-
1
-
-
0004232285
-
-
New York: Clarendon Press, Reprinted Donald Davidson, 207–25 (hereafter, ‘ME’
-
1980. Essays on Actions and Events New York: Clarendon Press. Reprinted in Donald Davidson, 207–25 (hereafter, ‘ME’).
-
(1980)
Essays on Actions and Events
-
-
-
2
-
-
85063698995
-
-
New York: Blackwell, particular, it rules out Jaegwon Kims elegant reconstruction of Davidsons argument ‘Psychophysical Laws,’ 1985) 369–86. Kim has Davidsons argument relying upon an assumption of the causal closure of the physical domain (381,383–4). Such an assumption would take much of the interest out of Davidsons argument for monism. For extended discussion, see §VI below, as well as my ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ Philosophical Studies3 235–58.1 now think that my rendering of Kims reconstruction of the argument for mental anomalism §11 of that paper does not adequately highlight the role that this assumption is supposed to play, though this does not affect the criticisms I make of the reconstruction. See also note 68 below., and, eds
-
LePore, E., and McLaughlin, B., eds. 1997. Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson Vol. 83, New York: Blackwell. In particular, it rules out Jaegwon Kim's elegant reconstruction of Davidson's argument in ‘Psychophysical Laws,’ in 1985) 369–86. Kim has Davidson's argument relying upon an assumption of the causal closure of the physical domain (381,383–4). Such an assumption would take much of the interest out of Davidson's argument for monism. For extended discussion, see §VI below, as well as my ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ Philosophical Studies3 235–58.1 now think that my rendering of Kim's reconstruction of the argument for mental anomalism in §11 of that paper does not adequately highlight the role that this assumption is supposed to play, though this does not affect the criticisms I make of the reconstruction. See also note 68 below.
-
(1997)
Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson
, vol.83
-
-
LePore, E.1
McLaughlin, B.2
-
3
-
-
85063698378
-
-
Kim, ‘Psychophysical Laws’
-
Kim, ‘Psychophysical Laws’
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
52549092047
-
Anomalism, Uncodifiability, and Psychophysical Relations
-
2 John McDowell, ‘Virtue and Reason,’ The Monist62 (1979) 331–50; ‘Functionalism and Anomalous Monism,’ Actions and Events: Essays on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson387–98
-
Child, William. 1993. ‘Anomalism, Uncodifiability, and Psychophysical Relations,’. The Philosophical Review, 102: 215–45. 2 John McDowell, ‘Virtue and Reason,’ The Monist62 (1979) 331–50; ‘Functionalism and Anomalous Monism,’ in Actions and Events: Essays on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson387–98
-
(1993)
The Philosophical Review
, vol.102
, pp. 215-245
-
-
Child, W.1
-
5
-
-
85063699288
-
-
See ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism.’ For further discussion of the relation between rationality and mental anomalism, see §§II, V, and VI of the present paper as well as notes 62,63, and 66 and surrounding text below
-
See ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism.’ For further discussion of the relation between rationality and mental anomalism, see §§II, V, and VI of the present paper as well as notes 62,63, and 66 and surrounding text below.
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
0004205847
-
-
New York: Clarendon Press, The PNCC has been attacked by a number of people, including McDowell, ‘Functionalism and Anomalous Monism,’ 398, and Jennifer Hornsby, ‘Agency and Causal Explanation,’ 161–88, at 186–8. The PCI has been attacked most prominently by Kim; for a survey of the relevant issues, see his ‘The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism,’ Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association63 (1989) 31–47. For skepticism about the causal nature of reasons, see notes 7 and 30 below, as well as Kims paper., and, eds
-
Heil, J., and Mele, A., eds. 1993. Mental Causation New York: Clarendon Press. The PNCC has been attacked by a number of people, including McDowell, ‘Functionalism and Anomalous Monism,’ 398, and Jennifer Hornsby, ‘Agency and Causal Explanation,’ in 161–88, at 186–8. The PCI has been attacked most prominently by Kim; for a survey of the relevant issues, see his ‘The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism,’ Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association63 (1989) 31–47. For skepticism about the causal nature of reasons, see notes 7 and 30 below, as well as Kim's paper.
-
(1993)
Mental Causation
-
-
Heil, J.1
Mele, A.2
-
8
-
-
85063704672
-
-
1 .’ See discussion at the end of §IV and note 68 below. (Note that this grounds Davidsons skepticism about the possibility of ruling out deviant causal chains the analysis of intentional action (‘Freedom to Act,’ reprinted Essays on Actions and Events, 63–81, at 79). To hold that intentional actions are appropriate behaviors caused, the right way, by primary reasons amounts to holding that, ceteris paribus, intentional actions are appropriate behaviors caused by primary reasons. Mental anomalism holds that neither ‘in the right way’ nor, ‘ceteris paribus’, can be explicated so as to produce exceptionless generalizations. John Bishop fails to notice this the course of his extended discussion of deviant causal chains, (Natural Agency, [New York: Cambridge University Press 1989] 125–75; see 164
-
1 .’ See discussion at the end of §IV and note 68 below. (Note that this grounds Davidson's skepticism about the possibility of ruling out deviant causal chains in the analysis of intentional action (‘Freedom to Act,’ reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events 63–81, at 79). To hold that intentional actions are appropriate behaviors caused in the right way by primary reasons amounts to holding that, ceteris paribus, intentional actions are appropriate behaviors caused by primary reasons. Mental anomalism holds that neither ‘in the right way’ nor ‘ceteris paribus’ can be explicated so as to produce exceptionless generalizations. John Bishop fails to notice this in the course of his extended discussion of deviant causal chains (Natural Agency [New York: Cambridge University Press 1989] 125–75; see 164).
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
85063703143
-
-
ME, 207. that passage, Davidson does not commit himself to the claim that human freedom would be contradicted by the existence of such laws. But he ends the paper with the remark that ‘The anomalism of the mental is thus a necessary condition for viewing action as autonomous’ (225). The impossibility of strict psychophysical and psychological laws of succession is thus held to be necessary (though clearly not sufficient) for freedom
-
ME, 207. In that passage, Davidson does not commit himself to the claim that human freedom would be contradicted by the existence of such laws. But he ends the paper with the remark that ‘The anomalism of the mental is thus a necessary condition for viewing action as autonomous’ (225). The impossibility of strict psychophysical and psychological laws of succession is thus held to be necessary (though clearly not sufficient) for freedom.
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
85063699207
-
-
‘Psychophysical Laws,’ 381; Child, 219
-
Kim. ‘Psychophysical Laws,’ 381; Child, 219
-
-
-
Kim1
-
11
-
-
85063702567
-
-
Here I am apparently disagreement with Noa Latham his excellent article ‘Singular Causal Statements and Strict Deterministic Laws,’ 1 Latham claims, without argument, that the PNCC requires that the fundamental physical laws be deterministic (41
-
1987. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 68: 29–43. Here I am apparently in disagreement with Noa Latham in his excellent article ‘Singular Causal Statements and Strict Deterministic Laws,’ 1 Latham claims, without argument, that the PNCC requires that the fundamental physical laws be deterministic (41).
-
(1987)
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.68
, pp. 29-43
-
-
-
12
-
-
85063703670
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, For why this is only a first approximation, see §111, where INUS conditions are distinguished from ‘CP’— ceteris paribus— conditions
-
Mackie, John. 1974. The Cement of the Universe 62Oxford: Clarendon Press. For why this is only a first approximation, see §111, where INUS conditions are distinguished from ‘CP’— ceteris paribus— conditions.
-
(1974)
The Cement of the Universe
, pp. 62
-
-
Mackie, J.1
-
13
-
-
85063704957
-
-
For the first and third, see Stephen Schiffer, ‘Ceteris Paribus Laws,’ 1–17, esp. 3–5. Schiffers considerations against the second model turn on issues surrounding the question of multiple realization and supervenience, discussion of which would take us too far afield here. light of the centrality of the second model to the discussion this section, it should be noted that an appeal to multiple realizability is not available to Davidson laying out the framework of the argument for mental anomalism. This is because it assumes something (realization) too similar to the token-identity thesis that he eventually wants to argue for on the basis of mental anomalism
-
1991. Mind, 100 For the first and third, see Stephen Schiffer, ‘Ceteris Paribus Laws,’ 1–17, esp. 3–5. Schiffer's considerations against the second model turn on issues surrounding the question of multiple realization and supervenience, discussion of which would take us too far afield here. In light of the centrality of the second model to the discussion in this section, it should be noted that an appeal to multiple realizability is not available to Davidson in laying out the framework of the argument for mental anomalism. This is because it assumes something (realization) too similar to the token-identity thesis that he eventually wants to argue for on the basis of mental anomalism.
-
(1991)
Mind
, vol.100
-
-
-
14
-
-
0001843810
-
Making Mind Matter More
-
1 at 78, n.10. As will become apparent, I agree with Fodors basic claim here that it is all special-science generalizations that are principle ceteris paribus, and that there is therefore nothing unique about psychology this regard. I also share his focus here on laws of succession when raising the question of anomalism, as well as his suggestion (75) that considerations about mental causation lead to a form of monism. But for Fodor the latter move depends upon assumptions about realizability (‘implementation of mechanisms’) that already seem to beg significant questions about monism. See note 13 above, and discussion about the status of monism the text further below, as well as §VI
-
Fodor, Jerry. 1989. ‘Making Mind Matter More,’. Philosophical Topics, 17: 59–79. 1 at 78, n.10. As will become apparent, I agree with Fodor's basic claim here that it is all special-science generalizations that are in principle ceteris paribus, and that there is therefore nothing unique about psychology in this regard. I also share his focus here on laws of succession when raising the question of anomalism, as well as his suggestion (75) that considerations about mental causation lead to a form of monism. But for Fodor the latter move depends upon assumptions about realizability (‘implementation of mechanisms’) that already seem to beg significant questions about monism. See note 13 above, and discussion about the status of monism in the text further below, as well as §VI.
-
(1989)
Philosophical Topics
, vol.17
, pp. 59-79
-
-
Fodor, J.1
-
16
-
-
12444256705
-
‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental,’ in
-
at 342. A clear sign of the strain produced by this collapsing of distinctions shows up McLaughlins subsequent reading of Davidsons reference to ‘rough, but homonomic laws’ (ME, 223) terms of strict laws which ‘fail to be as explicit and exceptionless as possible. (but] can be sharpened into one. without shifting to a different general vocabulary’ (346). How is that a strict law? McLaughlins identification of ‘homonomic’ with ‘strict’ forces this clearly unhappy reading. Davidson is unambiguously referring to ceteris paribus laws by the remark
-
McLaughlin, Brian. “ ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental,’ in ”. In Actions and Events: Essays on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson 331–68. at 342. A clear sign of the strain produced by this collapsing of distinctions shows up in McLaughlin's subsequent reading of Davidson's reference to ‘rough, but homonomic laws’ (ME, 223) in terms of strict laws which ‘fail to be as explicit and exceptionless as possible. (but] can be sharpened into one. without shifting to a different general vocabulary’ (346). How is that a strict law? McLaughlin's identification of ‘homonomic’ with ‘strict’ forces this clearly unhappy reading. Davidson is unambiguously referring to ceteris paribus laws by the remark.
-
Actions and Events: Essays on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson
, pp. 331-368
-
-
McLaughlin, B.1
-
18
-
-
85063702186
-
-
I am indebted to comments of two anonymous referees for helping me to appreciate the importance of this issue for the present set of concerns.
-
I am indebted to comments of two anonymous referees for helping me to appreciate the importance of this issue for the present set of concerns.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0003438275
-
-
New York: Clarendon Press, See also ‘Belief and the Basis of Meaning,’ reprinted Donald Davidson, 141–54, at 154
-
1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation New York: Clarendon Press. See also ‘Belief and the Basis of Meaning,’ reprinted in Donald Davidson, 141–54, at 154.
-
(1984)
Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation
-
-
-
20
-
-
85063704363
-
-
I should emphasize here that recognition of rationality as the essential individuating feature of the mental— as the interest which governs mental ascription— does not require seeing it as playing the central role grounding mental anomalism. I discuss the role of explanatory interests the individuation of vocabularies further §V. I argue there that it is not, which, interest mental ascriptions serve, but, that, they serve a particular interest, at all, which is at the basis of mental anomalism. This fact is tied directly to the generic causal definition of mental properties emphasized later this paper
-
I should emphasize here that recognition of rationality as the essential individuating feature of the mental— as the interest which governs mental ascription— does not require seeing it as playing the central role in grounding mental anomalism. I discuss the role of explanatory interests in the individuation of vocabularies further in §V. I argue there that it is not which interest mental ascriptions serve, but that they serve a particular interest at all, which is at the basis of mental anomalism. This fact is tied directly to the generic causal definition of mental properties emphasized later in this paper.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
85063702448
-
-
See ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental,’ 357
-
McLaughlin. See ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental,’ 357.
-
-
-
McLaughlin1
-
22
-
-
85063697963
-
-
‘Psychophysical Laws,’ Kim presents a picture of how the existence of bridge laws connecting mental and physical properties would ‘change the subject’ that appears to apply directly to laws of succession. Bridge laws would transmit the constitutive elements of one domain to the laws governing the other domain, thus compromising the integrity of the latter (375). By licensing substitutions within the laws of succession, the bridge laws would thus lead to a ‘change of subject’ those laws of succession. I have discussed a number of problems with this view detail ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism.’
-
In ‘Psychophysical Laws,’ Kim presents a picture of how the existence of bridge laws connecting mental and physical properties would ‘change the subject’ that appears to apply directly to laws of succession. Bridge laws would transmit the constitutive elements of one domain to the laws governing the other domain, thus compromising the integrity of the latter (375). By licensing substitutions within the laws of succession, the bridge laws would thus lead to a ‘change of subject’ in those laws of succession. I have discussed a number of problems with this view in detail in ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism.’
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
85063700633
-
If that strategy turns on the point about a ‘change in subject,’ it is restricted to bridge laws, as argued in the text. Since it is thus too limited to block the sorts of laws— strict psychophysical laws of succession— that the argument for monism depends upon having been blocked (see §VI)
-
it is also too limited to ground mental anomalism, which is, after all, a completely general thesis
-
This brings out a further problem with the attempt to ground mental anomalism in considerations of rationality. If that strategy turns on the point about a ‘change in subject,’ it is restricted to bridge laws, as argued in the text. Since it is thus too limited to block the sorts of laws— strict psychophysical laws of succession— that the argument for monism depends upon having been blocked (see §VI), it is also too limited to ground mental anomalism, which is, after all, a completely general thesis.
-
This brings out a further problem with the attempt to ground mental anomalism in considerations of rationality
-
-
-
24
-
-
85063700444
-
-
The point is clearly made by Davidson at ME, 224. Strictly speaking, the point here is confined to types of mental events that causally interact with physical events; but it is these that are Davidsons concern ME (208,223). For further discussion of the point, see §VI, and ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §IV
-
The point is clearly made by Davidson at ME, 224. Strictly speaking, the point here is confined to types of mental events that causally interact with physical events; but it is these that are Davidson's concern in ME (208,223). For further discussion of the point, see §VI, and ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §IV.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
84874322814
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, This is especially clear Davidson, ‘Problems the Explanation of Action,’ 34–49 (hereafter, ‘PEA’), at 41., and, eds
-
Pettit, P., Sylvan, R., and Norman, J., eds. 1987. Metaphysics and Morality Oxford: Basil Blackwell. This is especially clear in Davidson, ‘Problems in the Explanation of Action,’ in 34–49 (hereafter, ‘PEA’), at 41.
-
(1987)
Metaphysics and Morality
-
-
Pettit, P.1
Sylvan, R.2
Norman, J.3
-
29
-
-
0000824398
-
‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes,’ reprinted in
-
Davidson. “ ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes,’ reprinted in ”. In Essays on Actions and Events 3–19.
-
Essays on Actions and Events
, pp. 3-19
-
-
Davidson1
-
30
-
-
85063699449
-
-
Davidson cites this as the central objection to non-causal theories of action (‘Actions, Reasons and Causes,’ 9–11). The issue is usefully discussed Frederick Stoutland, ‘The Causation of Behavior,’ Essays on Wittgenstein Honor of G.H. von Wright, Acta Philosophica Fennica1–3 286–325. The point is crucial to my strategy this paper. I want to place all the weight of mental anomalism upon the causal nature of reasons, and so it matters how causation enters into their nature. I am emphasizing (along with Davidson) that it enters at the ground level: reasons are such only by virtue of their causal nature (see further §V). (Note that the claim that reasons are causes is a premise (PCI) the argument for monism. Its deployment against non-causal theories of action thus does not depend upon assuming monism (or causal closure— see §VI below). This is relevant to epiphenomenalist criticisms of anomalous monism; see note 7 above.), ed
-
Hintikka, J., ed. 1976. Vol. 28, Davidson cites this as the central objection to non-causal theories of action (‘Actions, Reasons and Causes,’ 9–11). The issue is usefully discussed in Frederick Stoutland, ‘The Causation of Behavior,’ in Essays on Wittgenstein in Honor of G.H. von Wright, Acta Philosophica Fennica1–3 286–325. The point is crucial to my strategy in this paper. I want to place all the weight of mental anomalism upon the causal nature of reasons, and so it matters how causation enters into their nature. I am emphasizing (along with Davidson) that it enters at the ground level: reasons are such only by virtue of their causal nature (see further §V). (Note that the claim that reasons are causes is a premise (PCI) in the argument for monism. Its deployment against non-causal theories of action thus does not depend upon assuming monism (or causal closure— see §VI below). This is relevant to epiphenomenalist criticisms of anomalous monism; see note 7 above.)
-
(1976)
, vol.28
-
-
Hintikka, J.1
-
31
-
-
85063700044
-
-
These points are also noted by McLaughlin ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental,’ 345
-
349–50. These points are also noted by McLaughlin in ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental,’ 345 &
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
85063701820
-
-
Unlike this tradition, however, Davidson has eschewed, analyses, of singular causal relations terms of strict-law coverage. Moreover, his extensionalist account of causal relations between particular events indicates that he would not endorse Russells and Quines pictures of the non-objective nature of singular causal citations. (See note 38 below, and surrounding text, for how this bears on the use of causal terminology within strict laws.) But Davidsons causal realism is compatible with his sharing Russells and Quines view that strict laws cannot be formulated terms of causally defined concepts. I am claiming that it is this stricture which is responsible for the impossibility of strict psychophysical laws. Davidson is thus a Humean about ‘causal’ laws, though not about singular causal relations
-
Unlike this tradition, however, Davidson has eschewed analyses of singular causal relations in terms of strict-law coverage. Moreover, his extensionalist account of causal relations between particular events indicates that he would not endorse Russell's and Quine's pictures of the non-objective nature of singular causal citations. (See note 38 below, and surrounding text, for how this bears on the use of causal terminology within strict laws.) But Davidson's causal realism is compatible with his sharing Russell's and Quine's view that strict laws cannot be formulated in terms of causally defined concepts. I am claiming that it is this stricture which is responsible for the impossibility of strict psychophysical laws. Davidson is thus a Humean about ‘causal’ laws, though not about singular causal relations.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
85063697992
-
-
Nagel E., (ed), New York: Hafner, Edited by
-
Mill, J. S., 1950. Philosophy of Scientific Method Edited by: Nagel, E., 195–6. New York: Hafner.
-
(1950)
Philosophy of Scientific Method
, pp. 195-196
-
-
Mill, J.S.1
-
34
-
-
0006017599
-
‘Causal Relations,’ reprinted in
-
at 157
-
Davidson. “ ‘Causal Relations,’ reprinted in ”. In Essays on Actions and Events 149–62. at 157
-
Essays on Actions and Events
, pp. 149-162
-
-
Davidson1
-
35
-
-
13744254268
-
‘The Individuation of Events,’ reprinted in
-
at 171–2
-
Davidson. “ ‘The Individuation of Events,’ reprinted in ”. In Essays on Actions and Events 163–80. at 171–2
-
Essays on Actions and Events
, pp. 163-180
-
-
Davidson1
-
37
-
-
0002919576
-
‘Natural Kinds,’ reprinted in his
-
New York: Columbia, at 121 & 137–8, read alongside 131
-
Quine, W. V., 1969. “ ‘Natural Kinds,’ reprinted in his ”. In Ontological Relativity and other Essays 114–38. New York: Columbia., at 121 & 137–8, read alongside 131.
-
(1969)
Ontological Relativity and other Essays
, pp. 114-138
-
-
Quine, W.V.1
-
38
-
-
85063699882
-
-
however, does not share this view; his formulation of the structure of a strict law at 158 of ‘Causal Relations’ explicitly invokes the term ‘causes.’ See note 32 above
-
Davidson. however, does not share this view; his formulation of the structure of a strict law at 158 of ‘Causal Relations’ explicitly invokes the term ‘causes.’ See note 32 above.
-
-
-
Davidson1
-
39
-
-
0039878188
-
-
See Quines ‘Reply to Charles Parsons,’ W. V. Quine (La Salle: Opencourt Press 396–403, at, and, eds
-
Hahn, L., and Schilpp, P., eds. 1986. The Philosophy of 397–8. See Quine's ‘Reply to Charles Parsons,’ in W. V. Quine (La Salle: Opencourt Press 396–403, at
-
(1986)
The Philosophy of
, pp. 397-398
-
-
Hahn, L.1
Schilpp, P.2
-
40
-
-
0004158639
-
-
4th ed., New York: Cambridge, I do not distinguish between dispositions and causally defined properties here; the relevant distinction is between both of these, on the one hand, and the sorts of properties that can figure strict laws, on the other. For discussion of the former distinction, see Sydney Shoemaker, ‘Causality and Properties,’ reprinted his 206–33. Shoemaker holds that dispositional predicates are those whose causal definition is contained their meaning (210), and that is not true of all causally defined properties. Nelson Goodman seems to have my wider use of ‘disposition’ Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1983), 41, n.7
-
1984. Identity, Cause and Mind, 4th ed. New York: Cambridge. I do not distinguish between dispositions and causally defined properties here; the relevant distinction is between both of these, on the one hand, and the sorts of properties that can figure in strict laws, on the other. For discussion of the former distinction, see Sydney Shoemaker, ‘Causality and Properties,’ reprinted in his 206–33. Shoemaker holds that dispositional predicates are those whose causal definition is contained in their meaning (210), and that is not true of all causally defined properties. Nelson Goodman seems to have my wider use of ‘disposition’ in Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1983), 41, n.7.
-
(1984)
Identity, Cause and Mind
-
-
-
42
-
-
0010841157
-
Three Varieties of Knowledge' in
-
Griffiths A.P., (ed), New York: Cambridge University Press, See 153–66 (hereafter,‘TVK’), at 163., Edited by
-
Davidson. 1991. “Three Varieties of Knowledge' in ”. In A.J. Ayer: Memorial Essays Edited by: Griffiths, A. P., New York: Cambridge University Press. See 153–66 (hereafter,‘TVK’), at 163.
-
(1991)
A.J. Ayer: Memorial Essays
-
-
Davidson1
-
43
-
-
0013103988
-
Skepticism and Semantic Knowledge
-
See 223–37. Forbes does not use this holistic point (see below the text) to block the possibility of strict psychophysical laws. His interest is responding to rule-following objections to dispositional accounts of meaning
-
Forbes, Graeme. 1984. ‘Skepticism and Semantic Knowledge,’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94 See 223–37. Forbes does not use this holistic point (see below in the text) to block the possibility of strict psychophysical laws. His interest is in responding to rule-following objections to dispositional accounts of meaning.
-
(1984)
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
, vol.94
-
-
Forbes, G.1
-
44
-
-
0037718761
-
-
It has plausibly been claimed that these conditions must be non-identical order to deflect worries about dispositional explanations being vacuous. For discussion, see Fodor, ‘You Can Fool Some of the People All of the Time: Hedged Laws and Psychological Explanations’ 19–33, and Paul Pietroski and Georges Rey, ‘When Other Things Arent Equal: Saving Ceteris Paribus Laws from Vacuity,’ British Journal of the Philosophy of Science46 (1995
-
1991. Mind, 100: 81–110. It has plausibly been claimed that these conditions must be non-identical in order to deflect worries about dispositional explanations being vacuous. For discussion, see Fodor, ‘You Can Fool Some of the People All of the Time: Hedged Laws and Psychological Explanations’ 19–33, and Paul Pietroski and Georges Rey, ‘When Other Things Aren't Equal: Saving Ceteris Paribus Laws from Vacuity,’ British Journal of the Philosophy of Science46 (1995)
-
(1991)
Mind
, vol.100
, pp. 81-110
-
-
-
46
-
-
0004088235
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, Humes claim that causes and effects must be ‘distinct’ entities should be understood to impose this same requirement of non-causal definition on nomic properties., See 1888), 86. For discussion, see Elizabeth Anscombe, ‘Times, Beginnings, and Causes,’ reprinted A. Kenney, ed., Rationalism, Empiricism, and Idealism (Oxford: Clarendon Press 86–103, at 88., ed
-
Selby-Bigge, L. A., ed. 1986. A Treatise of Human Nature Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hume's claim that causes and effects must be ‘distinct’ entities should be understood to impose this same requirement of non-causal definition on nomic properties., See 1888), 86. For discussion, see Elizabeth Anscombe, ‘Times, Beginnings, and Causes,’ reprinted in A. Kenney, ed., Rationalism, Empiricism, and Idealism (Oxford: Clarendon Press 86–103, at 88.
-
(1986)
A Treatise of Human Nature
-
-
Selby-Bigge, L.A.1
-
47
-
-
85063697982
-
-
Though his ‘Reply to Tyler Bürge,’ read at the Western Division APA, Davidson writes that ‘it would be perfectly possible to individuate each igneous rock non-causal terms (by location at various times, etc.)’ (ms., 5). It is worth comparing such space-time descriptions with Humes own account of ‘distinct’ objects (see note 46 above). The fact that strict laws might be confined to formulation such terms illustrates just how useless they would be for the purposes of explanation and prediction. For discussion, see ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §VI, and §V below
-
1989. Though in his ‘Reply to Tyler Bürge,’ read at the Western Division APA, Davidson writes that ‘it would be perfectly possible to individuate each igneous rock in non-causal terms (by location at various times, etc.)’ (ms., 5). It is worth comparing such space-time descriptions with Hume's own account of ‘distinct’ objects (see note 46 above). The fact that strict laws might be confined to formulation in such terms illustrates just how useless they would be for the purposes of explanation and prediction. For discussion, see ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §VI, and §V below.
-
(1989)
-
-
-
49
-
-
85063698264
-
-
41ff. Goodman, however, allows that this distinction may be contextual, with no stable or unitary vocabulary for picking out ‘manifest’ properties (41, n.7). Davidson, following Quine, must take a more foundationalist line on such properties due to the PNCC. See discussion immediately below
-
Goodman, Nelson. Fact, Forecast, and Fiction 41ff. Goodman, however, allows that this distinction may be contextual, with no stable or unitary vocabulary for picking out ‘manifest’ properties (41, n.7). Davidson, following Quine, must take a more foundationalist line on such properties due to the PNCC. See discussion immediately below.
-
Fact, Forecast, and Fiction
-
-
Goodman, N.1
-
51
-
-
85063701836
-
‘Facts of the Matter,’ reprinted in R. Shahan and C. Swoyer, eds
-
Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 155–69, at
-
Quine. 1979. “ ‘Facts of the Matter,’ reprinted in R. Shahan and C. Swoyer, eds. ”. In Essays on the Philosophy of W.V. Quine 165–6. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press. 155–69, at
-
(1979)
Essays on the Philosophy of W.V. Quine
, pp. 165-166
-
-
Quine1
-
52
-
-
24644523461
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, I thus disagree with Barry Strouds claim, his excellent ‘Quines Physicalism,’ 321–33, that Quines physicalism ‘contains nothing to make it a version of physicalism particular. To say only that there is or will be some single, unified science capable of expressing everything that is fundamentally true of the world is not to attribute any specific character to the world’ (326). On the contrary, Quines attitude towards the dispositional idiom provides a determinate, if unarticulated, conception of the character of physical terms., and, eds
-
Barrett, R., and Gibson, R., eds. 1990. Perspectives on Quine Oxford: Basil Blackwell. I thus disagree with Barry Stroud's claim, in his excellent ‘Quine's Physicalism,’ in 321–33, that Quine's physicalism ‘contains nothing to make it a version of physicalism in particular. To say only that there is or will be some single, unified science capable of expressing everything that is fundamentally true of the world is not to attribute any specific character to the world’ (326). On the contrary, Quine's attitude towards the dispositional idiom provides a determinate, if unarticulated, conception of the character of physical terms.
-
(1990)
Perspectives on Quine
-
-
Barrett, R.1
Gibson, R.2
-
55
-
-
0011173730
-
‘Representation and Interpretation,’ in
-
Mohyeldin K.A., Said W.H., (eds), Oxford: Clarendon Press, New- ton-Smith, R. Viale, and K. Wilkes, eds., 13–26, at 24,. Edited by
-
Davidson. 1990. “ ‘Representation and Interpretation,’ in ”. In Modelling the Mind Edited by: Mohyeldin, K. A., and Said, W. H., Oxford: Clarendon Press. New- ton-Smith, R. Viale, and K. Wilkes, eds., 13–26, at 24
-
(1990)
Modelling the Mind
-
-
Davidson1
-
56
-
-
85063701724
-
-
I elaborate on the issues touched on this paragraph ‘Normativity, Externalism and the Status of Content,’ ms
-
I elaborate on the issues touched on in this paragraph in ‘Normativity, Externalism and the Status of Content,’ ms.
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
85063698028
-
-
I am indebted to an anonymous referee for forcing me to be clearer on the issues discussed what follows the text. I have discussed related issues at greater length ‘Normativity, Externalism and the Status of Content.’
-
I am indebted to an anonymous referee for forcing me to be clearer on the issues discussed in what follows in the text. I have discussed related issues at greater length in ‘Normativity, Externalism and the Status of Content.’
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
85063703738
-
-
Recall, however, the moral of §II: ‘changing the subject’ here must refer to bridge laws, if it is even to suggest the possibility of quasi-definitional reduction. Davidsons point here seems to be that whether a change of subject has occurred depends upon whether the interests to which the vocabulary is responsive continue to have their purposes served by the new vocabulary. Suppose one is envisaging having dropped dispositional properties like elasticity favor of nomic properties. Suppose also that no change of subject thus occurs. Then, since nomic properties are not interest-relative, one will have justified the claim that the particular explanatory interest that ‘elasticity’ served is inessential to the explanatory role it plays. This is because no change of subject has occurred moving from interest-relative to non-interest-relative terms. See further discussion of this idea below the text
-
Recall, however, the moral of §II: ‘changing the subject’ here must refer to bridge laws, if it is even to suggest the possibility of quasi-definitional reduction. Davidson's point here seems to be that whether a change of subject has occurred depends upon whether the interests to which the vocabulary is responsive continue to have their purposes served by the new vocabulary. Suppose one is envisaging having dropped dispositional properties like elasticity in favor of nomic properties. Suppose also that no change of subject thus occurs. Then, since nomic properties are not interest-relative, one will have justified the claim that the particular explanatory interest that ‘elasticity’ served is inessential to the explanatory role it plays. This is because no change of subject has occurred in moving from interest-relative to non-interest-relative terms. See further discussion of this idea below in the text.
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
85063698313
-
-
Strictly speaking, the issue is, rationality, not normativity generally; indeed, as Davidson himself observes, normativity pervades all the sciences some sense (ME, 220–1; PEA, 47). With this mind, I will continue to talk terms of normativity. I have discussed this issue further ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §V
-
Strictly speaking, the issue is rationality, not normativity generally; indeed, as Davidson himself observes, normativity pervades all the sciences in some sense (ME, 220–1; PEA, 47). With this in mind, I will continue to talk in terms of normativity. I have discussed this issue further in ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §V.
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
85063699327
-
-
‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §VI, I discuss this point further, the context of criticizing Childs (and McDowells) reconstruction of Davidsons argument for mental anomalism (see note 4 above). I am grateful to David Brink for reassuring discussion of this issue
-
In ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §VI, I discuss this point further, in the context of criticizing Child's (and McDowell's) reconstruction of Davidson's argument for mental anomalism (see note 4 above). I am grateful to David Brink for reassuring discussion of this issue.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
85063701719
-
-
distinguishing between the dispositional status of psychological and folk-physical/special-science properties, Davidson may have mind a certain view about the concept of error (conditions of correctness for meanings and beliefs). The view is that the possibility of error is necessary and idiosyncratic to psychological properties, and depends upon failure of nomic inclusion. This would shift the weight of mental anomalism back onto considerations of normativity. I have discussed this issue depth, and argued that this line of argument fails, ‘Semantic Determinants and Psychology as a Science,’ forthcoming in
-
Erkenntnis. In distinguishing between the dispositional status of psychological and folk-physical/special-science properties, Davidson may have in mind a certain view about the concept of error (conditions of correctness for meanings and beliefs). The view is that the possibility of error is necessary and idiosyncratic to psychological properties, and depends upon failure of nomic inclusion. This would shift the weight of mental anomalism back onto considerations of normativity. I have discussed this issue in depth, and argued that this line of argument fails, in ‘Semantic Determinants and Psychology as a Science,’ forthcoming in
-
Erkenntnis.
-
-
-
64
-
-
85063703849
-
-
The status of folk-physics is a separate matter. ‘Normativity, Externalism and the Status of Content,’ I argue that normativity and external constitution, the two essential features of commonsense psychological content, derive from an attitude of committed enquiry on which science, and therefore the very basis of eliminativism, depends
-
The status of folk-physics is a separate matter. In ‘Normativity, Externalism and the Status of Content,’ I argue that normativity and external constitution, the two essential features of commonsense psychological content, derive from an attitude of committed enquiry on which science, and therefore the very basis of eliminativism, depends.
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
85063700438
-
-
This formulation of closure is weaker than Davidsons (ME 222), which further holds that But my formulation is easier to work with, and the difficulties it incurs when treated as an assumption the argument for anomalous monism (see below the text) carry over directly to Davidsons. See also the discussion below the text on the relation between general monism and closure
-
This formulation of closure is weaker than Davidson's (ME 222), which further holds that every event has a physical causal explanation. But my formulation is easier to work with, and the difficulties it incurs when treated as an assumption in the argument for anomalous monism (see below in the text) carry over directly to Davidson's. See also the discussion below in the text on the relation between general monism and closure.
-
Every event has a physical causal explanation.
-
-
-
68
-
-
85063703708
-
-
2 .’ This apparent oversight might be explained by a tacit assumption of closure, since (with monism as yet undecided) closure conflicts with and thus rules out the need to consider the possibility of such laws. For further discussion, see ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §IV. McLaughlin, ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental’ (343), appears to realize that closure cannot legitimately be assumed Davidsons picture. But he fails to see that his own identification of strict and homogeneously formulated laws (see note 16 above), entails, closure (see below the text, and note 69
-
2 .’ This apparent oversight might be explained by a tacit assumption of closure, since (with monism as yet undecided) closure conflicts with and thus rules out the need to consider the possibility of such laws. For further discussion, see ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism,’ §IV. McLaughlin, in ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental’ (343), appears to realize that closure cannot legitimately be assumed in Davidson's picture. But he fails to see that his own identification of strict and homogeneously formulated laws (see note 16 above) entails closure (see below in the text, and note 69).
-
-
-
-
69
-
-
85063699271
-
-
It is important to realize that closure is weaker than either of these claims. Closure does hold that there are homogeneously formulated (i.e. physical) laws covering all causally interacting physical events. But closure is compatible with overdetermination together with the existence of strict psychophysical laws of succession (see discussion below the text). It is therefore compatible with the existence of heterogeneously formulated strict laws. Thus, the criticisms I made §II of the two claims do not tell directly against assuming closure
-
It is important to realize that closure is weaker than either of these claims. Closure does hold that there are homogeneously formulated (i.e. physical) laws covering all causally interacting physical events. But closure is compatible with overdetermination together with the existence of strict psychophysical laws of succession (see discussion below in the text). It is therefore compatible with the existence of heterogeneously formulated strict laws. Thus, the criticisms I made in §II of the two claims do not tell directly against assuming closure.
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
85063703757
-
-
Material from earlier versions of this paper was presented to colloquia at University College, Dublin and the University of California at Riverside, and I am grateful to those audiences for discussion. For valuable advice on earlier drafts, I am especially indebted to David Brink and Pat Kitcher. I would also like to thank Kelly Becker, Paul Churchland, Adrian Cussins, Nick Jolley, Pierre Keller, Philip Kitcher, Noa Latham, Jim Levine, Sandy Mitchell, David Perlmutter, Jessica Pfeifer and Gila Sher, as well as several anonymous referees, for helpful comments.
-
Material from earlier versions of this paper was presented to colloquia at University College, Dublin and the University of California at Riverside, and I am grateful to those audiences for discussion. For valuable advice on earlier drafts, I am especially indebted to David Brink and Pat Kitcher. I would also like to thank Kelly Becker, Paul Churchland, Adrian Cussins, Nick Jolley, Pierre Keller, Philip Kitcher, Noa Latham, Jim Levine, Sandy Mitchell, David Perlmutter, Jessica Pfeifer and Gila Sher, as well as several anonymous referees, for helpful comments.
-
-
-
|