메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 3, 2006, Pages 377-400

Reconciling communicative action with recognition: Thickening the ‘inter’ of intersubjectivity

Author keywords

Axel Honneth; communicative action; communicative rationality; discourse ethics; J rgen Habermas; recognition; universal pragmatics

Indexed keywords


EID: 33750909689     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0191453706063214     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (50)
  • 1
    • 0004011977 scopus 로고
    • Against traditional approaches to morality, Kant distinguishes between the function of the human will in general, which is to choose the course of action that fits one's aims, preferences, and character, and the function of the human will concerning moral matters. When concerned with moral matters, we do not start out from subjective aims or preferences but from what is necessary for us to do. For Kant, this necessity could only be generated from our rational considerations, which, in turn, must be formulated as a principle of obligation. Kant claims that it is only the categorical imperative that could fulfil these requirements: ‘act only on that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law’, New Jersey: Prentice Hall
    • Against traditional approaches to morality, Kant distinguishes between the function of the human will in general, which is to choose the course of action that fits one's aims, preferences, and character, and the function of the human will concerning moral matters. When concerned with moral matters, we do not start out from subjective aims or preferences but from what is necessary for us to do. For Kant, this necessity could only be generated from our rational considerations, which, in turn, must be formulated as a principle of obligation. Kant claims that it is only the categorical imperative that could fulfil these requirements: ‘act only on that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law’ (Immanuel Kant, section I, The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1989[1785]).
    • (1989) The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals
    • Kant, I.1
  • 2
    • 34548361155 scopus 로고
    • trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 95
    • Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. II, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1987), p. 96, 95.
    • (1987) The Theory of Communicative Action , vol.2 , pp. 96
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 3
    • 0002936124 scopus 로고
    • What is Universal Pragmatics?
    • trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, ‘What is Universal Pragmatics?’, in Communication and the Evolution of Society, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1979), pp. 1–68.
    • (1979) Communication and the Evolution of Society , pp. 1-68
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 4
    • 84998075874 scopus 로고
    • trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. I, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1984), pp. 99–100.
    • (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action , vol.1 , pp. 99-100
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 5
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. W. Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 160, 161
    • Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, trans. W. Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), p. 159, 160, 161.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms , pp. 159
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 6
    • 0000416704 scopus 로고
    • On Systematically Distorted Communication
    • Jürgen Habermas, ‘On Systematically Distorted Communication’, Inquiry 13 (1970): 210.
    • (1970) Inquiry , vol.13 , pp. 210
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 7
    • 0003807937 scopus 로고
    • For example, for the justification of moral norms, Habermas formulates a universalization principle (U-principle): ‘For a norm to be valid, the consequences and side effects that its general observance can be expected to have for the satisfaction of the particular interests of each person affected must be such that all affected can accept them freely.’ See, Boston, MA: Beacon Press
    • For example, for the justification of moral norms, Habermas formulates a universalization principle (U-principle): ‘For a norm to be valid, the consequences and side effects that its general observance can be expected to have for the satisfaction of the particular interests of each person affected must be such that all affected can accept them freely.’ See Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1995), p. 120.
    • (1995) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action , pp. 120
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 11
    • 33646155488 scopus 로고
    • Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 56, note 61
    • Karl-Otto Apel, Etik och kommunikation (Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 1990), p. 54, 56, note 61.
    • (1990) Etik och kommunikation , pp. 54
    • Apel, K.-O.1
  • 13
    • 84997872035 scopus 로고
    • Teorin om det kommunikativa handlandet: ett svar på kritik
    • Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 318 (my translation)
    • Jürgen Habermas, ‘Teorin om det kommunikativa handlandet: ett svar på kritik’, in Kommunikativt handlande (Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 1995), pp. 332–3, 318 (my translation).
    • (1995) Kommunikativt handlande , pp. 332-333
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 14
    • 84997904482 scopus 로고
    • Habermas and Rationality
    • Fred Dallmayr, ‘Habermas and Rationality’, Political Theory 16(4) (1988): 556.
    • (1988) Political Theory , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 556
    • Dallmayr, F.1
  • 17
    • 84997866408 scopus 로고
    • Fred Dallmayr's Critique of Habermas
    • 584
    • Richard Bernstein, ‘Fred Dallmayr's Critique of Habermas’, Political Theory 16(4) (1988): 582, 584.
    • (1988) Political Theory , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 582
    • Bernstein, R.1
  • 18
    • 0040291248 scopus 로고
    • Historical Materialism and the Development of Normative Structures
    • quote from, Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 585
    • quote from Habermas, ‘Historical Materialism and the Development of Normative Structures’, in Communication and the Evolution of Society (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1979), pp. 119–20), 585.
    • (1979) Communication and the Evolution of Society , pp. 119-120
    • Habermas1
  • 19
    • 34548368483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 108, 150, 150–1, 158–9
    • Joachim Israel, Språk och kunskap (Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 1992), 108, 150, 150–1, 158–9.
    • (1992) Språk och kunskap
    • Israel, J.1
  • 20
    • 33645128943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ludvika: Dualis förlag
    • Martin Buber, Jag och Du (Ludvika: Dualis förlag, 2001[1923]).
    • (2001) Jag och Du
    • Buber, M.1
  • 21
    • 0039500671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recognition and Moral Obligation
    • Axel Honneth, ‘Recognition and Moral Obligation’, Social Research 64(1) (1997): 16–35.
    • (1997) Social Research , vol.64 , Issue.1 , pp. 16-35
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 22
    • 0003891615 scopus 로고
    • ed. C. W. Morris (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press
    • George Herbert Mead, Mind, Self, and Society, ed. C. W. Morris (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1934).
    • (1934) Mind, Self, and Society
    • Mead, G.H.1
  • 23
    • 11644257057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Asymmetry and Mutuality: Habermas and Levinas
    • 61
    • Robert Gibbs, ‘Asymmetry and Mutuality: Habermas and Levinas’, Philosophy & Social Criticism 23(6) (1997): 60, 61.
    • (1997) Philosophy & Social Criticism , vol.23 , Issue.6 , pp. 60
    • Gibbs, R.1
  • 24
    • 11644305077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Worlds Apart? Habermas and Levinas
    • Arne J. Vetlesen, ‘Worlds Apart? Habermas and Levinas’, Philosophy & Social Criticism 23(1) (1997): 16.
    • (1997) Philosophy & Social Criticism , vol.23 , Issue.1 , pp. 16
    • Vetlesen, A.J.1
  • 25
    • 33750901874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For examples of how this widened notion of communicative rationality could be incorporated in the analysis of political institutions and institutional design, see, Aldershot, Hants: Ashgate Publishing, chs V and VI
    • For examples of how this widened notion of communicative rationality could be incorporated in the analysis of political institutions and institutional design, see Eva Erman, Human Rights and Democracy: Discourse Theory and Global Rights Institutions (Aldershot, Hants: Ashgate Publishing, 2005), chs V and VI.
    • (2005) Human Rights and Democracy: Discourse Theory and Global Rights Institutions
    • Erman, E.1
  • 26
    • 0003871218 scopus 로고
    • Asymmetry is rarely touched upon within traditional moral philosophy in general and most approaches to difference are made within the liberal-communitarian debate and not explicitly within discourse ethics. But, of course, there are exceptions; see, for example, Cambridge: Polity Press
    • Asymmetry is rarely touched upon within traditional moral philosophy in general and most approaches to difference are made within the liberal-communitarian debate and not explicitly within discourse ethics. But, of course, there are exceptions; see, for example, Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Situating the Self
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 27
    • 0004129258 scopus 로고
    • Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 299–300, 85, 84
    • Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity (Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1969), p. 88, 299–300, 85, 84).
    • (1969) Totality and Infinity , pp. 88
    • Levinas, E.1
  • 28
    • 84966724989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In contrast to Husserl and Heidegger, the problem of the nature of the contact with the Other is not a problem of the alter ego, since everything is centred on the alterity of the alter ego. The pre-eminence of Being over beings and of ontology over metaphysics, in Heidegger's thinking, subscribes to the western tradition in which the same dominates the other and freedom precedes justice. The relationship with the other is thereby subordinated to ontology. For Levinas, however, ethics is about primordial access to the Other beyond all ontology
    • In contrast to Husserl and Heidegger, the problem of the nature of the contact with the Other is not a problem of the alter ego, since everything is centred on the alterity of the alter ego. The pre-eminence of Being over beings and of ontology over metaphysics, in Heidegger's thinking, subscribes to the western tradition in which the same dominates the other and freedom precedes justice. The relationship with the other is thereby subordinated to ontology. For Levinas, however, ethics is about primordial access to the Other beyond all ontology (Levinas, Totality and Infinity, p. 89).
    • Totality and Infinity , pp. 89
    • Levinas1
  • 29
    • 0007137392 scopus 로고
    • Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press
    • Emmanuel Levinas, Collected Philosophical Papers (Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1987), p. 43.
    • (1987) Collected Philosophical Papers , pp. 43
    • Levinas, E.1
  • 31
    • 0347440672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 198
    • Mikael Carleheden, Det andra moderna (Göteborg: Daidalos förlag, 1996), pp. 193–6, 198.
    • (1996) Det andra moderna , pp. 193-196
    • Carleheden, M.1
  • 33
    • 0004225610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2nd revised edn (New York: Continuum
    • Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd revised edn (New York: Continuum, 1999[1989]), p. 97.
    • (1999) Truth and Method , pp. 97
    • Gadamer, H.-G.1
  • 37
    • 0007198607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Other of Justice: Habermas and the Ethical Challenge of Postmodernism
    • S. White (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Axel Honneth, ‘The Other of Justice: Habermas and the Ethical Challenge of Postmodernism’, in S. White (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Habermas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 318.
    • (1995) The Cambridge Companion to Habermas , pp. 318
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 38
    • 0008508852 scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Friendship
    • Jacques Derrida, ‘The Politics of Friendship’, Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988): 632–44.
    • (1988) Journal of Philosophy , vol.85 , pp. 632-644
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 44
    • 0004023381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Benhabib's version of discourse ethics, the participants of a moral practical discourse must eventually see each other as concrete others. Rather than emphasizing the universality of validity claims and of ideal consensus among ‘fictitiously defined selves’, Benhabib shows that universality is a concrete process of political and moral struggle where real subjects strive for autonomy
    • In Benhabib's version of discourse ethics, the participants of a moral practical discourse must eventually see each other as concrete others. Rather than emphasizing the universality of validity claims and of ideal consensus among ‘fictitiously defined selves’, Benhabib shows that universality is a concrete process of political and moral struggle where real subjects strive for autonomy (Benhabib, Situating the Self, pp. 152–3).
    • Situating the Self , pp. 152-153
    • Benhabib1
  • 45
    • 84998160905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Also Israel argues that ideal role-taking ought to be seen as based on language in order to avoid a subject philosophical framework; see, Stockholm: Natur och Kultur
    • Also Israel argues that ideal role-taking ought to be seen as based on language in order to avoid a subject philosophical framework; see (Joachim Israel, Martin Buber: dialogfilosof och sionist (Stockholm: Natur och Kultur, 2000), p. 140.
    • (2000) Martin Buber: dialogfilosof och sionist , pp. 140
    • Israel, J.1
  • 47


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.