메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 104, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 203-225

Moral dilemmas, collective responsibility, and moral progress

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33751574849     PISSN: 00318116     EISSN: 15730883     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1010357607895     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (17)

References (53)
  • 1
    • 0038592320 scopus 로고
    • trans. Mary J. Gregor Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • To fill this out, we could either insist that one side is always stronger, or we could stipulate that in cases of equality, our all-things-considered obligation is to pick one alternative and fulfill it. See Immanuel Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. Mary J. Gregor (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), pp. 16-25;
    • (1971) The Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals , pp. 16-25
    • Kant, I.1
  • 2
    • 0002140616 scopus 로고
    • Consistency in Rationalist Moral Systems
    • Alan Donagan, "Consistency in Rationalist Moral Systems," Journal of Philosophy (1984): 291-309;
    • (1984) Journal of Philosophy , pp. 291-309
    • Donagan, A.1
  • 3
    • 0005041658 scopus 로고
    • Moral Conflict and its Structure
    • and David Brink, "Moral Conflict and its Structure," Philosophical Review 103 (1994) 215-247,
    • (1994) Philosophical Review , vol.103 , pp. 215-247
    • Brink, D.1
  • 4
    • 52549117178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H. E. Mason, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • reprinted in H. E. Mason, ed., Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 102-126).
    • (1996) Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory , pp. 102-126
  • 5
    • 10944257187 scopus 로고
    • Against Moral Dilemmas
    • Earl Conee suggests this in his "Against Moral Dilemmas," Philosophical Review 90 (1982), pp. 87-97.
    • (1982) Philosophical Review , vol.90 , pp. 87-97
    • Conee, E.1
  • 6
    • 52549097677 scopus 로고
    • Reprinted in C. Gowans, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Reprinted in C. Gowans, ed., Moral Dilemmas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 239-249.
    • (1987) Moral Dilemmas , pp. 239-249
  • 7
    • 0010135797 scopus 로고
    • Moral Dilemmas and Consistency
    • Ruth Barcan Marcus, "Moral Dilemmas and Consistency," Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 121-36. Page numbers refer to the reprinting in Gowans, pp. 188-204.
    • (1980) Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , pp. 121-136
    • Marcus, R.B.1
  • 8
    • 0347629977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More about Moral Dilemmas
    • H. E. Mason, ed., New York: Oxford University Press
    • Ruth Barcan Marcus, "More about Moral Dilemmas," in H. E. Mason, ed., Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory
    • Marcus, R.B.1
  • 12
    • 52549092044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I call it the stringency objection because it suggests that if dilemmas are real, then the agent seems blamed for things beyond his control, and thus the moral requirements involved are too strict, or "stringent."
  • 13
    • 52549083927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at a colloquium at the University of California, Irvine January 14
    • This objection is raised in several of the papers cited in the next section, especially by Philippa Foot. A form of it was also raised by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, in "A Moral Argument Against Moral Dilemmas," at a colloquium at the University of California, Irvine (January 14, 2000). The formulation given by Sayre-McCord focused specifically on the unfairness of any code that demands the impossible. It then relied on this unfairness as grounds for rejecting a code that allows dilemmas in favor of a modified version of that code that didn't generate dilemmas but otherwise (so far as possible) contained the other moral features of the code.
    • (2000) A Moral Argument Against Moral Dilemmas
    • Sayre-McCord, G.1
  • 14
    • 0010144705 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Consistency
    • reprinted in Gowans
    • Bernard Williams, "Ethical Consistency," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, XXIX (1965), reprinted in Gowans, pp. 115-137, page numbers refer to the reprinting in Gowans.
    • (1965) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.29 , pp. 115-137
    • Williams, B.1
  • 15
    • 0346400990 scopus 로고
    • Moral Realism and Moral Dilemma
    • See especially pp. 123-124. Foot's views are explained in her two papers, "Moral Realism and Moral Dilemma," Journal of Philosophy LXXX (1983), pp. 379-398,
    • (1983) Journal of Philosophy , vol.80 , pp. 379-398
    • Foot1
  • 16
    • 52549105463 scopus 로고
    • Moral Dilemmas Revisited
    • Sinott-Armstrong, Raffman, and Asher, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • and "Moral Dilemmas Revisited" in Sinott-Armstrong, Raffman, and Asher, eds., Modality, Morality, and Belief: Essays in Honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 117-128. Foot and Williams use "remainder" for what I am calling the residue.
    • (1995) Modality, Morality, and Belief: Essays in Honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus , pp. 117-128
  • 19
    • 52549114058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Williams, "Ethical Consistency," p. 125. This is a simplification of Williams's views. He does end by considering the possibility that while the feelings are irrational, it may sometimes be best to be irrational.
    • Ethical Consistency , pp. 125
    • Williams1
  • 24
    • 52549122664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that on Marcus's view, it is not necessary that there should be any punishment or public sanctions, what matters is that the weaker obligation has not fallen away.
  • 29
    • 16644379310 scopus 로고
    • Moral Dilemmas and Guilt
    • These worries are suggested by Greenspan in her "Moral Dilemmas and Guilt," Philosophical Studies 43 (1983): 117-125.
    • (1983) Philosophical Studies , vol.43 , pp. 117-125
    • Greenspan1
  • 30
    • 16644392635 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • She addresses them later, in her book, Practical Guilt (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), and to some extent in "Perspectival Guilt." Because the moral I want to draw diverges from that later discussion, I will explain the issues independently of her proposed resolution. There is some overlap in our discussion; where appropriate I will make note of it.
    • (1995) Practical Guilt
  • 31
    • 0004233558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York, Bantam
    • William Styron, Sophie's Choice (New York, Bantam, 1979). The scene is described on pages 480-484.
    • (1979) Sophie's Choice
    • Styron, W.1
  • 38
    • 52549116395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Greenspan discusses collective action in her later "Perspectival Guilt," and in Practical Guilt. One virtue of the perspectival approach to guilt, she says, is that an individual could be part of a group that is guilty, without being personally blamed, if he did nothing wrong. That person could clear himself by focusing on the right perceptual slices (p. 135). She also suggests a distinction between holding someone guilty in a backward-looking sense and holding them responsible in a forward-looking sense (p. 137). Her comments are in the spirit of the analysis I am suggesting here.
  • 40
    • 52549110524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thanks to Patricia Greenspan for bringing these questions to my attention.
  • 41
    • 52549119343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One other question might be whether it is true that a feeling of guilt would motivate us in the way described here. Perhaps it would have an opposite effect. For example, the guilt might function the way shame sometimes does, when it causes us to go on as before rather than face unpleasant realities. I don't know, as a matter of psychology, to what extent this might be the case, and the problem raises difficult questions. It seems to me that in a wide enough range of cases, its plausible that the motivation might work roughly the way I've suggested. The relevance of exceptions to this raises complex issues about the proper relationship between real emotional life and moral theory, issues I can't address here. I do discuss some related things in the last two paragraphs of this section. For more on emotions and morality, see Patricia Greenspan, Practical Guilt.
  • 42
    • 52549114058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When he considers whether the pain is the real motivator. See the beginning of section II, and see Williams, "Ethical Consistency," page 125. He argues that the reason the pain isn't the true motivator is that the residue arises via a "moral thought," but doesn't consider what happens if there is no bad outcome at all.
    • Ethical Consistency , pp. 125
    • Williams1
  • 43
    • 52549111225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is an oversimplification of what is a subtle and complex problem, but I think the basic idea can be captured easily in an example. For those of us who think the right of women to vote has a moral component, we might have intuitions that fighting against that right now is reprehensible, while feeling simultaneously that fighting against it years ago is a much milder moral transgression, if it is one at all.
  • 44
    • 52549126113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Greenspan hints at something like this in her discussion of the appropriateness of guilt. See note 30, above.
  • 45
    • 52549120881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Again, thanks to Patricia Greenspan for raising this.
  • 47
    • 52549131169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Moral Progress' from Philosophy to Technology
    • Donald Hodges, "'Moral Progress' From Philosophy to Technology," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 28, pp. 430-436;
    • Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.28 , pp. 430-436
    • Hodges, D.1
  • 48
    • 85048902651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Progress and Social Theory
    • Leslie Sklair, "Moral Progress and Social Theory," Ethics 79, pp. 239-234;
    • Ethics , vol.79 , pp. 239-1234
    • Sklair, L.1
  • 49
    • 85044810369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Progress Revisited
    • and Leslie Sklair, "Moral Progress Revisited," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 31, pp. 433-439. These works aren't entirely limited to the Marx/Hegel approach, but to the extent that they depart from it, the questions are more abstract than those considered here.
    • Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.31 , pp. 433-439
    • Sklair, L.1
  • 50
    • 84925907005 scopus 로고
    • Moral Progress
    • Ruth Macklin, "Moral Progress," Ethics 87 (1977): 370-382.
    • (1977) Ethics , vol.87 , pp. 370-382
    • Macklin, R.1
  • 51
    • 52549101835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Macklin, "Moral Progress," pp. 371-372. This is only a part of Macklin's complete definition.
    • Moral Progress , pp. 371-372
    • Macklin1
  • 53
    • 52549094402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am not claiming that abortion is an analogous case. Merely that it would be for someone who already conceived of abortion as a moral dilemma.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.