-
1
-
-
84936068266
-
-
Hereinafter referred to as LE.3. Scott J. Shapiro, The Difference that Rules Make, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY 56 (Brian Bix, ed., 1998).
-
Ronald Dworkin, LAW'S EMPIRE (1986). Hereinafter referred to as LE.3. Scott J. Shapiro, The Difference that Rules Make, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY 56 (Brian Bix, ed., 1998).
-
(1986)
LAW'S EMPIRE
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
2
-
-
85022373012
-
-
(2nd ed., ). Hereinafter referred to as CL.
-
H.L.A. Hart, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 255 (2nd ed., 1994). Hereinafter referred to as CL.
-
(1994)
THE CONCEPT OF LAW 255
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
4
-
-
85022443154
-
-
Accordingly, Hart's characterization of the rule of recognition as a social rule has two cognitive elements: (1) the officials of a system take the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition; and (2) most of the population generally obey laws validated by that rule.
-
Nevertheless, obedience is more than just convergent behavior; it presupposes that such behavior is (at least sometimes) guided by the rule. Accordingly, Hart's characterization of the rule of recognition as a social rule has two cognitive elements: (1) the officials of a system take the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition; and (2) most of the population generally obey laws validated by that rule.
-
Nevertheless, obedience is more than just convergent behavior; it presupposes that such behavior is (at least sometimes) guided by the rule
-
-
-
6
-
-
78650447024
-
-
11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139, 156. Hereinafter referred to as NAPP.
-
Jules Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139, 156 (1982). Hereinafter referred to as NAPP.
-
(1982)
Negative and Positive Positivism
-
-
Coleman, J.1
-
7
-
-
77950031829
-
-
see Timothy A.O. Endicott, Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting, 4 LEGAL THEORY
-
For a discussion of this point, see Timothy A.O. Endicott, Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting, 4 LEGAL THEORY 3, 283-300 (1998).
-
(1998)
For a discussion of this point
, vol.3
, pp. 283-300
-
-
-
8
-
-
85022411418
-
-
347 U.S.
-
Brown, 347 U.S. 483, 494 (1954).
-
(1954)
Brown
, vol.483
, pp. 494
-
-
-
9
-
-
85022410991
-
-
347 U.S.
-
Brown, 347 U.S. 483, 495 (1954).
-
(1954)
Brown
, vol.483
, pp. 495
-
-
-
10
-
-
85022404158
-
-
163 U.S.
-
Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 544 (1896).
-
(1896)
Plessy v. Ferguson
, vol.537
, pp. 544
-
-
-
11
-
-
85022404158
-
-
163 U.S.
-
Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 544 (1896).
-
(1896)
Plessy v. Ferguson
, vol.537
, pp. 544
-
-
-
12
-
-
85022411418
-
-
347 U.S.
-
Brown, 347 U.S. 483, 494 (1954).
-
(1954)
Brown
, vol.483
, pp. 494
-
-
-
13
-
-
85022432673
-
-
(LE 28-29), but it is clear that all parties shared the Equal Protection Clause as the relevant criterion of legal validity. The dispute was over whether public school segregation is consistent with the requirements of this clause.
-
Dworkin cites the Brown case in LAW'S EMPIRE as an example of the kind of disagreement that is inconsistent with positivism (LE 28-29), but it is clear that all parties shared the Equal Protection Clause as the relevant criterion of legal validity. The dispute was over whether public school segregation is consistent with the requirements of this clause.
-
Dworkin cites the Brown case in LAW'S EMPIRE as an example of the kind of disagreement that is inconsistent with positivism
-
-
-
14
-
-
85022380053
-
-
Endicott believes that many paradigms are subject to revision, but not all. Some of them have a conceptual flavor: “[i]t seems that no conception of epic poetry could account for other instances of the genre, if it excluded the Odyssey.” Endicott, Hart and the Semantic Sting at
-
Endicott makes a similar point. Endicott believes that many paradigms are subject to revision, but not all. Some of them have a conceptual flavor: “[i]t seems that no conception of epic poetry could account for other instances of the genre, if it excluded the Odyssey.” Endicott, Hart and the Semantic Sting at 294.
-
Endicott makes a similar point
, pp. 294
-
-
-
15
-
-
85022406202
-
-
Brian Leiter, for example, argues that legal realism is not committed to the view that the law is always radically indeterminate: “the evidential base of cases actually litigated could not support the inference that the law is globally indeterminate, for it would omit all those ‘easy’ cases in which a clear-cut legal rule dictates a result.” See Brian Leiter, Legal Realism, in A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY 267 (Dennis Patterson, ed., ). While it would be difficult to provide a plausible account of where those limits fall, disputes about an interpretation of standard S that fall clearly outside those limits must be construed as being about whether S is an authoritative standard.
-
All sides (with the exception of critical legal theorists) acknowledge that there are limits on the range of reasonable interpretations of a law. Brian Leiter, for example, argues that legal realism is not committed to the view that the law is always radically indeterminate: “the evidential base of cases actually litigated could not support the inference that the law is globally indeterminate, for it would omit all those ‘easy’ cases in which a clear-cut legal rule dictates a result.” See Brian Leiter, Legal Realism, in A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY 267 (Dennis Patterson, ed., 1996). While it would be difficult to provide a plausible account of where those limits fall, disputes about an interpretation of standard S that fall clearly outside those limits must be construed as being about whether S is an authoritative standard.
-
(1996)
All sides (with the exception of critical legal theorists) acknowledge that there are limits on the range of reasonable interpretations of a law
-
-
-
16
-
-
85022420235
-
-
All sides (with the exception of critical legal theorists) acknowledge that there are limits on the range of reasonable interpretations of a law.
-
A more recent argument by Coleman addressing this issue is discussed in Subsection IV.2, All sides (with the exception of critical legal theorists) acknowledge that there are limits on the range of reasonable interpretations of a law.
-
A more recent argument by Coleman addressing this issue is discussed in Subsection IV.2
-
-
-
17
-
-
77956842168
-
-
115 N.Y. 506, 22 N.E. 188, 192 emphasis added.
-
Riggs v. Palmer, 115 N.Y. 506, 22 N.E. 188, 192 (1889); emphasis added.
-
(1889)
Riggs v. Palmer
-
-
-
18
-
-
85022435456
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 191-192.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 191-192
-
-
-
19
-
-
85022354873
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 190.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 190
-
-
-
20
-
-
84920766555
-
-
4 LEGAL THEORY 3, 250. Hereinafter referred to as TV. See also Endicott, Hart and the Semantic Sting at 285 (“Hart did not have a criterial semantic theory-or any semantic theory at all, if a semantic theory is a general explanatory account of what makes an application of an expression correct”).
-
See Joseph Raz, Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison, 4 LEGAL THEORY 3, 250 (1998). Hereinafter referred to as TV. See also Endicott, Hart and the Semantic Sting at 285 (“Hart did not have a criterial semantic theory-or any semantic theory at all, if a semantic theory is a general explanatory account of what makes an application of an expression correct”).
-
(1998)
Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
24
-
-
85022438377
-
-
11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982); and Kenneth Einar Himma, The Epistemic Sense of the Pedigree Thesis, 80 PAC. PHIL. Q.
-
See Jules L. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982); and Kenneth Einar Himma, The Epistemic Sense of the Pedigree Thesis, 80 PAC. PHIL. Q. 1 (1999).
-
(1999)
Negative and Positive Positivism
, pp. 1
-
-
Coleman, J.L.1
-
25
-
-
85022398221
-
-
Raz argues that that there are shared criteria for the use of a concept does not imply that there cannot be disagreement about those criteria (TV 261-65). He points out that people may share criteria that are not fully specified, so that disagreements may arise where specified criteria run out.
-
Joseph Raz argues for a defense against the semantic sting that relies on the possibility that a society's criteria of validity might be incomplete. Raz argues that that there are shared criteria for the use of a concept does not imply that there cannot be disagreement about those criteria (TV 261-65). He points out that people may share criteria that are not fully specified, so that disagreements may arise where specified criteria run out.
-
Joseph Raz argues for a defense against the semantic sting that relies on the possibility that a society's criteria of validity might be incomplete
-
-
-
27
-
-
85022404425
-
-
If so, the same argument can be made about these interpretations as the one that I will make about (R1). What ultimately matters, as we will see, is that a holding in either direction results in valid law-no matter how one characterizes the disagreement.
-
Brian Bix pointed out to me that there may be other ways to interpret the disagreement in Riggs. If so, the same argument can be made about these interpretations as the one that I will make about (R1). What ultimately matters, as we will see, is that a holding in either direction results in valid law-no matter how one characterizes the disagreement.
-
Brian Bix pointed out to me that there may be other ways to interpret the disagreement in Riggs
-
-
-
28
-
-
85022368739
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 189.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 189
-
-
-
29
-
-
85022368739
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 189.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 189
-
-
-
30
-
-
85022368739
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 189.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 189
-
-
-
31
-
-
85022394515
-
-
22 N.E. 188, 191; emphasis added.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 191; emphasis added.
-
Riggs
-
-
-
32
-
-
85022375660
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 191.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 191
-
-
-
33
-
-
85022354873
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 190.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 190
-
-
-
34
-
-
85022354873
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 190.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 190
-
-
-
35
-
-
85022375660
-
-
22 N.E.
-
Riggs, 22 N.E. 188, 191.
-
Riggs
, vol.188
, pp. 191
-
-
-
36
-
-
85022431247
-
-
3 U.S. 365, 1 L.Ed. 638 (1797); Cook v. Meyer, 73 Ala. 580 (1883); Hotaling v. Cronise, 2 Cal. 60 (1852); Young v. McKenzie, 3 Ga. 31 (1847); Kramer v. Rebman, 9 Iowa 114 (1859); Dwelly v. Dwelly, 46 Me. 377 (1859); Sibley v. Smith, 2 Mich. 486 (1853); Sullivan v. La Crosse & M. Steam-Packet Co., 10 Minn. 386 (1865); Burnside v. Whitney, 21 N.Y. 148 (1865); Bailey v. Bryan, 48 N.C. 357 (1856); Appeal of Esterley, 54 Pa. St. 192 (1867); and Hearn v. Ewin, 43 Tenn.
-
See, e.g., Brown v. Barry, 3 U.S. 365, 1 L.Ed. 638 (1797); Cook v. Meyer, 73 Ala. 580 (1883); Hotaling v. Cronise, 2 Cal. 60 (1852); Young v. McKenzie, 3 Ga. 31 (1847); Kramer v. Rebman, 9 Iowa 114 (1859); Dwelly v. Dwelly, 46 Me. 377 (1859); Sibley v. Smith, 2 Mich. 486 (1853); Sullivan v. La Crosse & M. Steam-Packet Co., 10 Minn. 386 (1865); Burnside v. Whitney, 21 N.Y. 148 (1865); Bailey v. Bryan, 48 N.C. 357 (1856); Appeal of Esterley, 54 Pa. St. 192 (1867); and Hearn v. Ewin, 43 Tenn. 399 (1866).
-
(1866)
Brown v. Barry
, pp. 399
-
-
-
39
-
-
85022362623
-
-
185 S.W. 487, 169 Ky.
-
Eversole v. Eversole, 185 S.W. 487, 169 Ky. 793 (1916).
-
(1916)
Eversole v. Eversole
, pp. 793
-
-
-
40
-
-
85022403341
-
-
37 Cal. Rptr. 681 (1964); Drafts v. Drafts, 114 So.2d 837 (1963); Wallach v. Wallach, 95 S.E.2d 750 (1956); Bissell Carpet Sweeper Co. v. Shane Co., 143 N.E.2d 415;Williams v. City ofWichita, 374 P.2d 578 (1962); Dieball v. Continental Cas. Co., 176 So.2d 774 (1965); State Highway Commission v. SouthernUnion Gas Co., 332 P.2d
-
See, e.g., Lowmanv. Stafford, 37 Cal. Rptr. 681 (1964); Drafts v. Drafts, 114 So.2d 837 (1963); Wallach v. Wallach, 95 S.E.2d 750 (1956); Bissell Carpet Sweeper Co. v. Shane Co., 143 N.E.2d 415;Williams v. City ofWichita, 374 P.2d 578 (1962); Dieball v. Continental Cas. Co., 176 So.2d 774 (1965); State Highway Commission v. SouthernUnion Gas Co., 332 P.2d 1007 (1958).
-
(1958)
Lowmanv. Stafford
, pp. 1007
-
-
-
41
-
-
85022428753
-
-
A.2d 71 (1953).
-
(1953)
A.2d
, pp. 71
-
-
-
42
-
-
85022392459
-
-
95 A.2d at 75. Indeed, as the Bird court points out, the Riggs holding has been criticized in a number of other cases. See, e.g., Shellenberger v. Ransom, 59 N.W. 935 (1894); Wall v. Pfanschmidt, 106 N.E. 785 (1914); and Box v. Lanier, 79 S.W.
-
Bird, 95 A.2d at 75. Indeed, as the Bird court points out, the Riggs holding has been criticized in a number of other cases. See, e.g., Shellenberger v. Ransom, 59 N.W. 935 (1894); Wall v. Pfanschmidt, 106 N.E. 785 (1914); and Box v. Lanier, 79 S.W. 1042 (1904).
-
(1904)
Bird
, pp. 1042
-
-
-
43
-
-
85022418824
-
-
As long as citizens and officials accept the Court's constitutional holdings, these holdings have the force of law. To my knowledge, the Court has never come closer to reaching the limits of such acceptance than it did with the Brown decision. So much resistance did Brown engender in the South that the court tolerated school segregation there for ten years after its decision. Judicial efforts to enforce Brown achieved real momentum only after the Civil Rights Act of
-
There are, of course, limits to what the Supreme Court can do in creating constitutional law, but those limits are defined by the acceptance of citizens and officials. As long as citizens and officials accept the Court's constitutional holdings, these holdings have the force of law. To my knowledge, the Court has never come closer to reaching the limits of such acceptance than it did with the Brown decision. So much resistance did Brown engender in the South that the court tolerated school segregation there for ten years after its decision. Judicial efforts to enforce Brown achieved real momentum only after the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
-
(1964)
There are, of course, limits to what the Supreme Court can do in creating constitutional law, but those limits are defined by the acceptance of citizens and officials
-
-
-
44
-
-
85022441895
-
-
U.S. 479 (1965).
-
(1965)
U.S
, pp. 479
-
-
-
46
-
-
85022436834
-
-
410 U.S.
-
Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 222 (1973).
-
(1973)
Roe v. Wade
, vol.113
, pp. 222
-
-
|