메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 51, Issue 204, 2001, Pages 289-306

Strategies for a logic of plurals

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33746163553     PISSN: 00318094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.0031-8094.2001.00231.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (54)

References (46)
  • 1
    • 84925974568 scopus 로고
    • The Theory of Descriptions
    • Popularly but wrongly attributed to Meinong at pp. 324-5
    • Popularly but wrongly attributed to Meinong. See T.J. Smiley, 'The Theory of Descriptions', Proceedings of the British Academy, 67 (1981), pp. 321-37, at pp. 324-5
    • (1981) Proceedings of the British Academy , vol.67 , pp. 321-337
    • Smiley, T.J.1
  • 3
    • 0009104751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Logic in Mathematics' (1914)
    • ed. H. Hermes et al, Oxford: Blackwell, at p. 227
    • Frege, 'Logic in Mathematics' (1914), in his Posthumous Writings, ed. H. Hermes et al. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1979), pp. 203-50, at p. 227
    • (1979) Posthumous Writings , pp. 203-250
    • Frege1
  • 4
    • 0039969294 scopus 로고
    • Complex Individuals and Multigrade Relations
    • See A. Morton, 'Complex Individuals and Multigrade Relations', Noûs, 9 (1975), pp. 309-18
    • (1975) Noûs , vol.9 , pp. 309-318
    • A.morton1
  • 7
    • 0000665713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To Be is to Be a Value of a Variable (or to Be Some Values of Some Variables)
    • Boolos' work on plurals can be found
    • Boolos' work on plurals can be found in 'To Be is to Be a Value of a Variable (or to Be Some Values of Some Variables)', Journal of Philosophy, 81 (1984), pp. 430-49
    • (1984) Journal of Philosophy , vol.81 , pp. 430-449
  • 8
    • 0001599661 scopus 로고
    • Nominalist Platonism
    • 'Nominalist Platonism', Philosophical Review, 94 (1985), pp. 327-44
    • (1985) Philosophical Review , vol.94 , pp. 327-344
  • 9
    • 0001097013 scopus 로고
    • Reading the Begriffsschrift
    • and 'Reading the Begriffsschrift', Mind, 94 (1985), pp. 331-44
    • (1985) Mind , vol.94 , pp. 331-344
  • 10
    • 0039257535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Logic, Mathematics and Philosophy
    • §5. For some initial criticisms,
    • For some initial criticisms, see A. Oliver, 'Logic, Mathematics and Philosophy', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51 (2000), pp. 857-73, §5
    • (2000) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.51 , pp. 857-873
    • Oliver, A.1
  • 12
    • 0003786255 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • This was emphatically not some casual thought. He makes identical remarks about 'Bunsen and Kirchhoff laid the foundations of spectral analysis' in his letter to Russell of 28 July 1902: see his Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, ed. G. Gabriel et al. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), p. 140
    • (1980) Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence , pp. 140
    • Gabriel, G.1
  • 13
    • 84962994242 scopus 로고
    • Frege and Dummett are Two
    • For the true story,
    • For the true story, see A. Oliver, 'Frege and Dummett are Two', The Philosophical Quarterly, 44 (1994), pp. 74-82
    • (1994) The Philosophical Quarterly , vol.44 , pp. 74-82
    • Oliver, A.1
  • 14
    • 85187733215 scopus 로고
    • The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice-Theoretical Approach
    • e.g, R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze and A. von Stechow eds, Berlin: De Gruyter
    • See, e.g., G. Link, 'The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: a Lattice-Theoretical Approach', in R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze and A. von Stechow (eds), Meaning, Use and Interpretation of Language (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1983), pp. 302-23
    • (1983) Meaning, Use and Interpretation of Language , pp. 302-323
    • Link, G.1
  • 15
    • 84937289021 scopus 로고
    • We owe the structure of this neat argument Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • We owe the structure of this neat argument to P. Lasersohn, Plurality, Conjunction and Events (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995), pp. 96-104
    • (1995) Plurality, Conjunction and Events , pp. 96-104
    • Lasersohn, P.1
  • 16
    • 60949302385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language
    • T.J. Smiley (ed.) at pp. 19-20
    • Higginbotham, 'On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language', in T.J. Smiley (ed.), Philosophical Logic (Oxford UP', 1998), pp. 1-27, at pp. 19-20
    • (1998) Philosophical Logic (Oxford UP') , pp. 1-27
    • Higginbotham1
  • 17
    • 0010204685 scopus 로고
    • Tom, Dick and Harry, and All the King's Men'
    • G. Massey, 'Tom, Dick and Harry, and All the King's Men', American Philosophical Quarterly, 13 (1976), pp. 89-107
    • (1976) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.13 , pp. 89-107
    • Massey, G.1
  • 19
    • 80053793285 scopus 로고
    • (definition of |=), p. 133 (transitivity), and p. 136 (logical equivalence)
    • For example, when sets imply sentences, implication ceases to be transitive and logical equivalence can no longer be defined as reciprocal implication. Even an author as astute as Hodges falls into this trap: see W. Hodges, Logic (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977), p. 128 (definition of |=), p. 133 (transitivity), and p. 136 (logical equivalence)
    • (1977) Logic (Harmondsworth: Penguin) , pp. 128
    • Hodges, W.1
  • 20
    • 0347834176 scopus 로고
    • tr. D. Steele (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul) §3
    • B. Bolzano, Paradoxes of the Infinite (1851), tr. D. Steele (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1950), §3
    • (1851) Paradoxes of the Infinite
    • Bolzano, B.1
  • 21
    • 0001881453 scopus 로고
    • The Logical Form of Action Sentences
    • N Rescher ed, Univ. of Pittsburgh Press
    • D. Davidson, 'The Logical Form of Action Sentences', in N Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action (Univ. of Pittsburgh Press, 1967), pp. 81-95
    • (1967) The Logic of Decision and Action , pp. 81-95
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 24
    • 35649011625 scopus 로고
    • repr. in his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984) at pp. 208-10
    • Davidson, 'The Method of Truth in Metaphysics' (1977), repr. in his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), pp. 199-214, at pp. 208-10
    • (1977) The Method of Truth in Metaphysics , pp. 199-214
    • Davidson1
  • 25
    • 0005011106 scopus 로고
    • The Role of Semantics in a Grammar
    • New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston at pp. 152-3
    • See J. McCawley, 'The Role of Semantics in a Grammar', in E. Bach and R. Harms (eds), Universals in Linguistic Theory (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1968), pp. 124-69, at pp. 152-3
    • (1968) Universals in Linguistic Theory , pp. 124-169
    • McCawley, J.1
  • 26
    • 39249084008 scopus 로고
    • The Semantics and Syntax of Number and Numbers
    • The idea also appeared independently in R. Bartsch, 'The Semantics and Syntax of Number and Numbers', in J. Kimball (ed.), Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 11 (New York: Seminar Press, 1973), pp. 55-93, at pp. 74-5. As it happens, both fail to include the 'No one else did' clause. We shall not press the opposite objection, that if 'The Fs φd', it need not be the case that every one of the Fs played a part in the φing (e.g., 'The Romans conquered Gaul')
    • (1973) Syntax and Semantics , vol.11 , pp. 55-93
    • Kimball (ed.), J.1
  • 28
    • 80053682969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schein means to do this: 'All predicates are, first of all, about events' (Plurals and Events, p. 3).
    • Schein means to do this: 'All predicates are, first of all, about events' (Plurals and Events, p. 3)
  • 29
    • 80053846199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And Higginbotham says that both he and Parsons had extended Davidson's analysis of action verbs to 'all predicates whatsoever': 'On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language', p. 20
    • On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language , pp. 2
  • 30
    • 84936216720 scopus 로고
    • Where he cites his 'On Semantics'
    • where he cites his 'On Semantics', Linguistic Inquiry, 16 (1985), pp. 547-93
    • (1985) Linguistic Inquiry , vol.16 , pp. 547-593
  • 31
    • 0003577034 scopus 로고
    • and Parsons, Events in the Semantics of English (MIT Press, 1990). In fact, however, Parsons (p. 187) says that predicates involving common nouns 'probably do not pick out events or states'. And even for Schein, not all predicates are predicates of events. For he turns 'is one of into the converse of the predicative relation, and this has no new place for event terms
    • (1990) Events in the Semantics of English (MIT Press)
    • Parsons1
  • 32
    • 42349096570 scopus 로고
    • Some Explanations in Reply to Mr Bradley
    • 'That it is meaningless (as Mr Bradley contends) to regard a class as being or not being a member of itself, must be assumed for the avoidance of a more mathematical contradiction; but I cannot see that this could be meaningless if there were such things as classes': Russell, 'Some Explanations in Reply to Mr Bradley', Mind, 19 (1910), pp. 373-8, at p. 376
    • (1910) Mind , vol.19 , pp. 373-378
    • Russell1
  • 33
    • 0039170583 scopus 로고
    • Investigations in the Foundations of Set Theory, F
    • tr. in J. van Heijenoort (ed.) at p. 200
    • E. Zermelo, 'Investigations in the Foundations of Set Theory, F (1908), tr. in J. van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel (Harvard UP, 1967), pp. 199-215, at p. 200
    • (1908) From Frege to Gödel (Harvard UP) , pp. 199-215
    • Zermelo, E.1
  • 34
    • 80053776879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his rejoinder to Oliver's 'The Logic of Plurals', presented at the Oxford Philosophy Society, May 1997
    • The Logic of Plurals
  • 35
    • 80053667168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Various examples of 'collections': Parsons suggests an analysis of plural action sentences just like Castaneda's, except that he talks of groups instead of sets or sums. But he says next to nothing about the nature of them (Events in the Semantics of English, pp. 45-7)
    • Events in the Semantics of English , pp. 45-47
  • 36
    • 80053811014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCawley, who, as we have observed, changes the subject to sets, explains that his sets are not the same as those of mathematics, since he has no empty set and ignores the difference between an individual and its singleton ('The Role of Semantics in a Grammar', p. 146)
    • The Role of Semantics in a Grammar , pp. 146
  • 37
    • 80053843388 scopus 로고
    • Cresswell makes order count, for example, taking 'admire each other' to apply to ordered pairs
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • Cresswell makes order count, for example, taking 'admire each other' to apply to ordered pairs: Semantical Essays: Possible Worlds and Their Rivals (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988), p. 138
    • (1988) Semantical Essays: Possible Worlds and Their Rivals , pp. 138
  • 38
    • 80053863114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Lewis, who does, reformulates the argument using 'class-like thing' in place of 'set': Parts of Classes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), p. 68.
    • David Lewis, who does, reformulates the argument using 'class-like thing' in place of 'set': Parts of Classes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), p. 68
  • 40
    • 84925907074 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Aggregates
    • T. Burge, 'A Theory of Aggregates', Noûs, 11 (1977), pp. 97-117
    • (1977) Noûs , vol.11 , pp. 97-117
    • Burge, T.1
  • 41
    • 34248867913 scopus 로고
    • Groups, I' and 'Groups, II
    • 723-744
    • F. Landman, 'Groups, I' and 'Groups, II', both in Linguistics and Philosophy, 12 (1989), pp. 559-605 and 723-44
    • (1989) Linguistics and Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 559-605
    • Landman, F.1
  • 42
    • 27244453484 scopus 로고
    • Collective Readings of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases
    • P. Gärdenfors ed, Dordrecht: Reidel
    • J. Lønning, 'Collective Readings of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases', in P. Gärdenfors (ed.), Generalised Quantifiers (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1987), pp. 203-35
    • (1987) Generalised Quantifiers , pp. 203-235
    • Lønning, J.1
  • 45
    • 0041156247 scopus 로고
    • Second-Order Logic Still Wild
    • M. Resnik, 'Second-Order Logic Still Wild', Journal of Philosophy, 85 (1988), pp. 75-87
    • (1988) Journal of Philosophy , vol.85 , pp. 75-87
    • Resnik, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.