-
1
-
-
0001217243
-
Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error
-
See for example
-
See for example Gilbert Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1999), pp. 315-332;
-
(1999)
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
, vol.99
, pp. 315-332
-
-
Harman, G.1
-
2
-
-
3543076485
-
The nonexistence of character traits
-
"The Nonexistence of Character Traits," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2000), pp. 223-226;
-
(2000)
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
, vol.100
, pp. 223-226
-
-
-
3
-
-
0012521516
-
Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics
-
John Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics," Noûs 32 (1998), pp. 504-530;
-
(1998)
Noûs
, vol.32
, pp. 504-530
-
-
Doris, J.1
-
5
-
-
0007269080
-
Can philosophical accounts of altruism accommodate experimental data on helping behavior?
-
and
-
and John Campbell, "Can Philosophical Accounts of Altruism Accommodate Experimental Data on Helping Behavior?" Australasian Journal of Philosophy 11 (1999), pp. 26-45.
-
(1999)
Australasian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.11
, pp. 26-45
-
-
Campbell, J.1
-
6
-
-
0010840474
-
-
Other philosophers who seem to show some sympathy towards this objection include Simon Blackburn (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
-
Other philosophers who seem to show some sympathy towards this objection include Simon Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), p. 36,
-
(1998)
Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning
, pp. 36
-
-
-
7
-
-
4544246386
-
-
and (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
and Thomas Hurka, Virtue, Vice, and Value (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 44.
-
Virtue, Vice, and Value
, pp. 44
-
-
Hurka, T.1
-
8
-
-
0004256839
-
-
In the field of social psychology, personality-based explanations have been criticized by, among others (New York: John Wiley and Sons)
-
In the field of social psychology, personality-based explanations have been criticized by, among others, W. Mischel, Personality and Assessment (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1968);
-
(1968)
Personality and Assessment
-
-
Mischel, W.1
-
9
-
-
0000517665
-
Beyond déjà vu in the search for cross-situational consistency
-
W. Mischel and P. Peake, "Beyond Déjà Vu in the Search for Cross-Situational Consistency," Psychological Review 89 (1982), pp. 730-755,
-
(1982)
Psychological Review
, vol.89
, pp. 730-755
-
-
Mischel, W.1
Peake, P.2
-
11
-
-
0003413361
-
-
For some important preliminary responses, see (Cambridge: Harvard University Press)
-
For some important preliminary responses, see Owen Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991);
-
(1991)
Varieties of Moral Personality
-
-
Flanagan, O.1
-
12
-
-
59849112511
-
Character traits, virtues, and vices: Are there none?
-
Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center
-
Michael Depaul, "Character Traits, Virtues, and Vices: Are There None?" Proceedings of the World Congress of Philosophy, Volume 1 (Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center, 1999), pp. 141-157;
-
(1999)
Proceedings of the World Congress of Philosophy
, vol.1
, pp. 141-157
-
-
Depaul, M.1
-
13
-
-
0001215490
-
Virtue ethics and situationist personality psychology
-
Maria Merritt, "Virtue Ethics and Situationist Personality Psychology," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3 (2000), pp. 365-383;
-
(2000)
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice
, vol.3
, pp. 365-383
-
-
Merritt, M.1
-
14
-
-
3543064746
-
A response to harman: Virtue ethics and character traits
-
Nafsika Athanassoulis, "A Response to Harman: Virtue Ethics and Character Traits," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2001), pp. 215-222.
-
(2001)
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
, vol.100
, pp. 215-222
-
-
Athanassoulis, N.1
-
15
-
-
3543089307
-
Errors about errors: Virtue theory and trait attribution
-
Recently Gopal Sreenivasan has developed a more sustained response to Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology", and Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics." He mentions two reservations he has with their approach, but only has space to defend the first. In what follows, I take up the task of developing something like his second reservation concerning the "scope of a theory of virtue." Thus this paper can be viewed as complementing Sreenivasan's response, although he should in no way be construed as endorsing any of what follows
-
Recently Gopal Sreenivasan ["Errors about Errors: Virtue Theory and Trait Attribution," Mind 111 (2002), pp. 47-68] has developed a more sustained response to Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology", and Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics." He mentions two reservations he has with their approach, but only has space to defend the first. In what follows, I take up the task of developing something like his second reservation concerning the "scope of a theory of virtue." Thus this paper can be viewed as complementing Sreenivasan's response, although he should in no way be construed as endorsing any of what follows.
-
(2002)
Mind
, vol.111
, pp. 47-68
-
-
-
16
-
-
4544334690
-
-
See in particular and "The Nonexistence of Character Traits." The presentation of Harman's view is based on the earlier article. It is important to note that while virtue ethics is a type of normative theory, it like many such theories is also committed to the truth of certain descriptive claims. Similarly, one might think that some consequentialists are committed to the existence of states of affairs, and some deontologists to the existence of faculties of practical reason. In the case of virtue ethics, what exactly the relevant descriptive commitments are will be considered at some length in sections II and V
-
See in particular Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology and The Nonexistence of Character Traits." The presentation of Harman's view is based on the earlier article. It is important to note that while virtue ethics is a type of normative theory, it like many such theories is also committed to the truth of certain descriptive claims. Similarly, one might think that some consequentialists are committed to the existence of states of affairs, and some deontologists to the existence of faculties of practical reason. In the case of virtue ethics, what exactly the relevant descriptive commitments are will be considered at some length in sections II and V.
-
Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology
-
-
Harman1
-
19
-
-
4544334690
-
-
Thus Harman wants to exclude schizophrenia, mania, depression, shyness, and sadness from being character traits , but it is not at all clear that he is justified in doing so based on these standards alone. Nor do his criteria seem able to exclude anorexia, bulimia, talkativeness, smoking, alcoholism, drug addiction, and many other "long-term stable dispositions to act in distinctive ways."
-
Thus Harman wants to exclude schizophrenia, mania, depression, shyness, and sadness from being character traits (Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology," p. 316), but it is not at all clear that he is justified in doing so based on these standards alone. Nor do his criteria seem able to exclude anorexia, bulimia, talkativeness, smoking, alcoholism, drug addiction, and many other "long-term stable dispositions to act in distinctive ways."
-
Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology
, pp. 316
-
-
Harman1
-
21
-
-
34547966737
-
Behavioral study of obedience
-
For further details about this experiment, see
-
For further details about this experiment, see Stanley Milgram, "Behavioral Study of Obedience," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 67 (1963), pp. 371-378,
-
(1963)
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology
, vol.67
, pp. 371-378
-
-
Milgram, S.1
-
22
-
-
84887357498
-
-
and the helpful discussion in Flanagan
-
and the helpful discussion in Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality, pp. 293-300
-
Varieties of Moral Personality
, pp. 293-300
-
-
-
24
-
-
84937284194
-
Obedience in modern society: The utrecht studies
-
For important recent work on Milgram and obedience experiments, see
-
For important recent work on Milgram and obedience experiments, see W. Meeus and Q. Raaijmakers, "Obedience in Modern Society: The Utrecht Studies," Journal of Social Issues 51 (1995), pp. 155-175;
-
(1995)
Journal of Social Issues
, vol.51
, pp. 155-175
-
-
Meeus, W.1
Raaijmakers, Q.2
-
25
-
-
84937288212
-
The ordinary quality of resistance: From milgram's laboratory to the village of le chambon
-
F. Rochat and A. Modigliani, "The Ordinary Quality of Resistance: From Milgram's Laboratory to the Village of Le Chambon," Journal of Social Issues 51 (1995), pp. 195-210;
-
(1995)
Journal of Social Issues
, vol.51
, pp. 195-210
-
-
Rochat, F.1
Modigliani, A.2
-
26
-
-
0030167228
-
The milgram obedience experiment: Support for a cognitive view of defensive attribution
-
T. Blass, "The Milgram Obedience Experiment: Support for a Cognitive View of Defensive Attribution," Journal of Social Psychology 136 (1996), pp. 407-410;
-
(1996)
Journal of Social Psychology
, vol.136
, pp. 407-410
-
-
Blass, T.1
-
27
-
-
0033121345
-
The milgram paradigm after 35 years: Some things we now know about obedience to authority
-
T. Blass, "The Milgram Paradigm after 35 Years: Some Things We Now Know about Obedience to Authority," Journal of Applied Social Psychology 29 (1999), pp. 955-978;
-
(1999)
Journal of Applied Social Psychology
, vol.29
, pp. 955-978
-
-
Blass, T.1
-
29
-
-
77950068140
-
-
After all, some explanation has to be given for why roughly one third of the participants did not turn the dial up all the way. Given that they were in exactly the same situation as the other subjects, it would seem that such an explanation would have to appeal to certain features of their psychology and personality in order to account for the difference in behavioral outcome
-
After all, some explanation has to be given for why roughly one third of the participants did not turn the dial up all the way. Given that they were in exactly the same situation as the other subjects, it would seem that such an explanation would have to appeal to certain features of their psychology and personality in order to account for the difference in behavioral outcome.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
0003766057
-
-
One subject reacted to the outcome of his participation by remarking, "So he's dead. I did my job!" (New York: Harper and Row)
-
One subject reacted to the outcome of his participation by remarking, "So he's dead. I did my job!" [S. Milgram, Obedience to Authority (New York: Harper and Row, 1974), p. 88].
-
(1974)
Obedience to Authority
, vol.88
-
-
Milgram, S.1
-
31
-
-
0002093295
-
Personality characteristics associated with obedience and defiance toward authoritative command
-
And another obedient subject reported that he models himself on a grandfather who, "believed one should take and carry out an order whether one believed it was right or wrong, as long as the person giving it was in authority to give it"
-
And another obedient subject reported that he models himself on a grandfather who, "believed one should take and carry out an order whether one believed it was right or wrong, as long as the person giving it was in authority to give it" [A. Elms and S. Milgram, "Personality Characteristics Associated with Obedience and Defiance Toward Authoritative Command," Journal of Experimental Research in Personality 1 (1966), p. 288].
-
(1966)
Journal of Experimental Research in Personality
, vol.1
, pp. 288
-
-
Elms, A.1
Milgram, S.2
-
32
-
-
77950092669
-
-
For similar concerns, see Milgram himself observed that for "a large number of cases the degree of tension reached extremes that are rarely seen in sociopsychological laboratory studies"
-
For similar concerns, see Athanassoulis, "A Response to Harman," p. 217. Milgram himself observed that for "a large number of cases the degree of tension reached extremes that are rarely seen in sociopsychological laboratory studies"
-
A Response to Harman
, pp. 217
-
-
Athanassoulis1
-
35
-
-
0001898986
-
Traits revisited
-
For a detailed discussion of situationism, see
-
For a detailed discussion of situationism, see G. Allport, "Traits Revisited," American Psychologist 21 (1966), pp. 1-10;
-
(1966)
American Psychologist
, vol.21
, pp. 1-10
-
-
Allport, G.1
-
36
-
-
0015664155
-
Situationism in psychology: An analysis and a critique
-
K. Bowers, "Situationism in Psychology: An Analysis and a Critique," Psychological Review 80 (1973), pp. 307-336;
-
(1973)
Psychological Review
, vol.80
, pp. 307-336
-
-
Bowers, K.1
-
39
-
-
0002068253
-
'From jerusalem to jericho': A study of situational and dispositional variables in helping behavior
-
J. Darley and C. Batson, "'From Jerusalem to Jericho': A Study of Situational and Dispositional Variables in Helping Behavior," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27 (1973), p. 102.
-
(1973)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.27
, pp. 102
-
-
Darley, J.1
Batson, C.2
-
41
-
-
0032340373
-
Values as truisms: Evidence and implications
-
For interesting recent work, see
-
For interesting recent work, see G. Maio and J. Olson, "Values as Truisms: Evidence and Implications," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74 (1998), pp. 294-311;
-
(1998)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.74
, pp. 294-311
-
-
Maio, G.1
Olson, J.2
-
42
-
-
0035609804
-
Addressing discrepancies between values and behavior: The motivating effect of reasons
-
and the references cited therein
-
G. Maio et al., "Addressing Discrepancies between Values and Behavior: The Motivating Effect of Reasons," Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 37 (2001), pp. 104-117, and the references cited therein.
-
(2001)
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology
, vol.37
, pp. 104-117
-
-
Maio, G.1
-
44
-
-
77950095115
-
-
Unfortunately we are not told which trait(s) this is supposed to be, although likely candidates include compassion, empathy, and charity
-
Unfortunately we are not told which trait(s) this is supposed to be, although likely candidates include compassion, empathy, and charity.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
38549138812
-
The intuitive psychologist and his shortcomings
-
See L. Berkowitz (ed.) (New York: Academic) and the discussion in Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality
-
See L. Ross, "The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings," in L. Berkowitz (ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Volume 10 (New York: Academic, 1977) and the discussion in Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality, pp. 306-307.
-
(1977)
Advances in Experimental Social Psychology
, vol.10
, pp. 306-307
-
-
Ross, L.1
-
47
-
-
0038886622
-
Swimming upstream against the fundamental attribution error: Subjects' weak generalizations from the darley and batson study
-
Ross, "The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings"
-
Ross, "The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings"; P. Pietromonaco and R. Nisbett, "Swimming Upstream against the Fundamental Attribution Error: Subjects' Weak Generalizations from the Darley and Batson Study," Social Behavior and Personality 10 (1982), pp. 1-4;
-
(1982)
Social Behavior and Personality
, vol.10
, pp. 1-4
-
-
Pietromonaco, P.1
Nisbett, R.2
-
50
-
-
0029181376
-
The correspondence bias
-
For important recent work, see
-
For important recent work, see D. Gilbert and P. Malone, "The Correspondence Bias," Psychological Bulletin 117 (1995), pp. 21-38;
-
(1995)
Psychological Bulletin
, vol.117
, pp. 21-38
-
-
Gilbert, D.1
Malone, P.2
-
51
-
-
77956771179
-
People as flexible interpreters: Evidence and issues from spontaneous trait inference
-
M. Zanna (ed.) (San Diego: Academic Press)
-
J. Uleman et al., "People as Flexible Interpreters: Evidence and Issues from Spontaneous Trait Inference," in M. Zanna (ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Volume 28 (San Diego: Academic Press, 1996), pp. 211-280;
-
(1996)
Advances in Experimental Social Psychology
, vol.28
, pp. 211-280
-
-
Uleman, J.1
-
52
-
-
85047685230
-
The Dispositional Inference Strikes Back: Situational Focus and Dispositional Suppression in Causal Attribution
-
and the references cited therein
-
V. Yzerbyt et al., "The Dispositional Inference Strikes Back: Situational Focus and Dispositional Suppression in Causal Attribution," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81 (2001), pp. 365-376, and the references cited therein.
-
(2001)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.81
, pp. 365-376
-
-
Yzerbyt, V.1
-
53
-
-
77950097429
-
-
See As he notes, "From the fact that people happen to add badly, it does not follow that there are no sums. Likewise with character traits" (p. 54)
-
See Sreenivasan, "Errors about Errors," pp. 53-54. As he notes, "From the fact that people happen to add badly, it does not follow that there are no sums. Likewise with character traits" (p. 54).
-
Errors about Errors
, pp. 53-54
-
-
Sreenivasan1
-
54
-
-
0003413361
-
-
For a preliminary sketch of various ways to resist committing the Fundamental Attribution Error, see
-
For a preliminary sketch of various ways to resist committing the Fundamental Attribution Error, see Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality, pp. 313-314,
-
Varieties of Moral Personality
, pp. 313-314
-
-
Flanagan1
-
59
-
-
4544334690
-
-
330 It is not clear whether Harman wants to reject local character traits as well. At times, he claims that his target is merely character traits as ordinarily conceived, which presumably is meant to include global but not local character traits
-
Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology," pp. 316, 330. It is not clear whether Harman wants to reject local character traits as well. At times, he claims that his target is merely character traits as ordinarily conceived, which presumably is meant to include global but not local character traits
-
Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology
, pp. 316
-
-
Harman1
-
60
-
-
3042663044
-
-
But he also writes that, "[w]e need to abandon all talk of virtue and character"
-
(Harman, "The Nonexistence of Character Traits," p. 223). But he also writes that, "[w]e need to abandon all talk of virtue and character"
-
The Nonexistence of Character Traits
, pp. 223
-
-
Harman1
-
61
-
-
3042663044
-
-
It would be surprising, however, if his project was to reject local character traits too since he has given us no reason for doing so, and in fact there is abundant empirical evidence for their existence, as we shall see in Section V
-
(Harman, "The Nonexistence of Character Traits," p. 224). It would be surprising, however, if his project was to reject local character traits too since he has given us no reason for doing so, and in fact there is abundant empirical evidence for their existence, as we shall see in Section V.
-
The Nonexistence of Character Traits
, pp. 224
-
-
Harman1
-
62
-
-
77950072126
-
-
According to another form of Global Trait Instrumentalism, we are not justified in believing either that there really are or that there really are not any global character traits, but it is still useful to talk as if such traits did exist
-
According to another form of Global Trait Instrumentalism, we are not justified in believing either that there really are or that there really are not any global character traits, but it is still useful to talk as if such traits did exist.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
3042663044
-
-
He explicitly rejects Global Trait Instrumentalism in Harman
-
He explicitly rejects Global Trait Instrumentalism in Harman, "The Nonexistence of Character Traits," p. 224.
-
The Nonexistence of Character Traits
, pp. 224
-
-
-
64
-
-
4043107034
-
Evaluatives and directives
-
As Harman himself readily acknowledges. Thus Judith Jarvis Thomson has recently been developing a version of virtue ethics which focuses on virtuous action rather than on the cultivation of virtuous character dispositions. See in particular G. Harman and J. Thomson (eds.) (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers)
-
As Harman himself readily acknowledges. Thus Judith Jarvis Thomson has recently been developing a version of virtue ethics which focuses on virtuous action rather than on the cultivation of virtuous character dispositions. See in particular Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Evaluatives and Directives," in G. Harman and J. Thomson (eds.), Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1996), pp. 125-154;
-
(1996)
Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity
, pp. 125-154
-
-
Thomson, J.J.1
-
65
-
-
4243348188
-
The right and the good
-
"The Right and The Good," The Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997), pp. 273-298.
-
(1997)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.94
, pp. 273-298
-
-
-
66
-
-
0003413361
-
-
Thus Owen Flanagan writes that "[t]he entire enterprise of virtue ethics depends on there being individual traits of character which are causally effective in the production of behavior across situations of a kind"
-
Thus Owen Flanagan writes that "[t]he entire enterprise of virtue ethics depends on there being individual traits of character which are causally effective in the production of behavior across situations of a kind" (Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality, p. 282).
-
Varieties of Moral Personality
, pp. 282
-
-
Flanagan1
-
67
-
-
77950093495
-
-
See also Rosalind Hursthouse (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
See also Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 11-12, 29.
-
(1999)
On Virtue Ethics
, vol.29
, pp. 11-12
-
-
-
69
-
-
77950086807
-
-
it is also to take the first step towards explaining why those actions rather than some others were performed" (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press)
-
it is also to take the first step towards explaining why those actions rather than some others were performed" [A. Maclntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), p. 199].
-
(1984)
After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory
, pp. 199
-
-
Maclntyre, A.1
-
70
-
-
70349150284
-
Character traits and desires
-
See also 542
-
See also Stephen Hudson, "Character Traits and Desires," Ethics 90 (1980), pp. 539, 542;
-
(1980)
Ethics
, vol.90
, pp. 539
-
-
Hudson, S.1
-
71
-
-
0001865848
-
On the old saw that character is destiny
-
Owen Flanagan and Amélie O. Rorty (eds.) (Cambridge: MIT Press)
-
Michele Moody-Adams, "On the Old Saw that Character is Destiny," in Owen Flanagan and Amélie O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990), p. 111;
-
(1990)
Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology
, pp. 111
-
-
Moody-Adams, M.1
-
73
-
-
77950089248
-
Traits revisited
-
For similar claims in psychology, see Allport and One might reasonably doubt whether all explanations have to be causal or whether the virtue ethicist is committed to giving a causal account of trait-based action. Unfortunately, adequate discussion of these important issues will have to wait for another time
-
For similar claims in psychology, see Allport, "Traits Revisited", and Mischel, Personality and Assessment, p. 5. One might reasonably doubt whether all explanations have to be causal or whether the virtue ethicist is committed to giving a causal account of trait-based action. Unfortunately, adequate discussion of these important issues will have to wait for another time.
-
Personality and Assessment
, pp. 5
-
-
Mischel1
-
74
-
-
77950080996
-
-
It need not follow, of course, that he did the relevant action for the reason that it was just. Rather, because he was just he recognized that particular reason, whatever it may be, as the one on which he ought to act
-
It need not follow, of course, that he did the relevant action for the reason that it was just. Rather, because he was just he recognized that particular reason, whatever it may be, as the one on which he ought to act.
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
77950097099
-
-
For more on character traits as dispositions, see in particular (Cambridge: Harvard University Press)
-
For more on character traits as dispositions, see in particular Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 9, 35-37;
-
(1985)
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
, vol.9
, pp. 35-37
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
76
-
-
42449122153
-
Traits of character: A conceptual analysis
-
reprinted in Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
Richard Brandt, "Traits of Character: A Conceptual Analysis," reprinted in Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), p. 266;
-
(1992)
Utilitarianism, and Rights
, pp. 266
-
-
Brandt, R.1
-
77
-
-
77950091243
-
The structure of virtue
-
and reprinted in
-
and "The Structure of Virtue, " reprinted in Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights, pp. 289-311.
-
Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights
, pp. 289-311
-
-
-
80
-
-
4544233293
-
-
See The counterfactual is merely a necessary condition since the virtue theorist may also want to insist that the T-sortal act also arise from a stable disposition and from the appropriate intentions and desires. Additionally, the probability qualification is important since trait possession is not an all or nothing event, but rather comes in degrees of more or less
-
See Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics," p. 509. The counterfactual is merely a necessary condition since the virtue theorist may also want to insist that the T-sortal act also arise from a stable disposition and from the appropriate intentions and desires. Additionally, the probability qualification is important since trait possession is not an all or nothing event, but rather comes in degrees of more or less
-
Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics
, pp. 509
-
-
Doris1
-
81
-
-
77950071206
-
-
see We shall return to this point at greater length in sections four and five. Finally, the qualification about merely attempting to perform the relevant action is needed for those cases where external impediments prevent the agent's actually being able to perform it
-
(see Brandt, "Traits of Character," p. 266). We shall return to this point at greater length in sections four and five. Finally, the qualification about merely attempting to perform the relevant action is needed for those cases where external impediments prevent the agent's actually being able to perform it.
-
Traits of Character
, pp. 266
-
-
Brandt1
-
83
-
-
84925895410
-
Virtues and actions
-
N. Dent, "Virtues and Actions," The Philosophical Quarterly 25 (1975), pp. 327-328;
-
(1975)
The Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.25
, pp. 327-328
-
-
Dent, N.1
-
87
-
-
84921947363
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Stephen Mumford, Dispositions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), pp. 11-12;
-
(1998)
Dispositions
, pp. 11-12
-
-
Mumford, S.1
-
92
-
-
77950076705
-
Persons, situations, and virtue ethics
-
See and Here our focus will be on Doris' argument in the earlier work
-
See Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics"; and Lack of Character. Here our focus will be on Doris' argument in the earlier work.
-
Lack of Character
-
-
Doris1
-
96
-
-
4544233293
-
-
522, fn 14
-
Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics," pp. 509, 522, fn 14.
-
Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics
, pp. 509
-
-
Doris1
-
97
-
-
77950087350
-
-
fn 23. In this regard, it seems to me quite plausible to think that the Milgram and Good Samaritan experiments provide some supporting evidence in favor of premises (ii) and (iv). If, for example, many of the seminary students did fully possess such virtues as charity and benevolence, then third party observers should have been able to predict that the students would not let time considerations distract them from aiding the slumped-over man. But as Darley and Batson showed, the degree to which the students exhibited helping behavior seemed to be strongly influenced by the degree to which they took themselves to be in a hurry. So it does seem as if these students did not fully possess the relevant virtues as robust features of their characters
-
Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics," p. 523, fn 23. In this regard, it seems to me quite plausible to think that the Milgram and Good Samaritan experiments provide some supporting evidence in favor of premises (ii) and (iv). If, for example, many of the seminary students did fully possess such virtues as charity and benevolence, then third party observers should have been able to predict that the students would not let time considerations distract them from aiding the slumped-over man. But as Darley and Batson showed, the degree to which the students exhibited helping behavior seemed to be strongly influenced by the degree to which they took themselves to be in a hurry. So it does seem as if these students did not fully possess the relevant virtues as robust features of their characters.
-
Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics
, pp. 523
-
-
Doris1
-
98
-
-
77950078763
-
-
Alternatively one could take the argument to show that the Consistency and Predictive Expectations are false, but that is not Doris' aim
-
Alternatively one could take the argument to show that the Consistency and Predictive Expectations are false, but that is not Doris' aim.
-
-
-
-
100
-
-
0004290120
-
-
See Ithaca: Cornell University Press
-
See James Wallace, Virtues and Vices (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1978), p. 143;
-
(1978)
Virtues and Vices
, pp. 143
-
-
Wallace, J.1
-
101
-
-
34247511892
-
Virtues in excess
-
Gary Watson, "Virtues in Excess," Philosophical Studies 46 (1984), p. 58;
-
(1984)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.46
, pp. 58
-
-
Watson, G.1
-
103
-
-
77950092669
-
-
makes a similar point in response to Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology."
-
Athanassoulis, "A Response to Harman," pp. 218-219, makes a similar point in response to Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology."
-
A Response to Harman
, pp. 218-219
-
-
Athanassoulis1
-
104
-
-
77950084368
-
-
For further discussion of this point in the context of responding to Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology," see
-
For further discussion of this point in the context of responding to Harman, "Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology," see Depaul, "Character Traits, Virtues, and Vices," pp. 150-153.
-
Character Traits, Virtues, and Vices
, pp. 150-153
-
-
Depaul1
-
105
-
-
0003986649
-
-
See trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1985), 1099b29-32, 1103b16-31, 1152a30-34, 1179b25-29, 1180al-5, 15-19;
-
See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1985), 1099b29-32, 1103b16-31, 1152a30-34, 1179b25-29, 1180al-5, 15-19;
-
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
106
-
-
85163425211
-
Aristotle on learning to be good
-
Amélie Rorty (ed.) (Berkeley: University of California Press)
-
M. Burnyeat, "Aristotle on Learning to Be Good," in Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp. 69-92;
-
(1980)
Essays on Aristotle's Ethics
, pp. 69-92
-
-
Burnyeat, M.1
-
107
-
-
84909054282
-
-
and for Aristotle's account of moral development
-
and Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, pp. 38-39, for Aristotle's account of moral development.
-
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
, pp. 38-39
-
-
Williams1
-
108
-
-
77950099512
-
-
See also In light of the above, it is extremely odd that John Campbell formulates his argument from social psychology as an attack on what he takes to be the popular Kantian and virtue ethical commitment to, "powerful forces toward helping behaviour that are widespread if not universal, and which occupy a central place in many persons' motivational constitution" (Campbell, "Can Philosophical Accounts of Altrism Accommodate Experimental Data on Helping Behavior?," p. 41)
-
See also Athanassoulis, "Response to Harman," pp. 219-220. In light of the above, it is extremely odd that John Campbell formulates his argument from social psychology as an attack on what he takes to be the popular Kantian and virtue ethical commitment to, "powerful forces toward helping behaviour that are widespread if not universal, and which occupy a central place in many persons' motivational constitution" (Campbell, "Can Philosophical Accounts of Altrism Accommodate Experimental Data on Helping Behavior?," p. 41).
-
Response to Harman
, pp. 219-220
-
-
Athanassoulis1
-
109
-
-
77950089082
-
-
Aristotle himself writes that, "the many naturally obey fear, not shame
-
Aristotle himself writes that, "the many naturally obey fear, not shame;
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
0003986649
-
-
they avoid what is base because of the penalties, not because it is disgraceful. For since they live by their feelings, they pursue their proper pleasures and the sources of them, and avoid the opposed pains, and have not even a notion of what is fine and truly pleasant, since they have had no taste of it" 1179b11-16. And according to Athanassoulis, "[v]irtue ethics presumably requires that moral behaviour, in the form of possessing virtuous character traits, is a possibility, rather than an actuality for the majority of people"
-
they avoid what is base because of the penalties, not because it is disgraceful. For since they live by their feelings, they pursue their proper pleasures and the sources of them, and avoid the opposed pains, and have not even a notion of what is fine and truly pleasant, since they have had no taste of it" (Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1179b11-16). And according to Athanassoulis, "[v]irtue ethics presumably requires that moral behaviour, in the form of possessing virtuous character traits, is a possibility, rather than an actuality for the majority of people" (Athanassoulis, "Response to Harman," p. 217).
-
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
112
-
-
0003587061
-
-
See also (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
See also Lawrence Blum, Moral Perception and Particularity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pp. 94-96,
-
(1994)
Moral Perception and Particularity
, pp. 94-96
-
-
Blum, L.1
-
113
-
-
4544233293
-
-
and footnote 32. What it is for a global character trait to be "weakly" or "moderately" possessed will be discussed in more detail at the end of Section V
-
and Doris, "Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics," footnote 32. What it is for a global character trait to be "weakly" or "moderately" possessed will be discussed in more detail at the end of Section V.
-
Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics
-
-
Doris1
-
114
-
-
77950089967
-
-
Thus Aristotle seems to locate most people somewhere between continence and incontinence when he writes that, "[i]ncontinence and continence are concerned with what exceeds the state of most people;
-
Thus Aristotle seems to locate most people somewhere between continence and incontinence when he writes that, "[i]ncontinence and continence are concerned with what exceeds the state of most people;
-
-
-
-
115
-
-
0003986649
-
-
the continent person abides [by reason] more than most people are capable of doing, the incontinent person less" (1152a25-27). The issue of continence introduces an important problem for arguments based on social psychology. For the empirical experiments do not usually discriminate between actions properly described as virtuous and those that are merely continent. The same problem arises with vice as opposed to incontinence
-
the continent person abides [by reason] more than most people are capable of doing, the incontinent person less" (Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1152a25-27). The issue of continence introduces an important problem for arguments based on social psychology. For the empirical experiments do not usually discriminate between actions properly described as virtuous and those that are merely continent. The same problem arises with vice as opposed to incontinence
-
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
119
-
-
77950090884
-
-
A more detailed account of global trait acquisition is developed in the next section
-
A more detailed account of global trait acquisition is developed in the next section.
-
-
-
-
122
-
-
0001895023
-
A critique of utilitarianism
-
In particular, the work of Bernard Williams and Michael Stocker is sometimes taken to show that appealing to impersonal rules or norms in the course of deliberation is dehumanizing and introduces a form of schizophrenia between an agent's reasons and motives. See especially(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) 131
-
In particular, the work of Bernard Williams and Michael Stocker is sometimes taken to show that appealing to impersonal rules or norms in the course of deliberation is dehumanizing and introduces a form of schizophrenia between an agent's reasons and motives. See especially Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 116, 131,
-
(1973)
Utilitarianism: For and Against
, pp. 116
-
-
Williams1
-
124
-
-
0000685612
-
-
Yet according to Doris, "[t]heoretical mediation through an ideal of virtue is no less obviously problematic than through an ideal of rationality, duty, or maximizing happiness, and alienation, if it is a genuine difficulty, may plague character-based ideals no less than other ideals"
-
The Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976), pp. 453-466. Yet according to Doris, "[t]heoretical mediation through an ideal of virtue is no less obviously problematic than through an ideal of rationality, duty, or maximizing happiness, and alienation, if it is a genuine difficulty, may plague character-based ideals no less than other ideals"
-
(1976)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.73
, pp. 453-466
-
-
-
126
-
-
84869669817
-
-
For a rather different and in my view convincing response to Doris on theoretical mediation, see
-
For a rather different and in my view convincing response to Doris on theoretical mediation, see Merritt, "Virtue Ethics," pp. 370-371.
-
Virtue Ethics
, pp. 370-371
-
-
Merritt1
-
127
-
-
0023476508
-
A conditional approach to dispositional constructs
-
For a start, see Mischel and Peake, "Beyond Déjà Vu in the Search for Cross-Situational Consistency;"
-
For a start, see Mischel and Peake, "Beyond Déjà Vu in the Search for Cross-Situational Consistency;" J. Wright and W. Mischel, "A Conditional Approach to Dispositional Constructs," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53 (1987), pp. 1159-1177;
-
(1987)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.53
, pp. 1159-1177
-
-
Wright, J.1
Mischel, W.2
-
128
-
-
0024078362
-
Conditional hedges and the intuitive psychology of traits
-
and
-
and "Conditional Hedges and the Intuitive Psychology of Traits," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 55 (1988), pp. 454-469;
-
(1988)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.55
, pp. 454-469
-
-
-
129
-
-
0024527963
-
Intuitive interactionism in person perception: Effects of situation-behavior relations on dispositional judgments
-
Y. Shoda, W. Mischel, and J. Wright, "Intuitive Interactionism in Person Perception: Effects of Situation-Behavior Relations on Dispositional Judgments," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 56 (1989), pp. 41-53;
-
(1989)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.56
, pp. 41-53
-
-
Shoda, Y.1
Mischel, W.2
Wright, J.3
-
130
-
-
0028520781
-
Intra-individual stability in the organization and patterning of behavior
-
and
-
and "Intra-individual Stability in the Organization and Patterning of Behavior," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67 (1994), pp. 674-687;
-
(1994)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.67
, pp. 674-687
-
-
-
131
-
-
0029287435
-
A cognitive-affective system theory of personality
-
and
-
and W. Mischel and Y. Shoda, "A Cognitive-Affective System Theory of Personality," Psychological Review 102 (1995), pp. 246-268.
-
(1995)
Psychological Review
, vol.102
, pp. 246-268
-
-
Mischel, W.1
Shoda, Y.2
-
132
-
-
77950096356
-
-
The "probably" qualifier in the consequent of each conditional is intended to capture the fact that local character trait possession can come in degrees. Note as well that strictly speaking (LT) can also serve as a necessary condition for global trait possession. Thus it is not meant to isolate the relevant difference between local as opposed to global character traits, but rather to emphasize the important role that temporal stability plays in the case of the former. What instead serves as the central differentiating condition is the failure of local character traits to exhibit cross-situational consistency
-
The "probably" qualifier in the consequent of each conditional is intended to capture the fact that local character trait possession can come in degrees. Note as well that strictly speaking (LT) can also serve as a necessary condition for global trait possession. Thus it is not meant to isolate the relevant difference between local as opposed to global character traits, but rather to emphasize the important role that temporal stability plays in the case of the former. What instead serves as the central differentiating condition is the failure of local character traits to exhibit cross-situational consistency.
-
-
-
-
134
-
-
0015643352
-
Toward a cognitive social learning reconceptualization of personality
-
See Mischel and Shoda, "Cognitive-Affective System Theory."
-
See W. Mischel, "Toward a Cognitive Social Learning Reconceptualization of Personality," Psychological Review 80 (1973), pp. 252-283; Mischel and Shoda, "Cognitive-Affective System Theory."
-
(1973)
Psychological Review
, vol.80
, pp. 252-283
-
-
Mischel, W.1
-
138
-
-
0001889724
-
Toward a unified, intra-individual dynamic conception of personality
-
See especially the important studies cited in footnote 57. For more recent work in this area, see also
-
See especially the important studies cited in footnote 57. For more recent work in this area, see also Y. Shoda and W. Mischel, "Toward a Unified, Intra-Individual Dynamic Conception of Personality," Journal of Research in Personality 30 (1996), pp. 414-428;
-
(1996)
Journal of Research in Personality
, vol.30
, pp. 414-428
-
-
Shoda, Y.1
Mischel, W.2
-
139
-
-
0002049280
-
Personality as a stable cognitive-affective activation network
-
S. Read and L. Miller (eds.) (Mahwah: Erlbaum)
-
"Personality as a Stable Cognitive-Affective Activation Network," in S. Read and L. Miller (eds.), Connectionist Models of Social Reasoning and Social Behavior (Mahwah: Erlbaum, 1998), pp. 175-208;
-
(1998)
Connectionist Models of Social Reasoning and Social Behavior
, pp. 175-208
-
-
-
142
-
-
0035623459
-
Unraveling the paradoxes of narcissism: A dynamic self-regulatory processing model
-
C. Morf and P. Rhodewalt, "Unraveling the Paradoxes of Narcissism: A Dynamic Self-Regulatory Processing Model," Psychological Inquiry 12 (2001), pp. 177-196;
-
(2001)
Psychological Inquiry
, vol.12
, pp. 177-196
-
-
Morf, C.1
Rhodewalt, P.2
-
144
-
-
85047685138
-
Situation interactionism in self-encoding (i am ... when ...)
-
Situation Interactionism in Self-Encoding (I Am ... When ...)," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 80 (2001), pp. 533-544;
-
(2001)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.80
, pp. 533-544
-
-
-
146
-
-
0036106546
-
Feeling and doing: Affective influences on interpersonal behavior
-
and
-
and J. Forgas, "Feeling and Doing: Affective Influences on Interpersonal Behavior," Psychological Inquiry 13 (2002), pp. 1-28.
-
(2002)
Psychological Inquiry
, vol.13
, pp. 1-28
-
-
Forgas, J.1
-
147
-
-
77950070176
-
-
Mischel and Shoda, "Cognitive-Affective System Theory," p. 261. See also B. Roberts et al., "The Kids Are Alright: Growth and Stability in Personality Development From Adolescence to Adulthood," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81 (2001), pp. 670-683 and the references cited therein.
-
Cognitive-affective System Theory
, pp. 261
-
-
Mischel1
Shoda2
-
148
-
-
85047682555
-
The kids are alright: Growth and stability in personality development from adolescence to adulthood
-
See also and the references cited therein
-
See also B. Roberts et al., "The Kids Are Alright: Growth and Stability in Personality Development From Adolescence to Adulthood," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81 (2001), pp. 670-683 and the references cited therein.
-
(2001)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.81
, pp. 670-683
-
-
Roberts, B.1
-
149
-
-
77950070176
-
-
Mischel and Shoda go on to note that individuals, "can link goal-relevant plans and implementation intentions to the relevant situations in ways that will trigger the desired behavior when needed"
-
Mischel and Shoda go on to note that individuals, "can link goal-relevant plans and implementation intentions to the relevant situations in ways that will trigger the desired behavior when needed" (Mischel and Shoda, "Cognitive-Affective System Theory," p. 261).
-
Cognitive-affective System Theory
, pp. 261
-
-
Mischel1
Shoda2
-
150
-
-
77950097429
-
-
According to Sreenivasan, "In one study, Charles Lord found that an individual's cross-situational consistency in conscientiousness was significantly higher when the pair of situations in question was regarded as similar by the individual himself or herself" (emphasis his)
-
According to Sreenivasan, "In one study, Charles Lord found that an individual's cross-situational consistency in conscientiousness was significantly higher when the pair of situations in question was regarded as similar by the individual himself or herself" (Sreenivasan, "Errors about Errors," p. 65, emphasis his).
-
Errors about Errors
, pp. 65
-
-
Sreenivasan1
-
151
-
-
0347783732
-
Predicting behavioral consistency from an individual's perception of situational similarities
-
For Lord's study, see
-
For Lord's study, see Charles Lord, "Predicting Behavioral Consistency From an Individual's Perception of Situational Similarities," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 42 (1982), pp. 1076-1088.
-
(1982)
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.42
, pp. 1076-1088
-
-
Lord, C.1
-
153
-
-
77950071564
-
-
Another departure from ordinary thinking about ethics was noted at the end of Section I in the context of discussing the Fundamental Attribution Error. My view readily agrees with the claim that ordinary people are far too quick to appeal to characterological explanations without sufficient evidence of temporally and cross-situationally repeatable trait-evincing behavior
-
Another departure from ordinary thinking about ethics was noted at the end of Section I in the context of discussing the Fundamental Attribution Error. My view readily agrees with the claim that ordinary people are far too quick to appeal to characterological explanations without sufficient evidence of temporally and cross-situationally repeatable trait-evincing behavior.
-
-
-
-
154
-
-
77950079045
-
-
A similar idea seems to have been expressed less formally by
-
A similar idea seems to have been expressed less formally by Watson, "Virtues in Excess," p. 58;
-
Virtues in Excess
, pp. 58
-
-
Watson1
-
158
-
-
77950094578
-
-
Unfortunately, (MS) is inadequate as it now stands for various reasons both technical - whether there can be a least member set if the minimal subset is infinite in size, whether there is vagueness in determining what falls inside and outside the scope of the minimal subset, whether there can be a determinate truth-value for counterfactuals concerning free human actions, whether (MS) can accommodate moral dilemmas - and intuitive, such as whether there might be more than one minimal subset for any given global character trait. I take up each of these issues in more recent work
-
Unfortunately, (MS) is inadequate as it now stands for various reasons both technical - whether there can be a least member set if the minimal subset is infinite in size, whether there is vagueness in determining what falls inside and outside the scope of the minimal subset, whether there can be a determinate truth-value for counterfactuals concerning free human actions, whether (MS) can accommodate moral dilemmas - and intuitive, such as whether there might be more than one minimal subset for any given global character trait. I take up each of these issues in more recent work.
-
-
-
-
159
-
-
77950091040
-
-
For all we know, a few of these subjects may possess well-developed global character traits. In the Good Samaritan experiment, 10% of participants in the high hurry scenario and 45% in the intermediate one, still stopped to help the slumped-over man. What is the best explanation of this behavior which seemingly neglected occurrent external determinants of action? Well, perhaps one way to answer this question would be to take that particular group of subjects and submit them to several other helping experiments involving varying degrees of situational influence. If the majority of participants continue to exhibit helping behavior, then we might have some empirical evidence that they in fact have the relevant virtues as part of their characters
-
For all we know, a few of these subjects may possess well-developed global character traits. In the Good Samaritan experiment, 10% of participants in the high hurry scenario and 45% in the intermediate one, still stopped to help the slumped-over man. What is the best explanation of this behavior which seemingly neglected occurrent external determinants of action? Well, perhaps one way to answer this question would be to take that particular group of subjects and submit them to several other helping experiments involving varying degrees of situational influence. If the majority of participants continue to exhibit helping behavior, then we might have some empirical evidence that they in fact have the relevant virtues as part of their characters.
-
-
-
-
162
-
-
0002093295
-
-
A follow-up study was done by Elms and Milgram on the significant number of disobedient participants in the Milgram experiment, and there some significant personality differences were uncovered, although how best to interpret their results still remains unclear
-
A follow-up study was done by Elms and Milgram on the significant number of disobedient participants in the Milgram experiment, and there some significant personality differences were uncovered, although how best to interpret their results still remains unclear (Elms and Milgram, "Personality Characteristics Associated with Obedience and Defiance Toward Authoritative Command," pp. 282-289).
-
Personality Characteristics Associated with Obedience and Defiance Toward Authoritative Command
, pp. 282-289
-
-
Elms1
Milgram2
-
166
-
-
38749124261
-
Dimes and helping: The other side of the coin
-
See, for example, the studies cited by
-
See, for example, the studies cited by J. Weyant and R. Clark, "Dimes and Helping: The Other Side of the Coin," Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 3 (1977), p. 107.
-
(1977)
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin
, vol.3
, pp. 107
-
-
Weyant, J.1
Clark, R.2
-
167
-
-
38749134726
-
Feeling good and helping: Further phone booth findings
-
G. Blevins and T. Murphy, "Feeling Good and Helping: Further Phone Booth Findings," Psychological Reports 34 (1974), p. 326.
-
(1974)
Psychological Reports
, vol.34
, pp. 326
-
-
Blevins, G.1
Murphy, T.2
-
169
-
-
84925890553
-
Further studies on the effect of feeling good on helping
-
P. Levin and A. Isen, "Further Studies on the Effect of Feeling Good on Helping," Sociometry 38 (1975), p. 146.
-
(1975)
Sociometry
, vol.38
, pp. 146
-
-
Levin, P.1
Isen, A.2
-
172
-
-
77950071565
-
-
See also their graphite variant on the payphone experiment
-
See also their graphite variant on the payphone experiment (Weyant and Clark, "Dimes and Helping," pp. 107-108).
-
Dimes and Helping
, pp. 107-108
-
-
Weyant1
Clark2
-
173
-
-
0001907123
-
Feeling good and helping: How quickly does the smile of dame fortune fade?
-
It is worth noting that also could not duplicate the results of a different helping experiment described by Isen and Levin in "Effect of Feeling Good on Helping." of finding the dime in the coin slot
-
It is worth noting that J. Schellenberg and G. Blevins ("Feeling Good and Helping: How Quickly Does the Smile of Dame Fortune Fade?," Psychological Reports 33 (1973), pp. 72-74) also could not duplicate the results of a different helping experiment described by Isen and Levin in "Effect of Feeling Good on Helping." of finding the dime in the coin slot.
-
(1973)
Psychological Reports
, vol.33
, pp. 72-74
-
-
Schellenberg, J.1
Blevins, G.2
-
174
-
-
84938048518
-
Generality of the 'glow of goodwill': Effects of mood on helping and information acquisition
-
See
-
See C. Batson et al., "Generality of the 'Glow of Goodwill': Effects of Mood on Helping and Information Acquisition," Social Psychology Quarterly 42 (1979), pp. 176-179.
-
(1979)
Social Psychology Quarterly
, vol.42
, pp. 176-179
-
-
Batson, C.1
-
175
-
-
84991180392
-
A whiff of reality: Empirical evidence concerning the effects of pleasant fragrances on work-related behavior
-
For important recent work on similar kinds of helping experiments, see
-
For important recent work on similar kinds of helping experiments, see R. Baron and M. Bronfen, "A Whiff of Reality: Empirical Evidence Concerning the Effects of Pleasant Fragrances on Work-Related Behavior," Journal of Applied Social Psychology 24 (1994), pp. 1179-1203;
-
(1994)
Journal of Applied Social Psychology
, vol.24
, pp. 1179-1203
-
-
Baron, R.1
Bronfen, M.2
-
176
-
-
0031287685
-
The sweet smell of ... helping: Effects of pleasant ambient fragrance on prosocial behavior in shopping malls
-
and as well as the more general issues about affective influence raised by Forgas, "Feeling and Doing."
-
and R. Baron, "The Sweet Smell of ... Helping: Effects of Pleasant Ambient Fragrance on Prosocial Behavior in Shopping Malls," Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 23 (1997), pp. 498-503, as well as the more general issues about affective influence raised by Forgas, "Feeling and Doing."
-
(1997)
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin
, vol.23
, pp. 498-503
-
-
Baron, R.1
|