neuropsychology: Monitoring and Control Processes , pp. 139-159
    • Cornoldi, C.1
  • 36
    • 0028471543 scopus 로고
    • Mental Contamination and Mental Correction: Unwanted Influences on Judgments and Evaluations
    • especially 122
    • See Timothy D. Wilson and Nancy Brekke, "Mental Contamination and Mental Correction: Unwanted Influences on Judgments and Evaluations," Psychological Bulletin 116 (1994): 117-142, especially 122
    • (1994) Psychological Bulletin , vol.116 , pp. 117-142
    • Wilson, T.D.1    Brekke, N.2
  • 37
    • 79958625752 scopus 로고
    • Belief and Will
    • reprinted in, ed, New York: Harper & Row, especially 107-111
    • See also H. H. Price, "Belief and Will," reprinted in Philosophy of Mind, ed. Smart Hampshire (New York: Harper & Row, 1966), 91-116, especially 107-111
    • (1966) Philosophy of Mind , pp. 91-116
    • Price, H.H.1
  • 38
    • 85038544406 scopus 로고
    • You Can't Not Believe Everything You Read
    • Wilson and Brekke discuss the difficulty involved in controlling attitudes, including belief, by focusing on the case of avoiding and correcting what they call "mental contamination." These are "cases whereby a judgment, emotion, or behavior is biased by unconscious or uncontrollable mental processes" (118). See also Daniel T. Gilbert, Romin W. Tafarodi, and Patrick S. Malone, "You Can't Not Believe Everything You Read," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65 (1993): 221-233
    • (1993) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , vol.65 , pp. 221-233
    • Daniel T. Gilbert1    Romin W. Tafarodi2    and Patrick S. Malone3
  • 39
    • 0040271395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Protecting our Minds: The Role of Lay Beliefs
    • ed. V. Y. Yzerbyt, G. Lories, and B. DardenneLondon: Sage
    • Timothy D. Wilson, Daniel T. Gilbert, and Thalia P. Wheatley, "Protecting our Minds: The Role of Lay Beliefs," in Metacognition: Cognitive and Social Dimensions, ed. V. Y. Yzerbyt, G. Lories, and B. Dardenne(London: Sage, 1998), 171-201, are more optimistic than Wilson and Brekke about the possible control that may be exercised. But they echo the sentiments of others doing empirical work, despairing of agents exercising anything like direct voluntary control over belief
    • (1998) Metacognition: Cognitive and Social Dimensions , pp. 171-201
    • Wilson, T.D.1    Gilbert, D.T.2    Wheatley, T.P.3
  • 43
    • 38949120741 scopus 로고
    • Contra Reliabilism
    • 175-187
    • Ginet, "Contra Reliabilism," The Monist 68 (1985): 175-187, 183
    • (1985) The Monist , vol.68 , pp. 183
    • Ginet1
  • 44
    • 0040509318 scopus 로고
    • Epistemic Obligations
    • Insofar as Richard Feldman's theory of justification is a species of epistemic deontologism, his position would qualify as an alternative theory that takes epistemic obligations seriously in evaluating the beliefs of epistemic agents without requiring that agents ever exercise direct voluntary control over their beliefs. See his "Epistemic Obligations," Philosophical Perspectives 2 (1988): 235-256
    • (1988) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.2 , pp. 235-256


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.