-
1
-
-
0041540859
-
Survey article: Subsidiarity
-
Andreas Fllesdal, 'Survey Article: Subsidiarity', Journal of Political Philosophy 6(2) (1998): 190.
-
(1998)
Journal of Political Philosophy
, vol.6
, Issue.2
, pp. 190
-
-
Fllesdal, A.1
-
2
-
-
0031488661
-
Democracy, subsidiarity, and citizenship in the "European commonwealth"
-
Neil MacCormick, 'Democracy, Subsidiarity, and Citizenship in the "European Commonwealth"', Law and Philosophy 16(4) (1997): 331.
-
(1997)
Law and Philosophy
, vol.16
, Issue.4
, pp. 331
-
-
MacCormick, N.1
-
3
-
-
0040086210
-
The principle of subsidiarity and the court of justice as an institutional actor
-
Gráinne de Búrca, 'The Principle of Subsidiarity and the Court of Justice as an Institutional Actor', Journal of Common Market Studies 36(2) (1998): 217;
-
(1998)
Journal of Common Market Studies
, vol.36
, Issue.2
, pp. 217
-
-
De Búrca, G.1
-
4
-
-
77950891756
-
Subsidiarity: Is it too vague to be effective as a legal principle?
-
Kalypso Nicolaidis and Stephen Weatherill (eds.), (European Studies, Oxford University)
-
Derrick Wyatt, 'Subsidiarity: Is It Too Vague to be Effective As A Legal Principle?', in Kalypso Nicolaidis and Stephen Weatherill (eds.), Whose Europe? National Models and the Constitution of the European Union (European Studies, Oxford University, 2003).
-
(2003)
Whose Europe? National Models and the Constitution of the European Union
-
-
Wyatt, D.1
-
13
-
-
33750510084
-
Social pluralism and subsidiarity in catholic social doctrine
-
See, in particular, Russell Hittinger, 'Social Pluralism and Subsidiarity in Catholic Social Doctrine', Annales Theologici 16 (2002): 385;
-
(2002)
Annales Theologici
, vol.16
, pp. 385
-
-
Hittinger, R.1
-
14
-
-
85047727655
-
The subsidiary state: Society, the state and the principle of subsidiarity in catholic social thought
-
Jeanne Heffernan (ed.), (Lanham: Lexington Books, forthcoming)
-
Kenneth Grasso, 'The Subsidiary State: Society, the State and the Principle of Subsidiarity in Catholic Social Thought', in Jeanne Heffernan (ed.), Christianity and Civil Society: Catholic and Neo-Calvinixt Perspectives (Lanham: Lexington Books, forthcoming).
-
Christianity and Civil Society: Catholic and Neo-calvinixt Perspectives
-
-
Grasso, K.1
-
15
-
-
0004206697
-
-
(May 15), paras 12-14
-
Leo XIII, Rerum Novarum (May 15, 1891), paras 12-14;
-
(1891)
Rerum Novarum
-
-
Leo XIII1
-
18
-
-
7044254768
-
-
(Paris: Presses Universtaires de France), chapters 1, 3
-
Chantal Millon-Delsol, L'Etat Subsidiaire (Paris: Presses Universtaires de France, 1992), chapters 1, 3.
-
(1992)
L'Etat Subsidiaire
-
-
Millon-Delsol, C.1
-
19
-
-
0003643991
-
From confederacy to federation: Thoughts on the finality of European integration
-
Speech at Humboldt University, Berlin, 12 May 2000 and the discussion in C. Joerges, Y. Mény, and J.H.H. Weiler (eds.), (Florence)
-
Federalism, long an underlying theme, has recently re-emerged very prominently in the debate over the nature and future of the European Union. See Joschka Fischer, "From Confederacy to Federation: Thoughts on the Finality of European Integration', Speech at Humboldt University, Berlin, 12 May 2000 and the discussion in C. Joerges, Y. Mény, and J.H.H. Weiler (eds.), What Kind of Constitution for What Kind of Polity?: Responses to Joschka Fischer (Florence, 2000).
-
(2000)
What Kind of Constitution for What Kind of Polity?: Responses to Joschka Fischer
-
-
Fischer, J.1
-
20
-
-
1542282174
-
-
New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers
-
See, e.g., Daniel J. Elazar, Covenant and Commonwealth (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1996), 35.
-
(1996)
Covenant and Commonwealth
, pp. 35
-
-
Elazar, D.J.1
-
21
-
-
20444505499
-
The United States and the European Union: Models for their epochs
-
Kalypso Nicolaidis and Robert Howse (eds.), (Oxford University Press), 45
-
Elazar considered the principle of subsidiarity to be an attempt to 'moderate' the 'pronounced hierarchical tendencies' of Catholic social theory: see Daniel J. Elazar, 'The United States and the European Union: Models for Their Epochs' in Kalypso Nicolaidis and Robert Howse (eds.), The Federal Vision: Legitimacy and Levels of Governance in the United States and the European Union (Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 42, 45.
-
(2001)
The Federal Vision: Legitimacy and Levels of Governance in the United States and the European Union
, pp. 42
-
-
Elazar, D.J.1
-
22
-
-
84994884884
-
Complementarity and equality in the political thought of Thomas Aquinas
-
See also Paul J. Weithman, 'Complementarity and Equality in the Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas', Theological Studies 59(2) (1998): 277.
-
(1998)
Theological Studies
, vol.59
, Issue.2
, pp. 277
-
-
Weithman, P.J.1
-
23
-
-
84970785461
-
The rule of the wise and holy: Hierarchy in the thomistic system
-
394
-
Samuel Beer, 'The Rule of the Wise and Holy: Hierarchy in the Thomistic System'. Political Theory 14(3) (1986): 391, 394.
-
(1986)
Political Theory
, vol.14
, Issue.3
, pp. 391
-
-
Beer, S.1
-
30
-
-
84954838666
-
Hierarchy, consent, and the "Western tradition"
-
For a brief but trenchant criticism of Beer's arguments, see Brian Tierney, 'Hierarchy, Consent, and the "Western Tradition'", Political Theory 15(4) (1987): 646.
-
(1987)
Political Theory
, vol.15
, Issue.4
, pp. 646
-
-
Tierney, B.1
-
31
-
-
33750498309
-
-
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press), chapters I-1V
-
For a wide-ranging account of the theological, legal, social and philosophical context in which Aquinas worked, see Thomas Gilby, The Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), chapters I-1V.
-
(1958)
The Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas
-
-
Gilby, T.1
-
32
-
-
0039269780
-
Ideas and experience in the political thought of Thomas Aquinas
-
For the argument that Aquinas was considerably motivated by contemporary practical politics, see Jeremy Catto, 'Ideas and Experience in the Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas', Past and Present 71 (1976): 3.
-
(1976)
Past and Present
, vol.71
, pp. 3
-
-
Catto, J.1
-
33
-
-
0003434168
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Fora contrary view, see John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), pp. 1-3.
-
(1998)
Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory
, pp. 1-3
-
-
Finnis, J.1
-
35
-
-
33750497867
-
-
Frederick Carney (trans.), (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund)
-
For a translation, see Frederick Carney (trans.), Politica: An Abridged Translation (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1995).
-
(1995)
Politica: An Abridged Translation
-
-
-
36
-
-
0004020565
-
-
New York: Praeger
-
According to Carl Friedrich, it was when Althusius 'transformed' the medieval idea of a 'feudal hierarchy of successive levels of lords and vassals' into a thoroughly covenantal and federal model, that a truly modern, federal theory of politics emerged. See Carl J. Friedrich, Trends of Federalism in Theory and Practice (New York: Praeger, 1968), p. 12.
-
(1968)
Trends of Federalism in Theory and Practice
, pp. 12
-
-
Friedrich, C.J.1
-
37
-
-
33750511343
-
-
See Part IV below
-
See Part IV below.
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
33750509197
-
-
See text at notes 153-154 below
-
See text at notes 153-154 below.
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
0345816168
-
-
E.I. Watkin (trans.), (New York: Sheed & Ward, n.d.)
-
Jacques Maritain, An Introduction to Philosophy, E.I. Watkin (trans.), (New York: Sheed & Ward, n.d.), pp. 98-99;
-
An Introduction to Philosophy
, pp. 98-99
-
-
Maritain, J.1
-
43
-
-
84875305079
-
-
294-298, 320-331
-
Finnis, Aquinas, pp. 10-14, 294-298, 320-331.
-
Aquinas
, pp. 10-14
-
-
Finnis1
-
44
-
-
33645197065
-
-
(August 4), para. 18
-
See also Leo XIII, Æterni Patris (August 4, 1879), para. 18;
-
(1879)
Æterni Patris
-
-
Leo XIII1
-
45
-
-
33750495848
-
-
(November 20), para. 8
-
Paul VI, Lumen Ecclesiae (November 20, 1974), para. 8;
-
(1974)
Lumen Ecclesiae
-
-
Paul VI1
-
46
-
-
28244482739
-
-
(September 14), para. 43
-
John Paul II, Fides et ratio (September 14, 1998), para. 43.
-
(1998)
Fides et Ratio
-
-
Paul II, J.1
-
49
-
-
33750493944
-
"Truth does not contradict truth": Averroës and the unity of truth
-
On Averroës' actual teaching, however, see Richard C. Taylor, "'Truth Does Not Contradict Truth": Averroës and the Unity of Truth', Topoi 19 (2000): 3.
-
(2000)
Topoi
, vol.19
, pp. 3
-
-
Taylor, R.C.1
-
54
-
-
33750507740
-
-
1.3.2, 4
-
ScG, 1.3.2, 4: 'Some things true of God are beyond all the competence of human reason, as that God is Three and One. Other things there are to which even human reason can attain, as the existence and unity of God, which philosophers have proved to a demonstration under the guidance of the light of natural reason. ... There are, therefore, some points of intelligibility in God, accessible to human reason, and other points that altogether transcend the power of human reason.
-
ScG
-
-
-
55
-
-
33750522506
-
-
1.7.3
-
See ScG, 1.7.3, where Aquinas refers to the "knowledge of principles naturally known' which are "put into us by God' and compares them to those things divinely revealed in the books of the Old and New Testament. Implicit in Aquinas's reasoning is the important distinction between what is first in the order of being, and what is first in the order of human cognition.
-
ScG
-
-
-
56
-
-
33750523048
-
-
2.4.1
-
ScG, 2.4.1.
-
ScG
-
-
-
57
-
-
33750517568
-
-
2.4.2
-
Aquinas explains that philosophy begins with 'creatures in themselves' and from them progresses to 'the knowledge of God', whereas the 'system of faith' begins with God and progresses to the knowledge of creatures 'in relation to God': ScG, 2.4.2.
-
ScG
-
-
-
58
-
-
33750495407
-
-
2.4.1, 5
-
ScG, 2.4.1, 5.
-
ScG
-
-
-
59
-
-
5444262851
-
-
A.P. D'Entreves (ed.), translated by J.G. Dawson (Oxford: Blackwell)
-
For translations of Aquinas's political and legal writings generally, see A.P. D'Entreves (ed.), Thomas Aquinas: Selected Political Writings, translated by J.G. Dawson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1959);
-
(1959)
Thomas Aquinas: Selected Political Writings
-
-
-
60
-
-
0007485652
-
-
R.J. Regan and W.P. Baumgarth (eds.), (Indianapolis: Hackett)
-
R.J. Regan and W.P. Baumgarth (eds.), St. Thomas Aquinas: On Amy, Morality and Politics (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988);
-
(1988)
St. Thomas Aquinas: on Amy, Morality and Politics
-
-
-
61
-
-
33750528580
-
-
R.W. Dyson (ed.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
R.W. Dyson (ed.), Aquinas: Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)
-
(2002)
Aquinas: Political Writings
-
-
-
63
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.1, 1252a
-
Politics, I.1, 1252a.
-
Politics
-
-
-
64
-
-
33750518416
-
-
Stephen Everson (ed.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
have here used Stephen Everson (ed.), Aristotle: The Politics and The Constitution of Athens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)
-
(1996)
Aristotle: The Politics and the Constitution of Athens
-
-
-
66
-
-
33750498095
-
-
note
-
The fact that Aristotle referred specifically to the polis, and Aquinas refers interchangeably to the civitas, regnum and provincia, is a matter taken up below.
-
-
-
-
69
-
-
33750499774
-
Sententia libri ethicorum
-
Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae
-
and consulted Sententia Libri Ethicorum, in Opera, t. 47 (Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae, 1971).
-
(1971)
Opera
, vol.47
-
-
-
70
-
-
33750526490
-
-
I.2.13 [31]
-
Eth., I.2.13 [31].
-
Eth.
-
-
-
71
-
-
33750506322
-
-
1.2.13 [31]
-
Eth., 1.2.13 [31].
-
Eth.
-
-
-
72
-
-
33750498684
-
-
3.17
-
See, e.g., ScG, 3.17,
-
ScG
-
-
-
73
-
-
33750523657
-
The place of the state in society according to Aquinas
-
415
-
and compare Edgar Scully, 'The Place of the State in Society According to Aquinas', The Thomist 45 (1981): 407, 415.
-
(1981)
The Thomist
, vol.45
, pp. 407
-
-
Scully, E.1
-
74
-
-
84974489670
-
Aristotle's science of the best regime
-
On the status of religion and philosophy in Aristotle, compare Robert Bartlett, 'Aristotle's Science of the Best Regime', American Political Science Review 88(1) (1994): 143
-
(1994)
American Political Science Review
, vol.88
, Issue.1
, pp. 143
-
-
Bartlett, R.1
-
75
-
-
84974379618
-
Aristotle's science of the best regime
-
and Mary Nichols, 'Aristotle's Science of the Best Regime', American Political Science Review 89(1) (1995): 152.
-
(1995)
American Political Science Review
, vol.89
, Issue.1
, pp. 152
-
-
Nichols, M.1
-
78
-
-
33750495849
-
Commentum in quartum librum Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi
-
Parmae: Typis Petri Fiaccadori
-
and consulted Commentum in quartum librum Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi, in Opera, t. 7/2 (Parmae: Typis Petri Fiaccadori, 1858).
-
(1858)
Opera
, vol.7
, Issue.2
-
-
-
79
-
-
33750520377
-
-
11.44 ex. ad 4
-
Sent., 11.44 ex. ad 4.
-
Sent.
-
-
-
80
-
-
11244268365
-
St. Thomas Aquinas on the two powers
-
Curiously, Aquinas adds that this distinction does not apply where 'the spiritual and temporal power are identified in one person as in the Pope, whose power is supreme in matters both temporal and spiritual'. A possible interpretation is that Aquinas has in mind those territories in central Italy where the Pope was both supreme pontiff and temporal lord as a matter of positive law. However, Aquinas specifically relates the power of the Pope to the dispensation of Jesus Christ who is both priest and king: 'a priest forever according to the order of Melchisedech' and 'King of kings in Lord of lords'. Compare I. T. Eschmann, 'St. Thomas Aquinas on the Two Powers', Mediaeval Studies 20 (1958): 107;
-
(1958)
Mediaeval Studies
, vol.20
, pp. 107
-
-
Eschmann, I.T.1
-
81
-
-
33750523262
-
The de Regno and the two powers
-
J. Reginald O'Donnell (ed.), (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies)
-
Leonard Boyle, 'The De Regno and the Two Powers' in J. Reginald O'Donnell (ed.), Essays in Honour of Anton Charles Pegis (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974), pp. 237-247;
-
(1974)
Essays in Honour of Anton Charles Pegis
, pp. 237-247
-
-
Boyle, L.1
-
82
-
-
33750531883
-
Aristotle, Aquinas, and the ideal constitution
-
Brian Tierney, 'Aristotle, Aquinas, and the Ideal Constitution', Proceedings of the PMR Conference 4 (1979): 1;
-
(1979)
Proceedings of the PMR Conference
, vol.4
, pp. 1
-
-
Tierney, B.1
-
85
-
-
33750519487
-
Summae theologiae
-
Romae: Ex Typographia Polyglotta SC de Propaganda Fide
-
have relied principally on the translation of the Fathers of the English Dominican Province (London: Burns & Oates, 1947-1948) and the Blackfriars translation (London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1964-1976), and have consulted Summae Theologiae, in Opera, t. 4-12 (Romae: Ex Typographia Polyglotta SC de Propaganda Fide, 1888-1906).
-
(1888)
Opera
, vol.4
, Issue.12
-
-
-
86
-
-
33750520563
-
-
I-II, 98.1
-
ST, I-II, 98.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
87
-
-
33750507285
-
-
I-II, 105.1, 108.2; II-II, 10.9, 42.1, 60.6, 99.4, 147.3, 186.3
-
Temporal and spiritual jurisdiction is also discussed, e.g., in ST, I-II, 105.1, 108.2; II-II, 10.9, 42.1, 60.6, 99.4, 147.3, 186.3.
-
ST
-
-
-
88
-
-
84875305079
-
-
chapter 7
-
See, generally, Finnis, Aquinas, chapter 7.
-
Aquinas
-
-
Finnis1
-
91
-
-
0007147484
-
-
Gerald Phelan and I. Th. Eschmann (trans.), Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies
-
and consulted Gerald Phelan and I. Th. Eschmann (trans.), On Kingship, to the King of Cyprus, (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1949)
-
(1949)
On Kingship, to the King of Cyprus
-
-
-
92
-
-
33750495181
-
-
(Spiazzi, ed.) 2nd edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti
-
as well as the Latin edition in Opuscula philosophlca (Spiazzi, ed.) (2nd edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1954).
-
(1954)
Opuscula Philosophlca
-
-
-
93
-
-
33750525327
-
Dominium Regale et politicum: Sir John Fortescue's response to the problem of tyranny as presented by Thomas Aquinas and Ptolemy of Lucca
-
163, note 9
-
On the problems of authorship, structure and text, see the 'Introductions' by Blythe and Eschmann, as well as the references in Thomas Osborne, 'Dominium Regale et Politicum: Sir John Fortescue's Response to the Problem of Tyranny as presented by Thomas Aquinas and Ptolemy of Lucca' Mediaeval Studies 62 (2000): 161, 163, note 9.
-
(2000)
Mediaeval Studies
, vol.62
, pp. 161
-
-
Osborne, T.1
-
94
-
-
33750508355
-
-
1.16.2 [115]
-
De Regno, 1.16.2 [115].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
97
-
-
33750532986
-
What Aquinas should have said? Finnis's Reconstruction of Social and Political Thomism
-
A. S. McGrade, 'What Aquinas should have said? Finnis's Reconstruction of Social and Political Thomism'. American Journal of Jurisprudence 44 (1999): 125
-
(1999)
American Journal of Jurisprudence
, vol.44
, pp. 125
-
-
McGrade, A.S.1
-
98
-
-
33750524064
-
St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the political common good
-
and Lawrence Dewan, 'St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the Political Common Good', The Thomist 64 (2000): 337.
-
(2000)
The Thomist
, vol.64
, pp. 337
-
-
Dewan, L.1
-
99
-
-
34248541660
-
-
Bk. IV, 1299a3-19, 1322b18-29; Bk. VII, 1329a27-34
-
Compare Aristotle's conception of the priesthood as merely one among the many offices needed in a political community: Politics, Bk. IV, 1299a3-19, 1322b18-29; Bk. VII, 1329a27-34.
-
Politics
-
-
-
100
-
-
84933481556
-
The uniqueness of the political philosophy of Thomas Aquinas
-
See James Schall, The Uniqueness of the Political Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas', Perspectives in Political Science 26 (1997): 85.
-
(1997)
Perspectives in Political Science
, vol.26
, pp. 85
-
-
Schall, J.1
-
101
-
-
33750504693
-
-
See text at notes 84-86 below
-
See text at notes 84-86 below.
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
33750521813
-
Contra impugnantes dei cultum et Religionem
-
(Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae), ['Impugn.'], II.2, ad 9
-
Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et Religionem, in Opera, t. 41 (Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae, 1970), ['Impugn.'], II.2, ad 9.
-
(1970)
Opera
, vol.41
-
-
-
104
-
-
84875305079
-
-
note 31
-
See Finnis, Aquinas, 226, note 31,
-
Aquinas
, pp. 226
-
-
Finnis1
-
105
-
-
33750507963
-
-
II-II, 31.3 ad 3
-
who points out that the church, like the state, is a community whose good exceeds the good of families and individuals. See, e.g., ST, II-II, 31.3 ad 3 (the common good of the church or the state [communis utilitas Ecclesiae vel reipublicae] may override the good of a family); 43.8 (the goods of the church and the state require special treatment compared to those of individuals).
-
ST
-
-
-
107
-
-
84965369785
-
-
I.I, 1252a30-31
-
Politics, I.I, 1252a30-31.
-
Politics
-
-
-
109
-
-
0004020506
-
-
Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (eds.). (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, New York)
-
have here used Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (eds.). Medieval Political Philosophy: A Source Book (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, New York, 1963), pp. 298-334
-
(1963)
Medieval Political Philosophy: A Source Book
, pp. 298-334
-
-
-
110
-
-
33750520392
-
Sententia libri politicorum
-
Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae
-
and consulted Sententia libri Politicorum, in Opera, t. 48 (Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae, 1971).
-
(1971)
Opera
, vol.48
-
-
-
111
-
-
33750503453
-
The vulgate text of Aquinas's commentary on Aristotle's polities
-
On Aquinas's authorship of Books I, II and (part of) III of the Commentary, see Conor Martin, 'The Vulgate Text of Aquinas's Commentary on Aristotle's Polities', Dominican Studies 5 (1952): 35.
-
(1952)
Dominican Studies
, vol.5
, pp. 35
-
-
Martin, C.1
-
112
-
-
33750508787
-
-
pro. 3
-
Pol., pro. 3.
-
Pol.
-
-
-
113
-
-
33750531077
-
-
pro. 4
-
Pol., pro. 4.
-
Pol.
-
-
-
114
-
-
33750517338
-
-
pro. 7.
-
Pol., pro. 7.
-
Pol.
-
-
-
115
-
-
33750534007
-
-
II-II, 47.11
-
See likewise ST, II-II, 47.11;
-
ST
-
-
-
116
-
-
33750504061
-
-
1.2.7-11 [25-29], VI.7.1-3 [1195-1197], X.I6.2 [2165]
-
Eth., 1.2.7-11 [25-29], VI.7.1-3 [1195-1197], X.I6.2 [2165].
-
Eth.
-
-
-
117
-
-
33750517320
-
-
1.1.2
-
On the architectonic arts generally, see ScG, 1.1.2;
-
ScG
-
-
-
120
-
-
0009568144
-
-
Richard J. Blackwell, Richard J. Spath and W. Edmund Thirlkel (trans.), (New Haven: Yale University Press)
-
have used Richard J. Blackwell, Richard J. Spath and W. Edmund Thirlkel (trans.), Commentary on Aristotle's Physics by St. Thomas Aquinas (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1963)
-
(1963)
Commentary on Aristotle's Physics by St. Thomas Aquinas
-
-
-
122
-
-
33750528588
-
-
1.2.13 [31]
-
See Eth., 1.2.13 [31] , discussed in the text at notes 34-38 above.
-
Eth.
-
-
-
124
-
-
33750523047
-
-
II, 44.1.2, s.c.
-
See Sent., II, 44.1.2, s.c.
-
Sent.
-
-
-
125
-
-
33750501619
-
-
II, 44.1.2, co.
-
Sent., II, 44.1.2, co.
-
Sent.
-
-
-
126
-
-
33750504694
-
-
II, 44.2.2, s.c.
-
Sent., II, 44.2.2, s.c.,
-
Sent.
-
-
-
127
-
-
33750514635
-
-
citing Romans 13:2.
-
Romans
, vol.13
, pp. 2
-
-
-
128
-
-
33750533189
-
-
II, 44.2.2, co. and ad 4, 5
-
Sent., II, 44.2.2, co. and ad 4, 5.
-
Sent.
-
-
-
129
-
-
33750498309
-
-
146-158
-
For a further discussion of resistance to tyranny, see the text at notes 177, 194-195 below. For an interpretation which emphasises the 'development' in Aquinas's thought on these questions, see Gilby, Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas. 90-106, 146-158,
-
Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas
, pp. 90-106
-
-
Gilby1
-
130
-
-
84875305079
-
-
but compare Finnis, Aquinas, 287-291.
-
Aquinas
, pp. 287-291
-
-
Finnis1
-
131
-
-
33750495406
-
-
II-II, 42.2, 66.8 ad 3, 69.4, 104.6 ad 3
-
See, further, ST, II-II, 42.2, 66.8 ad 3, 69.4, 104.6 ad 3;
-
ST
-
-
-
132
-
-
33750499317
-
S. Thomae Aquinatis super Epistolas S. Pauli Lectura
-
Raphael Cai (ed.), (Taurini-Romae: Marietti)
-
Raphael Cai (ed.), S. Thomae Aquinatis Super Epistolas S. Pauli Lectura, t. 1: Super Epistolam ad Romanos, (8th edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1953), 13.1.
-
(1953)
Super Epistolam ad Romanos, (8th Edn.)
, vol.1
-
-
-
133
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.1-2, 1252a18-22, 1252b10-18, 28-31
-
Politics, I.1-2, 1252a18-22, 1252b10-18, 28-31.
-
Politics
-
-
-
134
-
-
34248541660
-
-
III.9, 1280b34-5, 1280b40
-
As Aristotle later put it, the polis is a community of households and clans, and a union of clans and villages: Politics, III.9, 1280b34-5, 1280b40.
-
Politics
-
-
-
135
-
-
34248541660
-
-
1.2, 1252b12-13, 16-17, 28-31
-
Politics, 1.2, 1252b12-13, 16-17, 28-31.
-
Politics
-
-
-
136
-
-
34248541660
-
-
1.2, 1253a. 18-29
-
Politics, 1.2, 1253a. 18-29.
-
Politics
-
-
-
137
-
-
34248541660
-
-
1.2, 1253a2-3; III.6, 1278b19-20
-
Politics, 1.2, 1253a2-3; III.6, 1278b19-20.
-
Politics
-
-
-
138
-
-
33750526913
-
-
1.9.10-11 [112-113]
-
Thus in Eth., 1.9.10-11 [112-113], Aquinas says that Aristotle's treatment of man's natural sociability 'must be understood within limits' - that Aristotle's discussion only pertains to 'happiness as it is attainable in this life, for happiness in a future life is entirely beyond the investigation of reason'.
-
Eth.
-
-
-
139
-
-
33750497490
-
St. Thomas Aquinas
-
Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey (eds.), University of Chicago Press
-
Compare Ernest Fortin, "St. Thomas Aquinas,' in Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey (eds.), History of Political Philosophy (3rd edn. University of Chicago Press, 1987).
-
(1987)
History of Political Philosophy (3rd Edn.)
-
-
Fortin, E.1
-
143
-
-
33750516751
-
Thomistic social philosophy and the theology of original sin
-
29-34
-
Eschmann, 'Thomistic Social Philosophy and the Theology of Original Sin', Medieval Studies 9 (1947): 19, 29-34.
-
(1947)
Medieval Studies
, vol.9
, pp. 19
-
-
Eschmann1
-
144
-
-
33750501423
-
-
I.1.5 [5]
-
Eth., I.1.5 [5].
-
Eth.
-
-
-
145
-
-
84875305079
-
-
See the discussion in Finnis, Aquinas, 24-25.
-
Aquinas
, pp. 24-25
-
-
Finnis1
-
146
-
-
33750509448
-
-
I.1, 1094al-18
-
Ethics, I.1, 1094al-18.
-
Ethics
-
-
-
147
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.1, 1252a17-23
-
It should be noted, however, that Aristotle begins the Politics with an analysis of the city-state understood as a 'whole' which is a 'compound' of 'parts': Politics, I.1, 1252a17-23.
-
Politics
-
-
-
148
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.2, 1252b15-16, 27-30, 1253a15-18; II.2, 1261b6-15
-
The idea that households have operations that are independent of the state is afRrmed by Aristotle. See Politics, I.2, 1252b15-16, 27-30, 1253a15-18; II.2, 1261b6-15.
-
Politics
-
-
-
149
-
-
33750531476
-
-
I-II, 72.4
-
See, e.g., ST, I-II, 72.4;
-
ST
-
-
-
151
-
-
33750506742
-
-
I.1.3 [4]
-
Also 'social and political' in De Regno, I.1.3 [4]
-
De Regno
-
-
-
152
-
-
33750513852
-
-
III.85.11
-
and 'political or social' in ScG, III.85.11.
-
ScG
-
-
-
153
-
-
33750516135
-
-
Jean T. Oesterle (trans.), Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press
-
have here used Jean T. Oesterle (trans.), Aristotle on Interpretation: Commentary by St. Thomas and Cajetan (Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press, 1962).
-
(1962)
Aristotle on Interpretation: Commentary by St. Thomas and Cajetan
-
-
-
154
-
-
33750507962
-
-
I, 96.4; I-II, 61.5, 95.4; II-II, 109.3, 114.2, 129.6, 188.8; III, 65.1
-
?' See, e.g., ST, I, 96.4; I-II, 61.5, 95.4; II-II, 109.3, 114.2, 129.6, 188.8; III, 65.1;
-
ST
-
-
-
155
-
-
33750513862
-
-
III.117.4, 128.1, 129.5, 131.4, 147.2
-
ScG, III.117.4, 128.1, 129.5, 131.4, 147.2;
-
ScG
-
-
-
156
-
-
33750522505
-
-
1.1.4 [4], VII.6.7 [1391]
-
Eth., 1.1.4 [4]), VII.6.7 [1391];
-
Eth.
-
-
-
157
-
-
33750502272
-
-
I.13.2 [94]
-
De Regno, I.13.2 [94].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
158
-
-
33750530866
-
-
I.1.24, 26, 28 [32, 34, 36]; III.5 [387]
-
Pol., I.1.24, 26, 28 [32, 34, 36]; III.5 [387]).
-
Pol.
-
-
-
159
-
-
33750523673
-
-
I.9.10 [112], VIII.12 [1719-1720], IX.10.7 [1891]
-
See also Eth., I.9.10 [112], VIII.12 [1719-1720], IX.10.7 [1891]
-
Eth.
-
-
-
162
-
-
33750527378
-
-
Chicago: Henry Regnery Company
-
For the latter works, I have used Robert W. Mulligan, S. J., St. Thomas Auinas: Truth (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1952)
-
(1952)
St. Thomas Auinas: Truth
-
-
Mulligan, R.W.1
-
164
-
-
33750494358
-
-
See the references at notes 70-71 above
-
See the references at notes 70-71 above.
-
-
-
-
165
-
-
33750515904
-
-
I-II, 72.4 ('political and social' animal); I-II, 95.4, II-II, 188.8 ('social' animal)
-
E.g., ST, I-II, 72.4 ('political and social' animal); I-II, 95.4, II-II, 188.8 ('social' animal).
-
ST
-
-
-
166
-
-
33750528770
-
-
I 96.4
-
ST, I 96.4. Aquinas's argument is that human beings are naturally 'social', so that even before the fall they would have lived in "society", although they would not have been subject to 'political' coercion. Aquinas's tendency to refer to the 'social' nature of human beings may possibly reflect his endeavour to synthesise the Augustinian account of the origin of human dominion in original sin with the Aristotelian idea that politics is natural to humanity.
-
ST
-
-
-
167
-
-
33750500738
-
-
II, 44.1.3
-
See, however, Sent., II, 44.1.3, where Aquinas distinguishes two modes of sovereignty (duplex est praelationis modus), one for guidance (ad regimen ordinales), the other for domination (ad dominandum). The former, he says, would have existed in the state of innocence, but the not the latter. For interpretations,
-
Sent.
-
-
-
168
-
-
33750526265
-
Two conceptions of political authority: Augustine, de Civitate Dei, XIX14-15, and some thirteenth-century interpretations
-
New Series 16
-
compare R. A. Markus, 'Two Conceptions of Political Authority: Augustine, De Civitate Dei, XIX. 14-15, and Some Thirteenth-Century Interpretations', Journal of Theological Studies, New Series 16 (1965): 68
-
(1965)
Journal of Theological Studies
, pp. 68
-
-
Markus, R.A.1
-
169
-
-
0040117670
-
Augustine and Aquinas on original sin and the function of political authority
-
and Paul J. Weithman, 'Augustine and Aquinas on Original Sin and the Function of Political Authority', Journal of the History of Philosophy 30(3) (1992): 353.
-
(1992)
Journal of the History of Philosophy
, vol.30
, Issue.3
, pp. 353
-
-
Weithman, P.J.1
-
170
-
-
33750508772
-
-
1.1.29 [37]
-
Pol., 1.1.29 [37].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
171
-
-
33750512181
-
-
VIII.12.18 (1719-1720)
-
See also Eth., VIII.12.18 (1719-1720),
-
Eth.
-
-
-
172
-
-
34248541660
-
-
Bk. 1.1-2
-
where the conjugal (conjugale) nature of human beings is said to be more fundamental than our political nature. It is true that Aristotle likewise compares the household to the polis. Both are forms of 'community' (koinonia), he says, and both are 'natural' (Politics, Bk. 1.1-2).
-
Politics
-
-
-
173
-
-
78751642821
-
-
VIII.12, 1162a17-19
-
Aristotle also says that human beings are 'naturally inclined to form couples - even more than to form cities, inasmuch as the household is earlier and more necessary than the city': Nicomachean Ethics, VIII.12, 1162a17-19. However, Aristotle never actually defines humankind specifically as a 'domestic animal'; human nature, according to him, is definitively 'political'.
-
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
-
175
-
-
25844523262
-
-
Compare Walter Ullmann's emphasis on the 'political' aspect of Aquinas's thought (A History of Political Thought, 175)
-
A History of Political Thought
, pp. 175
-
-
-
176
-
-
0004152399
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, chapters 4-10
-
with Hannah Arendt's emphasis on the 'social' (The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), chapters 4-10).
-
(1958)
The Human Condition
-
-
-
177
-
-
0040860987
-
Celestial hierarchies revisited: Walter Ullmann's vision of medieval polities
-
32-44
-
For a critique of Ullmann's interpretation of Aquinas, see Francis Oakley, 'Celestial Hierarchies Revisited: Walter Ullmann's Vision of Medieval Polities', Past and Present 60 (1973): 3, 32-44.
-
(1973)
Past and Present
, vol.60
, pp. 3
-
-
Oakley, F.1
-
178
-
-
0004265971
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press, chapter 4
-
For a critique of Arendt's interpretation of Aristotle (with implications for her interpretation of Aquinas), see Stephen Salkever, Finding the Mean (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990), chapter 4.
-
(1990)
Finding the Mean
-
-
Salkever, S.1
-
180
-
-
33750510519
-
-
contrasts Aquinas's respect for social groups with the 'well nigh all-inclusive' nature of Aristotle's polis, but suggests, at 214, that Aquinas's respect for the free association of social groups was Aristotelian in inspiration. Scully, 'The Place of the State in Society According to Aquinas,'
-
The Place of the State in Society According to Aquinas
-
-
Scully1
-
181
-
-
84875305079
-
-
chapter VII
-
underscores the interdependence of the social and the political. Finnis, Aquinas, chapter VII,
-
Aquinas
-
-
Finnis1
-
182
-
-
33750528436
-
-
357-361
-
limits the political to the provision of a specifically political common good, public and limited, strictly supplemental to the distinctive contribution to the common good provided by other social groups, such as families and private associations. Against this, Dewan, 'St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the Political Common Good', 339, 357-361, argues for the primacy of the political. My point, simply, is that Aquinas placed greater emphasis on society than did Aristotle, as suggested by his repeated references to the 'social' nature of human beings.
-
St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the Political Common Good
, pp. 339
-
-
Dewan1
-
183
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.1, 1252b28-30
-
Politics, I.1, 1252b28-30.
-
Politics
-
-
-
184
-
-
33750500244
-
-
1.2.4 [14]
-
De Regno, 1.2.4 [14].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
185
-
-
85043064639
-
-
Franciscus Susemihl (ed.). Leipzig
-
William of Moerbeke's translation of the Politics, which Aquinas uses, translated Aristotle's polis (city-state) as civitas, oikia (household) as damns or familias, and kôrnê (village) as viens. See Franciscus Susemihl (ed.). Politicorum libri octo cum vetusta translatione guilelmi de moerbeke (Leipzig, 1872).
-
(1872)
Politicorum Libri octo cum Vetusta Translatione Guilelmi de Moerbeke
-
-
-
186
-
-
33750523656
-
-
Carolus Zell (ed.), 2 vols (Heidelberg: Mohr and Winter)
-
For the translation of the Ethics by Robert Grosseteste, as revised by an anonymous redactor, probably William of Moerbeke, see Carolus Zell (ed.), Ethicorum nichomacheorum libri decem, 2 vols (Heidelberg: Mohr and Winter, 1820).
-
(1820)
Ethicorum Nichomacheorum Libri Decem
-
-
-
187
-
-
33750495866
-
-
I.1.3 [11], I.1.7-9 [15-17], I.1.23-25 [31-33], I.1.30-32 [38-40]
-
Pol., I.1.3 [11], I.1.7-9 [15-17], I.1.23-25 [31-33], I.1.30-32 [38-40];
-
Pol.
-
-
-
188
-
-
33750497650
-
-
I-II, 90.3 ad 3, II-II, 47.11, 50.1
-
ST, I-II, 90.3 ad 3, II-II, 47.11, 50.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
189
-
-
33750515905
-
-
1.2.4 [14]
-
De Regno, 1.2.4 [14].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
191
-
-
84884082485
-
St. Thomas and the decretal of innocent IV Romana Ecclesia: Ceterum
-
9
-
note f. For a list of medieval (and Thomistic) terms for various kinds of 'community', see I. Th. Eschmann, 'St. Thomas and the Decretal of Innocent IV Romana Ecclesia: Ceterum, Medieval Studies 8 (1946): 1, 9. They include: universitas, communitas, societas. consociatio, collegium, corpus, congregatio, collectio, multitudo, respublica, regnum, gens, populus, civitas, villa, viens, hurgum, castrum, castellum, familia, ecclesia, capitulum and inonasterium.
-
(1946)
Medieval Studies
, vol.8
, pp. 1
-
-
Eschmann, I.Th.1
-
192
-
-
33750501177
-
-
I-II, 91.1, 21.4, 100.5
-
ST, I-II, 91.1, 21.4, 100.5;
-
ST
-
-
-
193
-
-
33750520760
-
-
I.42, 70 71, 78, 85 86, 93, 102, II.39, 42, III.64, 98
-
ScG, I.42, 70 71, 78, 85 86, 93, 102, II.39, 42, III.64, 98.
-
ScG
-
-
-
194
-
-
33750511341
-
-
I.1.3 [11]
-
Pol., I.1.3 [11].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
195
-
-
33750527800
-
-
1.1.7-9 [15-17]
-
Aquinas repeatedly refers to the 'falsity' of the equation of household and city, comparing this false view with the 'true relationship' of the household and the city: Pol., 1.1.7-9 [15-17].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
196
-
-
33750520376
-
-
II, 5.1 res.
-
However, see Quaestiones de qiiodlibet, II, 5.1 res., where Aquinas compares the authority of a father over a family and a king over a realm: 'Since obedience is due a superior, the duty of obedience is extended as far as his authority. Now a father of the flesh first has authority over a child with regard to domestic life, for the head of the family is related to the home as a king to a realm; hence just as the king's subjects are bound to obey him in those matters which pertain to the government of the realm, so are children and other domestic members bound to obey the head of the family in those matters which pertain to the management of the home.'
-
Quaestiones de Qiiodlibet
-
-
-
197
-
-
33750498093
-
-
Sandra Edwards (trans.) Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies
-
have here used Sandra Edwards (trans.), St. Thomas Aquinas: Quodlibetal Questions I and 2 (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1983)
-
(1983)
St. Thomas Aquinas: Quodlibetal Questions 1 and 2
-
-
-
198
-
-
84875286298
-
-
(Spiazzi ed.) 9th edn. Taurino: Marietti
-
and consulted Quaestiones quodlibetales (Spiazzi ed.) (9th edn. Taurino: Marietti, 1956).
-
(1956)
Quaestiones Quodlibetales
-
-
-
199
-
-
33750534196
-
-
I.1.23-5, [31-3, 38-40]
-
Pol., I.1.23-5, 30-32 [31-3, 38-40]. Moreover, when expositing Aristotle's views relating to the superiority of the polis over the household, Aquinas does not hesitate to repeat the Aristotelian dictum that it is in politics that one must determine the instruction of children and women.
-
Pol.
, pp. 30-32
-
-
-
200
-
-
33750530405
-
-
See Pol., I:11.6.
-
Pol.
, vol.1
-
-
-
201
-
-
84922546766
-
-
II.2, ad 10
-
However, also to be considered is the discussion in Contra impugnantes, II.2, ad 10
-
Contra Impugnantes
-
-
-
202
-
-
33750501825
-
-
Proctor, I.3
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.3, p. 94),
-
Apology
, pp. 94
-
-
-
203
-
-
84923275102
-
-
II, 5.1 res.
-
where Aquinas affirms that education is a responsibility of the republic, but adds that for this reason within the church education must be subject to the authority of the Apostolic See. Compare, also. Quaestiones de quodlibetes, II, 5.1 res., affirming the authority of a father in respect of the moral education (morum disciplinant) of his children.
-
Quaestiones de Quodlibetes
-
-
-
204
-
-
33750518618
-
-
I-II
-
S T, I-II, 90-114.
-
ST
, pp. 90-114
-
-
-
205
-
-
33750533006
-
-
I-II, 90.3 ad 3
-
ST, I-II, 90.3 ad 3. The translation of civitas as 'state' (or 'political community') seems to be warranted by the context, although in other contexts it is better translated 'city' in order to distinguish it from the 'province' (provincia) or 'kingdom' (regnum). See the text at notes 144-152 below.
-
ST
-
-
-
206
-
-
33750509648
-
-
II-II
-
ST, II-II, 47-122.
-
ST
, pp. 47-122
-
-
-
207
-
-
33750525542
-
-
II-II, 47.11; 50.1
-
ST, II-II, 47.11; 50.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
208
-
-
33750518619
-
-
II-II, 50.1
-
ST, II-II, 50.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
209
-
-
33750531680
-
-
II-II, 50.1
-
ST, II-II, 50.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
210
-
-
33750515903
-
-
I.2.4 [14]
-
De Regna, I.2.4 [14].
-
De Regna
-
-
-
211
-
-
33750519290
-
-
1.2.4 [14]
-
De Regno, 1.2.4 [14].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
212
-
-
0004085243
-
-
Frederick Maitland (trans.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
Compare Otto von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age, Frederick Maitland (trans.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968), p. 96: The polis or civitas ... was discovered by medieval Philosophy in a medieval town, and, by virtue of the ideal of the organic structure of the whole Human Race, the community of this polis or civitas was subordinated to a regnum and the to the Imperium ... Thus, no sooner has the medieval thinker given his definition [of the civitas], than he is withdrawing it without the slightest embarrassment: his superlative becomes a comparative, and the absolute becomes relative.'
-
(1968)
Political Theories of the middle Age
, pp. 96
-
-
Von Gierke, O.1
-
214
-
-
33750507508
-
-
Proctor, 1.4
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.4, p. 128), Aquinas refers to "cities', 'villages' and "hamlets' (civitas, vieux, villis).
-
Apology
, pp. 128
-
-
-
217
-
-
33750498890
-
-
1.1.23 [31]
-
"[I]n one [vieux], the weaver's, in another the smith's', he says. See Pol., 1.1.23 [31].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
219
-
-
33750519486
-
-
1868 repr.; Graz: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt
-
interacting critically with Otto von Gierke, Das deutsche Genossenschaftsrecht, vol. 1 (1868 repr.; Graz: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt, 1954).
-
(1954)
Das Deutsche Genossenschaftsrecht
, vol.1
-
-
Von Gierke, O.1
-
221
-
-
0004032916
-
-
Moreover, craftsmen and merchants traded on the basis of a developing lex mercatoria, which had its origin in the practices and expectations of traders, and not simply in the positive laws of the cities and realms in which they lived. On the autonomy of the law of merchants, see Berman, Law and Revolution, 333-356.
-
Law and Revolution
, pp. 333-356
-
-
Berman1
-
222
-
-
0039950931
-
-
London, (quoted in Berman, 342)
-
Gerard Malynes, in the Preface to his Consuetudo vel Lex Mercatoria, or the Ancient Law Merchant (London, 1622) (quoted in Berman, 342), considered that the lex mercatoria 'is customary law approved by the authority of all kingdoms and commonweals, and not a law established by the sovereignty of any prince'.
-
(1622)
The Preface to His Consuetudo Vel Lex Mercatoria, or the Ancient Law Merchant
-
-
Malynes, G.1
-
224
-
-
0008697795
-
-
See Black, Guilds and Civil Society, 132-142, who (at 132) describes Althusius's theory as 'perhaps the most substantial exposition of guild ideas ever known'.
-
Guilds and Civil Society
, pp. 132-142
-
-
Black1
-
225
-
-
1542426839
-
-
508/7-ca. 250 B.C.: A Political and Social Study (Princeton: Princeton University Press)
-
See the discussion of the reforms of Cleisthenes in the Constitution of Athens (Everson, ed.), XX-XXII. In fact, the demes and phulai of Athens possessed significant powers of self-government. See David Whitehead, The Demes of Attica, 508/7-ca. 250 B.C.: A Political and Social Study (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986).
-
(1986)
The Demes of Attica
-
-
Whitehead, D.1
-
226
-
-
0008697795
-
-
See Black, Guilds and Civil Society, 76-85, who remarks at 84: '[P]hilosophers saw social personality only in terms of family and state, domesticity and formal politics. A whole range of actual socio-political life vanishes into the air whenever we look at a work of political theory. Was this gulf a price paid for the classical heritage?'
-
Guilds and Civil Society
, pp. 76-85
-
-
Black1
-
228
-
-
33750523851
-
-
II.2
-
Impugn., II.2
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
229
-
-
33750510924
-
-
Proctor. 1.3
-
(Proctor. Apology, 1.3).
-
Apology
-
-
-
231
-
-
33750527799
-
-
II.2, co
-
Impugn., II.2, co
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
232
-
-
33750522271
-
-
Proctor, 1.3
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.3, p. 88).
-
Apology
, pp. 88
-
-
-
233
-
-
33750513851
-
-
II.2, co
-
Impugn., II.2, co
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
234
-
-
33750510518
-
-
Proctor, 1.3
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.3, p. 87).
-
Apology
, pp. 87
-
-
-
235
-
-
33750504259
-
-
II.2, ad 1
-
Impugn., II.2, ad 1
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
236
-
-
33750517566
-
-
Proctor, 1.3
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.3, pp. 88-9).
-
Apology
, pp. 88-89
-
-
-
237
-
-
33750511560
-
-
II.2, ad 2
-
Impugn., II.2, ad 2
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
238
-
-
33750495402
-
-
Proctor, 1.3
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.3, pp. 89-90).
-
Apology
, pp. 89-90
-
-
-
239
-
-
33750497865
-
-
11.2, ad 3
-
Impugn., 11.2, ad 3
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
240
-
-
33750502452
-
-
Proctor, 1.3
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.3, p. 90).
-
Apology
, pp. 90
-
-
-
241
-
-
34248541660
-
-
II.2, III.9
-
Even though the idea of dual citizenship existed in classical Greece, Aristotle treats citizenship as an exclusive relationship between an individual and his city-state. See Politics, II.2, III.9
-
Politics
-
-
-
243
-
-
33750493963
-
-
I.2
-
More precisely, Aquinas represents Aristotle as holding this view: De Veritate, 5.3 co. While Aristotle certainly understood the Hellenic nation (for example) to be a much wider category than the individual city-state of Ancient Greece, he certainly did not elevate the good of the nation over and above the good of the city-state. See Ethics, I.2, 1094b7-11.
-
Ethics
-
-
-
244
-
-
33750526694
-
-
I.14.5 [100]
-
De Regno, I.14.5 [100].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
245
-
-
33750514841
-
-
II.15.4
-
See, likewise, ScG, II.15.4, where Aquinas compares the universal governance of a king within his kingdom to the subordinate role of the king's wardens within each city.
-
ScG
-
-
-
246
-
-
33750531880
-
-
Jean Oesterle (trans.), University of Notre Dame Press
-
See, similarly, De Malo, I.1 res.: 'the ruler of a city intends a particular good which is the good of the city, but the king, who is his superior, intends a universal good, the peace of the whole kingdom'. I have here used Jean Oesterle (trans.), St. Thomas Aquinas: On Evil (University of Notre Dame Press, 1993)
-
(1993)
St. Thomas Aquinas: on Evil
-
-
-
247
-
-
33750533990
-
-
(Bazzi. et al., eds.) 9th edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti
-
and consulted the Latin edition in Quaestiones disputatae, t. 2 (Bazzi. et al., eds.) (9th edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1953).
-
(1953)
Quaestiones Disputatae
, vol.2
-
-
-
248
-
-
33750525113
-
-
III.98.1
-
SeG, III.98.1.
-
SeG
-
-
-
249
-
-
33750501409
-
-
II-II, 50.3 arg.
-
Compare ST, II-II, 50.3 arg., stating that the household is part of a city or kingdom, thus treating city and kingdom as interchangeable, rather than the city as a constituent element of the kingdom.
-
ST
-
-
-
250
-
-
33750522504
-
-
I, 22.1 res.
-
See also ST, I, 22.1 res., discussing the government of an individual, a family, a city or a kingdom.
-
ST
-
-
-
251
-
-
33750532110
-
-
1.2.4-6 [14-15] (civitax vel provinda, etc.).
-
De Regno, 1.2.4-6 [14-15] (civitax vel provinda, etc.).
-
De Regno
-
-
-
252
-
-
33750532326
-
-
1.2.3 [12]; 1.3.1 [16]; 1.3.5 [20]; 1.4.8 [28]
-
For further references, see De Regno, 1.2.3 [12]; 1.3.1 [16]; 1.3.5 [20]; 1.4.8 [28].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
253
-
-
33750509863
-
-
1.10.1 [68], 1.14.2 [98], 1.15.1 [102], 1.16.5 [119], 11.1.1 [123] (civ it as vel regnum, etc.)
-
See, e.g., De Regno, 1.10.1 [68], 1.14.2 [98], 1.15.1 [102], 1.16.5 [119], 11.1.1 [123] (civ it as vel regnum, etc.)
-
De Regno
-
-
-
254
-
-
0041071497
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Compare C.N.S. Woolf, Bartolus of Sassoferrato: His Position in the Political Thought of his Time (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1913), pp. 274-275: 'we find in Aquinas the view that the Provincia is a more perfect community, because more self-sufficient, than the Civitas, as the Civitas is more self-sufficient than the Vicus... [I]t was only a small step further to see the culmination of this hierarchy of States in a universal Imperium, the finally most self-sufficient and perfect community.'
-
(1913)
Bartolus of Sassoferrato: His Position in the Political Thought of His Time
, pp. 274-275
-
-
Woolf, C.N.S.1
-
255
-
-
84883989593
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 44ff.
-
On the nascent national kingdoms of the thirteenth century, see Joseph Strayer, On the Medieval Origins of the Modern State (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), pp. 44ff.
-
(1970)
On the Medieval Origins of the Modern State
-
-
Strayer, J.1
-
256
-
-
33750514066
-
-
1.10.1 [68], 1.14.2 [98], 1.15.1 [102], 1.16.5 [119], II.1.1 [123]
-
De Regno, 1.10.1 [68], 1.14.2 [98], 1.15.1 [102], 1.16.5 [119], II.1.1 [123];
-
De Regno
-
-
-
257
-
-
33750501609
-
-
I-II, 96.5 res.
-
ST, I-II, 96.5 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
259
-
-
0004314389
-
-
Horace L. Jones (trans.) (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Loeb Classical Library)
-
See, e.g., Stabo, Geography, Horace L. Jones (trans.) (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Loeb Classical Library, 1932), XVII.3.25;
-
(1932)
Geography
-
-
Stabo1
-
261
-
-
33750531879
-
-
Dist. III, Pt. 2; Dist. XVII. Pt. 1, Ord. G1.; Dist. XII, c. 13, §3; Dist. XVII, Pt. 2, §2; Dist. XVIII, Pt. 1, Ord. Gl.
-
See Gratian, Decretum, Dist. III, Pt. 2; Dist. XVII. Pt. 1, Ord. G1.; Dist. XII, c. 13, §3; Dist. XVII, Pt. 2, §2; Dist. XVIII, Pt. 1, Ord. Gl.
-
Decretum
-
-
Gratian1
-
262
-
-
33750531881
-
Decretum magistri gratiani
-
Aemilius Friedberg (ed.), Leipzig
-
have here used Aemilius Friedberg (ed.), Decretum Magistri Gratiani in Corpus luris Canonici, 2 vols (Leipzig, 1879-1881)
-
(1879)
Corpus Luris Canonici, 2 Vols
-
-
-
263
-
-
84895679990
-
-
Augustine Thomson and James Gordley (eds.), Washington: Catholic University of America Press
-
and Augustine Thomson and James Gordley (eds.), The Treatise on Laws: Decretum Dist. 1-20, with the Ordinary Gloss (Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1993).
-
(1993)
The Treatise on Laws: Decretum Dist. 1-20, with the Ordinary Gloss
-
-
-
264
-
-
84922546766
-
-
II.2-3
-
Aquinas's familiarity with canon law is amply displayed, e.g., in Contra impugnantes, II.2-3
-
Contra Impugnantes
-
-
-
265
-
-
33750527798
-
-
Proctor, 1.3-4
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.3-4).
-
Apology
-
-
-
266
-
-
33750495403
-
-
note 23
-
Eschmann, On Kingship, 10, note 23, observes that 'nothing is very definite about this notion except that... a province is part of a greater and more comprehensive whole'.
-
Kingship
, pp. 10
-
-
Eschmann1
-
267
-
-
84875305079
-
-
On the involvement of Aquinas's own family in the historical confrontations between emperor and pope of his day, see Finnis, Aquinas, 1-3
-
Aquinas
, pp. 1-3
-
-
Finnis1
-
269
-
-
33750498889
-
-
Notably, Eschmann, 'Thomistic Social Philosophy', 49, argues that for Aquinas, the only genuinely universal human community is the ecclesia.
-
Thomistic Social Philosophy
, pp. 49
-
-
Eschmann1
-
270
-
-
33750522290
-
-
I-II, 19.5, 96.5; II-II, 69.3, 104.5.
-
ST, I-II, 19.5, 96.5; II-II, 69.3, 104.5.
-
ST
-
-
-
271
-
-
33750522270
-
-
II.3.12 [112]. For other examples of Aquinas's occasional references to the emperor, see Scriptum super Sententiis, II, 44.4.4
-
Compare De Regno, II.3.12 [112]. For other examples of Aquinas's occasional references to the emperor, see Scriptum super Sententiis, II, 44.4.4
-
De Regno
-
-
-
272
-
-
33750516338
-
-
(see Dyson, Aquinas, 277-278);
-
Aquinas
, pp. 277-278
-
-
Dyson1
-
274
-
-
33750497480
-
-
II.3, co.
-
Impugn., II.3, co.
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
275
-
-
33750521186
-
-
Proctor, I.4
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4).
-
Apology
-
-
-
276
-
-
33750533426
-
-
I-II, 96.5 res.
-
ST, I-II, 96.5 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
277
-
-
33750533989
-
-
I.102 and III.98.
-
See, e.g., ScG, I.102 and III.98.
-
ScG
-
-
-
278
-
-
33750505904
-
-
I-II, 91.1.
-
ST, I-II, 91.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
279
-
-
33750496255
-
-
I-II, 21.4 (totius communitatis universi)
-
Compare the references in ST, I-II, 21.4 (totius communitatis universi)
-
ST
-
-
-
280
-
-
33750521600
-
-
I-II, 100.5 (communitatem seu republicam homi num sub Deo)
-
and ST, I-II, 100.5 (communitatem seu republicam homi num sub Deo);
-
ST
-
-
-
281
-
-
33750506537
-
-
I, 103.1-8
-
and see ST, I, 103.1-8,
-
ST
-
-
-
282
-
-
33750525541
-
-
I.42, 70-71, 78, 85-86, 93, 102, II.39, 42, III.64, 98; Mem., II.12.12 [2663]
-
ScG, I.42, 70-71, 78, 85-86, 93, 102, II.39, 42, III.64, 98; Mem., II.12.12 [2663].
-
ScG
-
-
-
283
-
-
33750509647
-
-
I, 108.1-8 and 112.1-4
-
See ST, I, 108.1-8 and 112.1-4, where Aquinas describes a graded hierarchy of angels, fulfilling the will of God.
-
ST
-
-
-
284
-
-
33750519067
-
-
I, 108.1
-
ST, I, 108.1;
-
ST
-
-
-
285
-
-
33750494981
-
-
11.3
-
cf. Impugn., 11.3
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
286
-
-
33750515902
-
-
Proctor, 1.4
-
(Proctor, Apology, 1.4).
-
Apology
-
-
-
287
-
-
33750498889
-
-
Note, also, Eschmann, Thomistic Social Philosophy', 37-38, 46-48, who argues that Aquinas deliberately refrains from concluding that Adam was in any sense created 'king' or 'head' of the entire human race.
-
Thomistic Social Philosophy
, pp. 37-38
-
-
Eschmann1
-
288
-
-
0004085243
-
-
Compare Dante, De Monarchia, (c. 1312), I:3ff.
-
Otto von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age, 20-21. Compare Dante, De Monarchia, (c. 1312), I:3ff., discussing the government of the household, village, city, kingdom and empire.
-
Political Theories of the middle Age
, pp. 20-21
-
-
Von Gierke, O.1
-
289
-
-
0040888299
-
-
Donald Nicholl (trans.), London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson
-
have here used Donald Nicholl (trans.), Monarchy, and Three Political Letters (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1954), pp. 10-11.
-
(1954)
Monarchy, and Three Political Letters
, pp. 10-11
-
-
-
290
-
-
0004030815
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
As James Blythe, Ideal Government and the Mixed Constitution in the Middle Ages (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 46, puts it, there was a need to adjust a theory that presupposed a relative wide and direct political participation (Aristotle) to a context in which monarchical rule was the norm and representative institutions were typical.
-
(1992)
Ideal Government and the Mixed Constitution in the middle Ages
, pp. 46
-
-
Blythe, J.1
-
291
-
-
33748360758
-
Feudalism
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See, likewise, Paul Vinogradoff, 'Feudalism,' in Cambridge Medieval History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1924), Vol. III, p. 458.
-
(1924)
Cambridge Medieval History
, vol.3
, pp. 458
-
-
Vinogradoff, P.1
-
293
-
-
33750531879
-
-
Dist. X, c. 1, Ord. Gl
-
See also Gratian, Decretum, Dist. X, c. 1, Ord. Gl.
-
Decretum
-
-
Gratian1
-
295
-
-
33750506970
-
Roman law and early representation in Spain and Italy, 1150-1250
-
Philadelphia: Princeton University Press
-
Gaines Post, 'Roman Law and Early Representation in Spain and Italy, 1150-1250', in Studies in Medieval Legal Thought, Public Law and the State, 1100-1322 (Philadelphia: Princeton University Press, 1964), pp. 61-62.
-
(1964)
Studies in Medieval Legal Thought, Public Law and the State, 1100-1322
, pp. 61-62
-
-
Post, G.1
-
296
-
-
33750531879
-
-
Dist. I, c. 12, Ord. Gl.; Dist. XI, Pt. 1, Ord. Gl.; Dist. XI, c. 2, Ord. Gl.; Dist. XI, c. 8; Dist. XII, c. 3 and c. 11; Dist. XVIII, Pt. 1, Ord. Gl.
-
See, e.g., Gratian, Decretum, Dist. I, c. 12, Ord. Gl.; Dist. XI, Pt. 1, Ord. Gl.; Dist. XI, c. 2, Ord. Gl.; Dist. XI, c. 8; Dist. XII, c. 3 and c. 11; Dist. XVIII, Pt. 1, Ord. Gl.
-
Decretum
-
-
Gratian1
-
302
-
-
0041997750
-
-
London: Longman
-
On corporate representation generally, see James Brundage, Medieval Canon Law (London: Longman, 1955), pp. 106-108, 110
-
(1955)
Medieval Canon Law
, pp. 106-108
-
-
Brundage, J.1
-
307
-
-
33750520394
-
A conciliar theory of the thirteenth century
-
Brian Tierney, 'A Conciliar Theory of the Thirteenth Century,' Catholic Historical Review 36 (1951-52) 415, 429-431;
-
(1951)
Catholic Historical Review
, vol.36
, pp. 415
-
-
Tierney, B.1
-
314
-
-
33750505031
-
Roots of a democratic church polity in the history of canon law
-
Charles Reid, "Roots of a Democratic Church Polity in the History of Canon Law', CLSA Proceedings 60 (1998): 150;
-
(1998)
CLSA Proceedings
, vol.60
, pp. 150
-
-
Reid, C.1
-
316
-
-
33750520578
-
Bishops and their dioceses
-
Kenneth Pennington, 'Bishops and their Dioceses', Folia canonica 5 (2002): 7;
-
(2002)
Folia Canonica
, vol.5
, pp. 7
-
-
Pennington, K.1
-
319
-
-
33750531879
-
-
Dist. XVII, Pt. 3, Ord. Gl.
-
and Gratian, Decretum, Dist. XVII, Pt. 3, Ord. Gl.
-
Decretum
-
-
Gratian1
-
323
-
-
33750531879
-
-
Dist. XI c. 9, Dist. XVII c. 6, Dist. XV c. 2, Dist. IX c. 9 and Dist. XXIV c. 6
-
For examples, see Gratian, Decretum, Dist. XI c. 9, Dist. XVII c. 6, Dist. XV c. 2, Dist. IX c. 9 and Dist. XXIV c. 6.
-
Decretum
-
-
Gratian1
-
328
-
-
33750511365
-
-
John of Salisbury, V.2, 6, 9.
-
For an example, see John of Salisbury, Policraticus (1159), V.2, 6, 9.
-
Policraticus
, Issue.1159
-
-
-
329
-
-
0040267076
-
-
Cary Nederman (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
have used Cary Nederman (ed.), Policraticus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
-
(1991)
Policraticus
-
-
-
332
-
-
33750499335
-
-
I.2.4 [14]
-
Thus, either a city, a kingdom or a province can constitute a perfect community: De Regno, I.2.4 [14];
-
De Regno
-
-
-
333
-
-
33750531898
-
-
I-II, 90.3 ad 3
-
see also ST, I-II, 90.3 ad 3.
-
ST
-
-
-
336
-
-
33750506333
-
Status, id est, magistratus: L'etat, c'est moi
-
and Post, 'Status, id est, Magistratus: L'Etat, c'est Moi', in Studies in Medieval Legal Thought, 345-348.
-
Studies in Medieval Legal Thought
, pp. 345-348
-
-
Post1
-
338
-
-
33750496268
-
-
21.4 ad 3, 96.1, 100.2
-
referring to ST I-II, 21.4 ad 3, 96.1, 100.2;
-
ST I-II
-
-
-
339
-
-
33750534208
-
-
V.2.4 [903]
-
Eth. V.2.4 [903];
-
Eth.
-
-
-
340
-
-
33750496269
-
-
1.1.3, 33 [11, 41], 11.8.6 [259], 111.6.5 [395]
-
Pol. 1.1.3, 33 [11, 41], 11.8.6 [259], 111.6.5 [395].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
341
-
-
33750524466
-
-
I-II, 100.2
-
In ST, I-II, 100.2, Aquinas distinguishes various kinds of 'community' [diversu modu coinmunitatum] - first as between cities ruled either by a king, by the people, or by a few powerful men - and in turn between the civil community [communitates civilis] and 'men ... in community with God' [homines ... ad comtnunicationem cum Deo].
-
ST
-
-
-
343
-
-
33750506125
-
-
III.1.3, 8 [350, 355]
-
Pol., III.1.3, 8 [350, 355],
-
Pol.
-
-
-
344
-
-
0004080299
-
-
III.1 1274b38, 1275b20
-
See Aristotle, Politics, III.1 1274b38, 1275b20.
-
Politics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
345
-
-
33750497491
-
-
III.2.6 [362]
-
Pol., III.2.6 [362].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
346
-
-
33750534010
-
-
1.2.3 [12]; 1.2.6 [15]; 1.3.1 [16]; 1.3.5 [20]; II.1.1-2 [123-4].
-
As noted earlier, see, e.g., De Regno, 1.2.3 [12]; 1.2.6 [15]; 1.3.1 [16]; 1.3.5 [20]; II.1.1-2 [123-4].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
347
-
-
33750510102
-
-
I-II, 96.5; II-II, 47.11; 50.1, 3
-
But see, also, 5T, I-II, 96.5; II-II, 47.11; 50.1, 3;
-
ST
-
-
-
348
-
-
33750497888
-
-
1.1.21 [29]; III.5.4 [387]
-
Pol., 1.1.21 [29]; III.5.4 [387],
-
Pol.
-
-
-
349
-
-
33750513864
-
-
II-II, 40.1 res.
-
and compare ST, II-II, 40.1 res. (civitatis vel regni seu provinciae).
-
ST
-
-
-
350
-
-
0039269782
-
-
(Blythe ed.), II.8.1; II. 10.1 and II.15.1
-
It is notable that Ptolemy of Lucca, De Regimine Principum (Blythe ed.), II.8.1; II. 10.1 and II.15.1, takes the progression even further, identifying 'a region, province, city or town', 'any association, province, city or town' and 'a kingdom, province, city or any other rule' as the objects of his inquires. The terminological progression in De Regno is in this respect interesting.
-
De Regimine Principum
-
-
-
351
-
-
33750506760
-
-
I.2.3 [12]
-
The expression "city or province' is first used as it were accidentally in De Regno, I.2.3 [12] when Aquinas is discussing the 'polity' or the virtuous rule of the many.
-
De Regno
-
-
-
352
-
-
33750519919
-
-
I.2.4 [14]
-
In earlier passages, he tends to use relatively generic terms such as 'community' (communitas) 'multitude' (multitudinis) and 'people' (populus) - but it is in a section soon following 1.2.3 [12] that Aquinas differentiates household, neighborhood, city and province (De Regno, I.2.4 [14]). It might be conjectured whether the Greek term 'polity' suggested a reference to the city (civitas), together with a felt need to add the term province (provincia). One might then wonder whether this conjunction of thoughts precipitated the idea of adapting the idea of Aristotelian self-suffciency to the medieval household, neighbourhood, city and province.
-
De Regno
-
-
-
353
-
-
33750533619
-
-
Louvain: Éditions Nauwelaerts
-
Georges de Lagarde, La naissance de l'espirit laïque au déclin du moyen age, Tome II: Secteur Social de la Scolastique (Louvain: Éditions Nauwelaerts, 1958), p. 80. I wish to thank Jean-Marc Berthoud for this translation.
-
(1958)
Tome II: Secteur Social de la Scolastique
, pp. 80
-
-
-
355
-
-
33750524898
-
Law and polities
-
in Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (eds.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Compare Paul Sigmund, 'Law and Polities', in Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Aquinas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
-
(1993)
The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Aquinas
-
-
Sigmund, P.1
-
357
-
-
9744284451
-
-
London: Routledge
-
Compare Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003), pp. 314-316.
-
(2003)
Aquinas
, pp. 314-316
-
-
Stump, E.1
-
358
-
-
33750511781
-
The history of freedom in christianity
-
London: Macmillan and Co
-
See also Lord Acton, 'The History of Freedom in Christianity', in The History of Freedom and Other Essays (London: Macmillan and Co, 1907), pp. 36-37;
-
(1907)
The History of Freedom and Other Essays
, pp. 36-37
-
-
Acton, L.1
-
359
-
-
0004161626
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, note 4
-
Friedrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), p. 457, note 4.
-
(1978)
The Constitution of Liberty
, pp. 457
-
-
Hayek, F.1
-
360
-
-
33750506758
-
-
I-II, 95.4 res.
-
ST, I-II, 95.4 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
361
-
-
33750496967
-
-
III.5.4 [387]
-
Pol., III.5.4 [387].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
362
-
-
33750499334
-
-
I-II, 105.1 res.
-
ST, I-II, 105.1 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
363
-
-
84921774914
-
-
1.3.1 [16]; cf. II. 1.1-2 [123-4]
-
De Regno, 1.3.1 [16]; cf. II. 1.1-2 [123-4].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
364
-
-
33750534008
-
-
III.5.7 [390]
-
Pol., III.5.7 [390].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
365
-
-
33750527613
-
-
III.6.3 [393]
-
Pol., III.6.3 [393].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
366
-
-
0001541675
-
The vulgate text of aquinas's commentary on aristotle's
-
50-52
-
On the transliteration of these Greek terms into the Latin of William of Morebeke and Aquinas, see Martin, "The Vulgate Text of Aquinas's Commentary on Aristotle's Politics,'' 39-40, 50-52.
-
Politics
, pp. 39-40
-
-
Martin1
-
367
-
-
33750504696
-
-
III.6.4 [394]
-
Pol., III.6.4 [394].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
368
-
-
33750526071
-
-
II.7.4 [245], discussed at notes 179 and 208 below
-
Although see Pol., II.7.4 [245], discussed at notes 179 and 208 below.
-
Pol.
-
-
-
369
-
-
33750505717
-
-
III.6.4 [394]
-
Pol., III.6.4 [394].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
370
-
-
33750517341
-
-
III.6.6-8 [396-398]
-
Pol., III.6.6-8 [396-398].
-
Pol.
-
-
-
371
-
-
33750511782
-
-
IV.76.4
-
ScG, IV.76.4.
-
ScG
-
-
-
372
-
-
34248541660
-
-
III13, 1284a4-7, 1284b32-34; III.17, 1288a 15-29
-
Politics, III.13, 1284a4-7, 1284b32-34; III.17, 1288a 15-29.
-
Politics
-
-
-
373
-
-
33750520186
-
-
I.1.1-7 [2-9].
-
De Regno, I.1.1-7 [2-9].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
374
-
-
33750505241
-
-
I.1 [2]; I.3.1-3 [17-18]; I.15.2-3 [103-104]
-
Aquinas is attracted to the metaphor of a pilot directing a ship towards its harbour: De Regno, I.1 [2]; I.3.1-3 [17-18]; I.15.2-3 [103-104].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
375
-
-
33750519302
-
-
I.3.1-3 [15-18]
-
De Regno, I.3.1-3 [15-18].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
376
-
-
33750500964
-
-
I.2.1-3 [10-13]
-
De Regno, I.2.1-3 [10-13].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
377
-
-
33750529789
-
-
I.4.1-2 [21-23]
-
De Regno, I.4.1-2 [21-23].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
378
-
-
33750493962
-
-
I.4.3 [24]
-
De Regno, I.4.3 [24].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
379
-
-
84888089561
-
-
I.4.4 [25]. Individuals, he suggests, will prevent and impede one another from pursuing their own ends
-
De Regno, I.4.4 [25]. Individuals, he suggests, will prevent and impede one another from pursuing their own ends.
-
De Regno
-
-
-
380
-
-
33750532775
-
-
I.3.4 [19]; I.4.4 [25]
-
De Regno, I.3.4 [19]; I.4.4 [25].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
381
-
-
33750515070
-
-
I.6.1-2 [36-38]
-
De Regno, I.6.1-2 [36-38].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
382
-
-
33750525554
-
-
I-II, 96.5 ad 3
-
See also Aquinas's treatment of Ulpian's famous text, 'the prince is not bound by the laws' (princeps legibus solutus est) in ST, I-II, 96.5 ad 3. Aquinas argues that while the prince is not subject to the coercive force of his own laws because there is no one to pass sentence upon him, he remains subject to its directive power, in line with the teaching of Christ and the law of the Church.
-
ST
-
-
-
391
-
-
33750512195
-
-
1.7.10 [51]
-
De Regno, 1.7.10 [51].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
392
-
-
33750504063
-
-
The apparent inconsistency between what Aquinas says about monarchy and the mixed regime has long been the subject of controversy. See Francisco de Vitoria, Lectiones in ST, I-II 90-105 De Lege, in
-
Lectiones in ST, I-II 90-105 De Lege
-
-
De Vitoria, F.1
-
393
-
-
0012705807
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Vitoria, Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p. 198. Vitoria argued that when Aquinas and Aristotle conclude that monarchy is best they did so considering the matter 'per se', whereas when they later expressed a preference for a mixed regime they were taking into consideration 'circumstances and persons'. This explanation is not without merit. Aristotle was very explicit in distinguishing the question of what system of government is best in the abstract, what is best for most cities, and what is best for any particular city.
-
Political Writings
, pp. 198
-
-
Vitoria1
-
394
-
-
34248541660
-
-
IV.1, 1288b21-39; IV.1, 1289b14-20; IV.11, 1295a25-31, 1296b3-11; IV.12, 1296b12-14; VII.4, 1325b34-37, 1334a
-
See Politics IV.1, 1288b21-39; IV.1, 1289b14-20; IV.11, 1295a25-31, 1296b3-11; IV.12, 1296b12-14; VII.4, 1325b34-37, 1334a.
-
Politics
-
-
-
395
-
-
33750530418
-
-
II.7.4 [245], commenting on Politics, II.6 1265b34-40
-
Pol., II.7.4 [245], commenting on Politics, II.6 1265b34-40,
-
Pol.
-
-
-
397
-
-
84875305079
-
-
See also Finnis, Aquinas, 261-262.
-
Aquinas
, pp. 261-262
-
-
Finnis1
-
398
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.1, 1252a.15-16
-
Politics, I.1, 1252a.15-16.
-
Politics
-
-
-
400
-
-
84928847054
-
Family, government, and the medieval aristotelians
-
See also James Blythe, 'Family, Government, and the Medieval Aristotelians', History of Political Thought 10 (1989): 1;
-
(1989)
History of Political Thought
, vol.10
, pp. 1
-
-
Blythe, J.1
-
401
-
-
33750526914
-
The mixed constitution and the distinction between regal and political power in the work of Thomas Aquinas
-
James Blythe, The Mixed Constitution and the Distinction between Regal and Political Power in the Work of Thomas Aquinas', Journal of the History of Ideas 47 (1986): 547.
-
(1986)
Journal of the History of Ideas
, vol.47
, pp. 547
-
-
Blythe, J.1
-
402
-
-
34248541660
-
-
I.1, 1252a.15-16
-
Politics, I.1, 1252a.15-16, translated by William of Moerbeke as: 'when according to the rules of the discipline one is in part both ruling and subject it is political'. Compare the translation of Jowett: 'when, according to the rules of the political science, the citizens rule and are ruled in turn, then he [the ruler] is called a statesman', with the more ambiguous translation of Lord: 'in political [rule] one who, on the basis of the precepts of this sort of science, rules and is ruled in turn'.
-
Politics
-
-
-
403
-
-
33750533620
-
-
Everson (ed.)
-
See Everson (ed.), Politics, 11;
-
Politics
, pp. 11
-
-
-
404
-
-
0004080299
-
-
Carnes Lord (trans.), (Chicago University of Chicago Press)
-
Carnes Lord (trans.), The Politics (Chicago University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 35;
-
(1984)
The Politics
, pp. 35
-
-
-
407
-
-
33750518434
-
-
I-II, 105.1 res., discussed at notes 208-229 below
-
For ease of expression, I will generally use the term 'democracy' in its modern sense to refer to simply to government by the many, without any necessary implication of corruption. Aquinas himself sometimes uses the term democratia, rather than politia, to designate the good form of government by the many. See ST, I-II, 105.1 res., discussed at notes 208-229 below.
-
ST
-
-
-
410
-
-
33750517805
-
-
Blythe points out that Aquinas's disciple. Peter of Auvergne, 'shows little sympathy for Thomas's distinction between regal and political rule.' and therefore seems 'to oscillate between support for a mixed constitution and support for a hereditary king': Blythe. Mixed Constitution, 78-79.
-
Mixed Constitution
, pp. 78-79
-
-
Blythe1
-
411
-
-
33750502683
-
-
IV.76.4
-
ScG, IV.76.4.
-
ScG
-
-
-
413
-
-
0009127814
-
Aspects ecclésiologiques de la querelle entre mendicants et séculiers dans la seconde moité du XIIIe Siécle et le début du XIVe
-
Yves Congar. 'Aspects Ecclésiologiques de la querelle entre Mendicants et Séculiers dans la Seconde Moité du XIIIe Siécle et le Début du XIVe', Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age 36 (1961): 35;
-
(1961)
Archives d'Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age
, vol.36
, pp. 35
-
-
Congar, Y.1
-
416
-
-
33750511573
-
-
Henry Bettenson (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
'The Church is a unity; yet by her fruitful increase she is extended far and wide to form a plurality ...'. I have here used the translation in Henry Bettenson (ed.), Documents of the Christian Church (2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), pp. 71-73.
-
(1967)
Documents of the Christian Church 2nd Edn.
, pp. 71-73
-
-
-
417
-
-
33750496453
-
-
I.1.3 [4]; II.1.1 [123]
-
E.g., De Regno, I.1.3 [4]; II.1.1 [123].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
418
-
-
33750521390
-
-
I.2.4 [14]
-
De Regno, I.2.4 [14].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
419
-
-
33750516351
-
-
I.2.5-6 [14-15]; I.3.1 [17]; I.3.5 [20]
-
E.g., De Regno, I.2.5-6 [14-15]; I.3.1 [17]; I.3.5 [20].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
420
-
-
33750500017
-
-
IV.76.4
-
ScG, IV.76.4.
-
ScG
-
-
-
421
-
-
80053456658
-
-
Mary Larkin (trans.) (St. Louis: Herder), chapter 6
-
The constitutional structure of Aquinas's own Dominican Order supports this interpretation. The order consisted of convents and provinces, governed, respectively, by conventual and provincial priors and a master-general, in conjunction with representative provincial chapters and a general chapter of the entire order. See Pierre Mandonnet, St. Dominic and His Work, Mary Larkin (trans.) (St. Louis: Herder, 1948), chapter 6;
-
(1948)
St. Dominic and His Work
-
-
Mandonnet, P.1
-
422
-
-
33750500749
-
Order of preachers
-
New York: Appleton
-
Pierre Mandonnet, 'Order of Preachers,' in The Catholic Encyclopedia (New York: Appleton, 1907-1912);
-
(1907)
The Catholic Encyclopedia
-
-
Mandonnet, P.1
-
428
-
-
33750520577
-
-
I.4.7 [27]
-
De Regno, I.4.7 [27].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
429
-
-
33750511572
-
-
I.7.1-12 [41-52]
-
De Regno, I.7.1-12 [41-52],
-
De Regno
-
-
-
430
-
-
33750507964
-
-
I.7.10-12 [51]
-
As noted earlier, if no human remedy is available, the only recourse left for private individuals is to entreat the intervention of God: De Regno I.7.10-12 [51].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
431
-
-
84875305079
-
-
287-291
-
Notably, the examples of divine intervention in the Bible that Aquinas cites involve the kings of Egypt, Babylon and Persia - paradigms of tyrannical government far removed the biblical ideal. See, also. Finnis, Aquinas, 275-279, 287-291. who discerns in Aquinas a private right of resistance, in at least some circumstances.
-
Aquinas
, pp. 275-279
-
-
Finnis1
-
434
-
-
33750517339
-
Aquinas on political obedience and disobedience
-
84
-
Richard Regan, 'Aquinas on Political Obedience and Disobedience', Thought 56 (1981): 77, 84.
-
(1981)
Thought
, vol.56
, pp. 77
-
-
Regan, R.1
-
435
-
-
33750515294
-
-
I.7.6-9 [47-50]
-
De Regno, I.7.6-9 [47-50].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
437
-
-
33750500355
-
-
John Patrick Reid (trans.), Providence: Providence College Press
-
res. I have here used John Patrick Reid (trans.), St. Thomas Aquinas On the Virtues in General (Providence: Providence College Press, 1951)
-
(1951)
St. Thomas Aquinas on the Virtues in General
-
-
-
438
-
-
33750505718
-
-
(Bazzi, et al., eds.) (9th edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti)
-
and consulted the Latin edition in Quaestiones disputatae, t. 2 (Bazzi, et al., eds.) (9th edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1953).
-
(1953)
Quaestiones Disputatae
, vol.2
-
-
-
440
-
-
0003705390
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
'The legitimate power of the [medieval] king was the fruit of a hundred pacts solemnly entered upon by princes and subjects, themselves represented by a thicket of institutions which were the work of generations and even centuries of common experience.' On this question, compare M. J. Wilks, The Problem of Sovereignty in the Later Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963), pp. 129-134;
-
(1963)
The Problem of Sovereignty in the Later middle Ages
, pp. 129-134
-
-
Wilks, M.J.1
-
441
-
-
33750532122
-
The relationship of theories of universals to theories of church government in the middle ages: A critique of previous views
-
Charles Zuckerman, 'The Relationship of Theories of Universals to Theories of Church Government in the Middle Ages: A Critique of Previous Views'. Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (1975): 579;
-
(1975)
Journal of the History of Ideas
, vol.36
, pp. 579
-
-
Zuckerman, C.1
-
443
-
-
33750516972
-
-
I-II, 95.4 and 105.1
-
ST, I-II, 95.4 and 105.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
444
-
-
1842517376
-
-
W. M. Lindsay (ed.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press), V.4-10
-
Isidore, Etymologiae, W. M. Lindsay (ed.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1911), V.4-10.
-
(1911)
Etymologiae
-
-
Isidore1
-
445
-
-
33750528785
-
-
VIII.9-10 1060a30-1161b10
-
Ethics, VIII.9-10 1060a30-1161b10;
-
Ethics
-
-
-
446
-
-
34248541660
-
-
IV.3-4 1294a30-b41
-
Politics, IV.3-4 1294a30-b41.
-
Politics
-
-
-
447
-
-
33750533821
-
-
I-II, 95.4 res
-
ST, I-II, 95.4 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
449
-
-
33750528437
-
-
I-II, 105.1
-
That is, without reading it in the context of ST, I-II, 105.1, discussed below.
-
ST
-
-
-
450
-
-
34248541660
-
-
IV.8, 1293b33-37, 1294a15-25; V.7, 1307a5-14
-
See Politics, IV.8, 1293b33-37, 1294a15-25; V.7, 1307a5-14.
-
Politics
-
-
-
452
-
-
33750525838
-
-
'Introductio', II, p. 19: 'it will not be absurd to call English laws leges, though they are unwritten, since whatever has been rightly decided and approved with the counsel and consent of the magnates and the general agreement of the res publica, the authority of the king or prince having first been added thereto, has the force of law'. (Sednon erit absurdum leges Anglicanas licet non scriptas leges appellare, cum legis vigorem habeat quidquid de consilio et consensu magnatum et rei publicæ communi sponsione, auctoritate regis sive principle præcedente, iuste fuerit definitum et approbatum.)
-
Introductio
, vol.2
, pp. 19
-
-
-
453
-
-
33750519496
-
-
I-II 105.1
-
ST I-II 105.1
-
ST
-
-
-
454
-
-
33750514638
-
-
II.74 [245]
-
See, likewise, Pol. II.74 [245], describing a mixed regime in which rule is shared among the people, the powerful and the king (puta si in aliquot dominetur populus, in aliquot potentes, in aliquot rex).
-
Pol.
-
-
-
455
-
-
84965368096
-
The right order of polity and economy: Reflections on St. Thomas and the "Old Law'
-
See James Schall. 'The Right Order of Polity and Economy: Reflections on St. Thomas and the "Old Law"', Cultural Dynamics 5(7) (1995): 427.
-
(1995)
Cultural Dynamics
, vol.5
, Issue.7
, pp. 427
-
-
Schall, J.1
-
456
-
-
33750511364
-
-
I-II, 105.1
-
In ST, I-II, 105.1, Aquinas cites or alludes to no less than 21 biblical texts. On the use of the Bible in medieval political theory,
-
ST
-
-
-
458
-
-
33750506335
-
-
pro. 7
-
See Pol., pro. 7
-
Pol.
-
-
-
459
-
-
33750514419
-
-
I.2.13 [31] discussed in the text at notes 36-37 and 54 above
-
and Eth., I.2.13 [31] discussed in the text at notes 36-37 and 54 above.
-
Eth.
-
-
-
460
-
-
33750510536
-
-
I-II, 105.1, Aristotle is cited on four occasions
-
In ST, I-II, 105.1, Aristotle is cited on four occasions.
-
ST
-
-
-
461
-
-
34248541660
-
-
II.6 1270b17
-
Politics, II.6 1270b17.
-
Politics
-
-
-
462
-
-
34248541660
-
-
III.5 1279a32
-
Politics, III.5 1279a32.
-
Politics
-
-
-
463
-
-
33750531290
-
-
I-II, 105.1 res
-
ST, I-II, 105.1 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
464
-
-
33750514189
-
-
I-II, 105.1 ad 3
-
Although note that in ST, I-II, 105.1 ad 3, Aquinas accepts the proposition that a divided kingdom leads to destruction.
-
ST
-
-
-
466
-
-
33750521616
-
-
I-II, 105.1 res
-
ST, I-II, 105.1 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
467
-
-
0004080299
-
-
IV.15, 1300a34-7
-
See Aristotle, Politics, IV.15, 1300a34-7: '
-
Politics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
468
-
-
33750528436
-
-
that all should ... appoint from all ... is characteristic of a polity'. Dewan, 'St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the Political Common Good', 356, note 27, points out that while the term 'king' suggests to us a hereditary office, Aquinas has an elected office in mind. The idea of a 'choice' or 'election' of the ruler is made explicit in De Regno and the Summa Theologiae, and in the Summa Contra Gentiles, where Aquinas is discussing the Pope, he is by definition writing about an elected office, albeit an office chosen by a 'few' (the college of cardinals). The office of Emperor, as well as many offices within the religious orders and universities, was also elective.
-
St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the Political Common Good
, pp. 356
-
-
Dewan1
-
469
-
-
33750513665
-
-
I.3.4 [19], I.4.4 [25], discussed in the text at note 173 above
-
Compare De Regno, I.3.4 [19], I.4.4 [25], discussed in the text at note 173 above.
-
De Regno
-
-
-
470
-
-
33750529180
-
-
I-II, 105.1 ad 2, emphasis added
-
ST, I-II, 105.1 ad 2, emphasis added.
-
ST
-
-
-
471
-
-
33750502684
-
-
I-II, 105.1 ad 2
-
ST, I-II, 105.1 ad 2.
-
ST
-
-
-
473
-
-
33750494999
-
-
I-II, 98-105
-
it 'seems indisputable' that Aquinas is 'recommending this form of government as best absolutely, and not just as one suited only to the Jews.' This, however, seems to overstate the case. Aquinas's primary concern in ST, I-II, 98-105, is theological, not political. The wider issue he is grappling with has to do with the status of the Old Law after the coming of Christ and the Gospel. Of the Old Law, Aquinas has said that it consists of moral, ceremonial and judicial precepts (Q.99.1-5). He has affirmed that the moral precepts of the Old Law belong to the law of nature (Q.100.1), that they concern acts of virtue (Q.100.2) and that they are not dispensable (Q.100.8). On the other hand, Aquinas has said that the ceremonial and judicial precepts are divinely inspired 'determinations' (cf Q.95.2 and 95.4) of the moral precepts, whereby man is directed to God and to his neighbour (Q.99.4). The ceremonial and judicial precepts, each being figurative (Q.102.2, Q.104.2), have ceased or been annulled at the coming of Christ (Q.103:3, Q.104:3). Nevertheless, the judicial precepts are figurative in a different sense and have been annulled in a different way, so that while the observance of the ceremonial precepts is a mortal sin (Q.103.4), the observance of the judicial precepts is not deadly, if understood as a determination of the natural and moral law - and not 'as though they derived their binding force through being institutions of the Old Law' (Q.104.2). Aquinas also explains that the determinations of the law must be different according to the different 'states of mankind' or different 'forms of government' under which people may live (Q.104:3). (It would of course be anomalous to seek to apply this last distinction - viz 'forms of government' - to the very question of whether the constitution of Israel embodied the best form of government) Aquinas's discussion in Q.105 must be understood in this context. The constitution of Israel is set forth by Aquinas as an 'ideal polity' strictly in the sense of a divinely inspired determinatio. The application of the enduring principles of natural law to Aquinas's own circumstances will depend, therefore, on the extent to which the different 'states of mankind' call for different 'determinations'. Interestingly, while in other areas (e.g., Q.105.2 ad 1-4, 10) Aquinas points to relevant differences in the states of mankind, he makes no such observation in respect of the constitution of Israel in Q.105.1.
-
ST
-
-
-
474
-
-
33750502273
-
-
See Schall. 'The Right Order of Polity and Economy', who argues that Aquinas understood the revelation contained in the Old Law to provide an illumination of philosophical questions which could not be completely addressed by philosophers on the basis of reason alone.
-
The Right Order of Polity and Economy
-
-
Schall1
-
475
-
-
33750508371
-
-
I-II, 105.1 res
-
ST, I-II, 105.1 res.
-
ST
-
-
-
476
-
-
33750498114
-
Aquinas's regimen bene commixtum and the medieval critique of classical republicanism
-
212-214
-
John Kayser and Ronald Lettieri, 'Aquinas's Regimen Bene Commixtum and the Medieval Critique of Classical Republicanism', The Thomist 46 (1982): 195, 212-214 point out that in looking to biblical Israel, rather than the Roman republic, Aquinas made a decisive break with the Polybian tradition. However, their argument is overstated in one important particular: while Aquinas is certainly dismissive of the Roman republic in
-
(1982)
The Thomist
, vol.46
, pp. 195
-
-
Kayser, J.1
Lettieri, R.2
-
477
-
-
33750503844
-
-
I.5.1-5 [30-33], he undertakes a similar diagnosis of the Hebrew polity in I.5.6 [34]
-
De Regno, I.5.1-5 [30-33], he undertakes a similar diagnosis of the Hebrew polity in I.5.6 [34].
-
De Regno
-
-
-
478
-
-
84871653714
-
-
I-II, 105.1 res.
-
The Vulgate translation of the text from Deuteronomy 1:15 quoted by Aquinas in ST, I-II, 105.1 res., reads: 'tuli de vestries tribubus viros sapientes et nobiles, et constitui eos princepes'.
-
ST
-
-
Aquinas1
-
479
-
-
33750501180
-
-
I-II, 105.1 arg. 1: 'congrega mihi septuaginta viros de senioribus Israel'
-
Some manuscripts refer to 70, rather than 72, elders - a fact which Aquinas recognizes (ST I-II, 105.1 arg. 1: 'congrega mihi septuaginta viros de senioribus Israel').
-
ST
-
-
-
480
-
-
33750510938
-
-
9
-
See Exodus 24:1, 9;
-
Exodus
, vol.24
, pp. 1
-
-
-
481
-
-
33750511976
-
-
24-5
-
Numbers 11:16, 24-5;
-
Numbers
, vol.11
, pp. 16
-
-
-
482
-
-
33750518432
-
-
and compare Luke 10:1.
-
Luke
, vol.10
, pp. 1
-
-
-
483
-
-
33750516349
-
The doudecimal courts of Qumran, Revelation, and the Sanhedrin
-
75-76
-
On the idea of representation of the tribes, see Joseph Baumgarten, 'The Doudecimal Courts of Qumran, Revelation, and the Sanhedrin', Journal of Biblical Literature 95 (1976): 59, 75-76, citing various rabbinic interpretations of the relevant texts.
-
(1976)
Journal of Biblical Literature
, vol.95
, pp. 59
-
-
Baumgarten, J.1
-
484
-
-
33750530868
-
-
The biblical texts also refer to rulers over 'thousands, hundreds, fifties and tens' (tribunos et centuriones et quinquagenarios et decanos). See Exodus 18:21;
-
Exodus
, vol.18
, pp. 21
-
-
-
485
-
-
33750506334
-
-
Deuteronomy 1:15
-
Deuteronomy
, vol.1
, pp. 15
-
-
-
486
-
-
33750526718
-
-
Exodus 18:21-22
-
Exodus
, vol.18
, pp. 21-22
-
-
-
487
-
-
0039269782
-
-
(Blythe ed.), IV.27.5
-
is cited by Ptolemy of Lucca, De Regimine Principum (Blythe ed.), IV.27.5 and compared to the division of the Jews under Judas Maccabeus into groups led by 'tribunes, centurions, pentacontarchs, and decurions' (I Maccabees 3:55). For the idea of Israel as a kind of tribal confederation,
-
De Regimine Principum
-
-
-
488
-
-
0004315525
-
-
Philadelphia: The Westminister Press
-
see John Bright, A History of Israel (Philadelphia: The Westminister Press, 1959), 42;
-
(1959)
A History of Israel
, pp. 42
-
-
Bright, J.1
-
489
-
-
33750494998
-
Israel as the confederation of the twelve tribes
-
New York: Harper and Row
-
Martin Noth, 'Israel as the Confederation of the Twelve Tribes,' in The History of Israel (New York: Harper and Row, 1958);
-
(1958)
The History of Israel
-
-
Noth, M.1
-
491
-
-
33750524896
-
-
In St. Luke 10:1 there is again a textual variation between the numbers 70 and 72, but Aquinas refers only to 72.
-
St. Luke
, vol.10
, pp. 1
-
-
-
492
-
-
33750533618
-
-
A. Guarenti (ed.), (2nd edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti), X.1
-
Expositio in Lucam, A. Guarenti (ed.), (2nd edn. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1953), X.1.
-
(1953)
Expositio in Lucam
-
-
-
493
-
-
33750518225
-
-
II.3, arg. 5, contra, ad 5
-
Impugn., II.3, arg. 5, contra, ad 5
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
494
-
-
33750510738
-
-
I.4, 112, 127
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, pp. 98, 112, 127).
-
Apology
, pp. 98
-
-
-
495
-
-
33750511139
-
-
II.3, arg. 10, 18-20, 25, contra, ad 10, 18, 20-22, 25
-
Impugn., II.3, arg. 10, 18-20, 25, contra, ad 10, 18, 20-22, 25
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
496
-
-
33750525837
-
-
I.4, 102-4, 106-25, 129, 134, 136-7, 139
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, pp. 99, 102-4, 106-25, 129, 134, 136-7, 139).
-
Apology
, pp. 99
-
-
-
497
-
-
33750510535
-
-
26.3, 35.5, 37.1, 40.6
-
Compare ST, III (Supplement), 26.3, 35.5, 37.1, 40.6.
-
ST
, vol.3
, Issue.SUPPL.
-
-
-
498
-
-
33750493961
-
-
II.3, contra, ad 5
-
Impugn., II.3, contra, ad 5
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
499
-
-
33750517112
-
-
I.4, 127
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, pp. 106-25, 127).
-
Apology
, pp. 106-125
-
-
-
500
-
-
33750503455
-
-
II.3, ad 24
-
Impugn., II.3, ad 24
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
501
-
-
33750509667
-
-
I.4
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, p. 139).
-
Apology
, pp. 139
-
-
-
502
-
-
33750501843
-
-
II.3, ad 23
-
Impugn., II.3, ad 23
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
503
-
-
33750505463
-
-
Proctor, I.4
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, p. 138).
-
Apology
, pp. 138
-
-
-
504
-
-
33750522057
-
-
II.3, arg. 28, ad 28
-
Impugn, II.3, arg. 28, ad 28
-
Impugn
-
-
-
505
-
-
33750521832
-
-
I.4, (141)
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, pp. 106, 141). However, Aquinas affirms, of course, the power of the pope to institute a special order of preachers that is not part of the regular hierarchy.
-
Apology
, pp. 106
-
-
-
506
-
-
50449085825
-
Subsidiarity and political authority in theological perspective
-
Oliver O'Donovan and Joan Lockwood O'Donovan (eds.), Grand Rapids: Eerdmans
-
Thus in Catholic social thought, the principle of subsidiarity applies not simply to 'political' institutions and relationships - such as the relationship between the European Union and its Member States - but also to the many other 'social' institutions and associations which constitute the 'pluriform' nature of human community. As such, Catholic social theory presupposes 'an organically pluralistic society of hierarchically ordered communities': Joan Lockwood O'Donovan, 'Subsidiarity and Political Authority in Theological Perspective', in Oliver O'Donovan and Joan Lockwood O'Donovan (eds.), Bonds of Imperfection: Christian Politics, Past and Present (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2004), p. 228.
-
(2004)
Bonds of Imperfection: Christian Politics, Past and Present
, pp. 228
-
-
O'Donovan, J.L.1
-
507
-
-
38149144415
-
Aristotle as authority: Alternative aristotelian sources of late medieval political theory
-
For a similar argument, comparing the 'singular and indivisible' city-state of Aristotle to the 'plurality' of jurisdictions recognized by Marsiglio of Padua, see Gary Nederman, 'Aristotle as Authority: Alternative Aristotelian Sources of Late Medieval Political Theory', History of European Ideas 8(1) (1987): 31.
-
(1987)
History of European Ideas
, vol.8
, Issue.1
, pp. 31
-
-
Nederman, G.1
-
509
-
-
33750528784
-
-
J. A. Watt (trans.), (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies)
-
have used J. A. Watt (trans.), John of Paris: On Royal and Papal Power (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1971).
-
(1971)
John of Paris: on Royal and Papal Power
-
-
-
510
-
-
33750501841
-
-
John distinguishes the characteristic diversity of secular kingdoms and the fundamental unity that characterises the Church (despite the variety of dioceses and communities of which the Church composed): De potestate regia et papali, III, 84-87.
-
De Potestate Regia et Papali
, vol.3
, pp. 84-87
-
-
-
511
-
-
33750506757
-
-
'[I]t is better', he says, 'that many should rule in many kingdoms than one alone should rule the whole world': De potestate regia et papali, XXI, 227.
-
De Potestate Regia et Papali
, vol.21
, pp. 227
-
-
-
512
-
-
33750503642
-
-
II.3, contra
-
See Aquinas, Impugn., II.3, contra
-
Impugn.
-
-
Aquinas1
-
513
-
-
33750533005
-
-
I.4
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4).
-
Apology
-
-
-
515
-
-
33750504270
-
-
who points out that in Ptolemy of Lucca's Determinatio Compendiosa, 'church and state are seen as completely analogous with respect to their organization' - continuing, he says, a 'process of assimilation' begun by Thomas Aquinas and the canonists, and extended by John of Paris and William of Ockham.
-
Determinatio Compendiosa
-
-
Lucca1
-
517
-
-
33750518634
-
-
In distinguishing between ordination to priesthood, and the grant of jurisdiction, John recognizes 'degrees of jurisdiction going with the episcopate: an archbishop in his province, a primate in a kingdom, a pope in the whole church'. Ordination to priesthood cannot be taken away, he says, but the jurisdiction of an archbishop or pope can be removed: De potestate regia et papali, XXV, 251.
-
De Potestate Regia et Papali
, vol.25
, pp. 251
-
-
-
519
-
-
33750527377
-
-
II.3, arg. 10, 18-20, 25, contra, ad 10, 18, 20-22, 25
-
Compare Aquinas, Impugn., II.3, arg. 10, 18-20, 25, contra, ad 10, 18, 20-22, 25
-
Impugn.
-
-
-
520
-
-
33750506535
-
-
I.4, 102-4, 106-25, 129, 134, 136-7, 139
-
(Proctor, Apology, I.4, pp. 99, 102-4, 106-25, 129, 134, 136-7, 139).
-
Apology
, pp. 99
-
-
-
522
-
-
33750526283
-
-
John says that God gave the Israelites a mixed constitution because too much power in the king leads to tyranny. However, God gave them a monarchy when they requested one 'as if in displeasure', 'because they were rejecting a constitution more beneficial to them': De potestate regia et papali, XIX, 207.
-
De Potestate Regia et Papali
, vol.19
, pp. 207
-
-
-
524
-
-
33750524670
-
-
F. Bleienstein (ed.), Stuttgart: E. Klett
-
The Latin is emphatic about the role of the provinces: 'eligerentur plures ab omni provincia et de omni provincia' (F. Bleienstein (ed.), Tractatus de Potestate Regia ei Papali (Stuttgart: E. Klett, 1969), XIX, 175,
-
(1969)
Tractatus de Potestate Regia Ei Papali
, vol.19
, pp. 175
-
-
-
526
-
-
33750505240
-
-
Compare Pierre D'Ailly, Tractatus de Ecclesiae, Concilii Generalis, Romani pontificis, et Cardinalium Auctoritate, col. 946, who, having drawn attention to the 72 elders chosen from among the people (septuginta duo seniors eligebantur de omni populo), says that in the Church many should be chosen from and by each province (quod esset optimum regimen Ecclesiae, si sub uno Papa eligerentur plures de omni, et ab omni Provincia), and that these elders should correspond to the cardinals, whose function is to temper the power of the pope (et tales deberent esse Cardinales, qui cum Papa et sub eo Ecclesiam regerent, et usum plentitudinis Potestatis temperarent)
-
Tractatus de Ecclesiae, Concilii Generalis, Romani Pontificis, et Cardinalium Auctoritate
-
-
D'Ailly, P.1
-
528
-
-
33750509004
-
-
Paris: Desclée & Cie
-
See, likewise, Jean Gerson, De Potestate Ecclesiastica (Oeuvres Complétes (Paris: Desclée & Cie, 1973), VI, 224-225),
-
(1973)
De Potestate Ecclesiastica Oeuvres Complétes
, vol.6
, pp. 224-225
-
-
Gerson, J.1
-
529
-
-
33750517805
-
-
who underscores the idea that the rectors were chosen from the people and from single tribes (Maneat ecclesiastica politia optima regimine; quale fuit sub Moyse gubernata; quoniam mixta fuit ac triplici politia: regali in Moyse, aristocratica in txxii senioribus. et timocratica dum de populo et singulis tribubus sub Moyse redores sumebantur) (cited in Blythe, Mixed Constitution, 251 and in
-
Mixed Constitution
, pp. 251
-
-
Blythe1
-
532
-
-
0010196176
-
-
Paul Sigmund (ed.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
See Paul Sigmund (ed.), A Catholic Concordance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991);
-
(1991)
A Catholic Concordance
-
-
-
539
-
-
33750512409
-
-
III.1.292; III.7:350; III.12:377-8; III.25.469-72; III:35.527. Although see III.28.491
-
Concordantia Catholica, III.1.292; III.7:350; III.12:377-8; III.25.469-72; III:35.527. Although see III.28.491.
-
Concordantia Catholica
-
-
-
541
-
-
33750512409
-
-
III.4:325, 332, 338 Nicolas simultaneously follows the classical classification of the types of government into monarchical, aristocratic and democratic (III, Preface, 279)
-
Concordantia Catholica, III.4:325, 332, 338. Nicolas simultaneously follows the classical classification of the types of government into monarchical, aristocratic and democratic (III, Preface, 279).
-
Concordantia Catholica
-
-
-
542
-
-
61149582831
-
-
II:32.234
-
However, relying principally on canon law, as well as glosses on the election of deacons recorded in the Acts of the Apostles (II:32.234), he argues that a well 'tempered' monarchy is one in which the king is elected by 'nobles who represent everyone with their consent' (III, Preface, 283). Indeed, tyranny, for Nicolas, is usurped rule, and usurpers are those 'who are neither asked to rule nor elected': III.4:330. Election by corporate representatives is the critical factor.
-
Acts of the Apostles
-
-
-
545
-
-
33750505716
-
-
c. 1579
-
See, likewise, Junius Brutus (pseudonym), Vindiciae contra tyrannos (c. 1579), I, 32: 'such were the 70 ancients in the kingdom of Israel, amongst whom the high priest was as it were president, those seventy being first chosen by six out of each tribe ... then the heads or governors of provinces. In like manner the judges and provosts of towns, captains of thousands, the centurions and others ... Of this rank there are in every well governed kingdom, the princes, the officers of the crown, the peers, the greatest and most notable lords, the deputies of provinces, of whom the ordinary body of the estate is composed, or the parliament or the diet, or other assembly ... .'
-
Vindiciae Contra Tyrannos
, vol.1
, pp. 32
-
-
Brutus, J.1
|