-
1
-
-
84925974568
-
The Theory of Descriptions
-
Popularly but wrongly attributed to Meinong at pp. 324-5
-
Popularly but wrongly attributed to Meinong. See T.J. Smiley, 'The Theory of Descriptions', Proceedings of the British Academy, 67 (1981), pp. 321-37, at pp. 324-5
-
(1981)
Proceedings of the British Academy
, vol.67
, pp. 321-337
-
-
Smiley, T.J.1
-
3
-
-
0009104751
-
Logic in Mathematics' (1914)
-
ed. H. Hermes et al, Oxford: Blackwell, at p. 227
-
Frege, 'Logic in Mathematics' (1914), in his Posthumous Writings, ed. H. Hermes et al. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1979), pp. 203-50, at p. 227
-
(1979)
Posthumous Writings
, pp. 203-250
-
-
Frege1
-
4
-
-
0039969294
-
Complex Individuals and Multigrade Relations
-
See A. Morton, 'Complex Individuals and Multigrade Relations', Noûs, 9 (1975), pp. 309-18
-
(1975)
Noûs
, vol.9
, pp. 309-318
-
-
A.morton1
-
6
-
-
0000296263
-
Plurals
-
See also J. Higginbotham and B. Schein, in 'Plurals', Proceedings of the North Eastern Linguistics Society, 19 (Univ. of Massachusetts, 1989), pp. 161-75, who argue that plural terms are predicative in nature and refer to concepts
-
(1989)
Proceedings of the North Eastern Linguistics Society
, vol.19
, pp. 161-175
-
-
Higginbotham, J.1
Schein, B.2
-
7
-
-
0000665713
-
To Be is to Be a Value of a Variable (or to Be Some Values of Some Variables)
-
Boolos' work on plurals can be found
-
Boolos' work on plurals can be found in 'To Be is to Be a Value of a Variable (or to Be Some Values of Some Variables)', Journal of Philosophy, 81 (1984), pp. 430-49
-
(1984)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.81
, pp. 430-449
-
-
-
8
-
-
0001599661
-
Nominalist Platonism
-
'Nominalist Platonism', Philosophical Review, 94 (1985), pp. 327-44
-
(1985)
Philosophical Review
, vol.94
, pp. 327-344
-
-
-
9
-
-
0001097013
-
Reading the Begriffsschrift
-
and 'Reading the Begriffsschrift', Mind, 94 (1985), pp. 331-44
-
(1985)
Mind
, vol.94
, pp. 331-344
-
-
-
10
-
-
0039257535
-
Logic, Mathematics and Philosophy
-
§5. For some initial criticisms,
-
For some initial criticisms, see A. Oliver, 'Logic, Mathematics and Philosophy', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51 (2000), pp. 857-73, §5
-
(2000)
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
, vol.51
, pp. 857-873
-
-
Oliver, A.1
-
12
-
-
0003786255
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
This was emphatically not some casual thought. He makes identical remarks about 'Bunsen and Kirchhoff laid the foundations of spectral analysis' in his letter to Russell of 28 July 1902: see his Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, ed. G. Gabriel et al. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), p. 140
-
(1980)
Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence
, pp. 140
-
-
Gabriel, G.1
-
13
-
-
84962994242
-
Frege and Dummett are Two
-
For the true story,
-
For the true story, see A. Oliver, 'Frege and Dummett are Two', The Philosophical Quarterly, 44 (1994), pp. 74-82
-
(1994)
The Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.44
, pp. 74-82
-
-
Oliver, A.1
-
14
-
-
85187733215
-
The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice-Theoretical Approach
-
e.g, R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze and A. von Stechow eds, Berlin: De Gruyter
-
See, e.g., G. Link, 'The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: a Lattice-Theoretical Approach', in R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze and A. von Stechow (eds), Meaning, Use and Interpretation of Language (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1983), pp. 302-23
-
(1983)
Meaning, Use and Interpretation of Language
, pp. 302-323
-
-
Link, G.1
-
15
-
-
84937289021
-
-
We owe the structure of this neat argument Dordrecht: Kluwer
-
We owe the structure of this neat argument to P. Lasersohn, Plurality, Conjunction and Events (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995), pp. 96-104
-
(1995)
Plurality, Conjunction and Events
, pp. 96-104
-
-
Lasersohn, P.1
-
16
-
-
60949302385
-
On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language
-
T.J. Smiley (ed.) at pp. 19-20
-
Higginbotham, 'On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language', in T.J. Smiley (ed.), Philosophical Logic (Oxford UP', 1998), pp. 1-27, at pp. 19-20
-
(1998)
Philosophical Logic (Oxford UP')
, pp. 1-27
-
-
Higginbotham1
-
17
-
-
0010204685
-
Tom, Dick and Harry, and All the King's Men'
-
G. Massey, 'Tom, Dick and Harry, and All the King's Men', American Philosophical Quarterly, 13 (1976), pp. 89-107
-
(1976)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.13
, pp. 89-107
-
-
Massey, G.1
-
19
-
-
80053793285
-
-
(definition of |=), p. 133 (transitivity), and p. 136 (logical equivalence)
-
For example, when sets imply sentences, implication ceases to be transitive and logical equivalence can no longer be defined as reciprocal implication. Even an author as astute as Hodges falls into this trap: see W. Hodges, Logic (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977), p. 128 (definition of |=), p. 133 (transitivity), and p. 136 (logical equivalence)
-
(1977)
Logic (Harmondsworth: Penguin)
, pp. 128
-
-
Hodges, W.1
-
20
-
-
0347834176
-
-
tr. D. Steele (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul) §3
-
B. Bolzano, Paradoxes of the Infinite (1851), tr. D. Steele (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1950), §3
-
(1851)
Paradoxes of the Infinite
-
-
Bolzano, B.1
-
21
-
-
0001881453
-
The Logical Form of Action Sentences
-
N Rescher ed, Univ. of Pittsburgh Press
-
D. Davidson, 'The Logical Form of Action Sentences', in N Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action (Univ. of Pittsburgh Press, 1967), pp. 81-95
-
(1967)
The Logic of Decision and Action
, pp. 81-95
-
-
Davidson, D.1
-
24
-
-
35649011625
-
-
repr. in his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984) at pp. 208-10
-
Davidson, 'The Method of Truth in Metaphysics' (1977), repr. in his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), pp. 199-214, at pp. 208-10
-
(1977)
The Method of Truth in Metaphysics
, pp. 199-214
-
-
Davidson1
-
25
-
-
0005011106
-
The Role of Semantics in a Grammar
-
New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston at pp. 152-3
-
See J. McCawley, 'The Role of Semantics in a Grammar', in E. Bach and R. Harms (eds), Universals in Linguistic Theory (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1968), pp. 124-69, at pp. 152-3
-
(1968)
Universals in Linguistic Theory
, pp. 124-169
-
-
McCawley, J.1
-
26
-
-
39249084008
-
The Semantics and Syntax of Number and Numbers
-
The idea also appeared independently in R. Bartsch, 'The Semantics and Syntax of Number and Numbers', in J. Kimball (ed.), Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 11 (New York: Seminar Press, 1973), pp. 55-93, at pp. 74-5. As it happens, both fail to include the 'No one else did' clause. We shall not press the opposite objection, that if 'The Fs φd', it need not be the case that every one of the Fs played a part in the φing (e.g., 'The Romans conquered Gaul')
-
(1973)
Syntax and Semantics
, vol.11
, pp. 55-93
-
-
Kimball (ed.), J.1
-
28
-
-
80053682969
-
-
Schein means to do this: 'All predicates are, first of all, about events' (Plurals and Events, p. 3).
-
Schein means to do this: 'All predicates are, first of all, about events' (Plurals and Events, p. 3)
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
80053846199
-
-
And Higginbotham says that both he and Parsons had extended Davidson's analysis of action verbs to 'all predicates whatsoever': 'On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language', p. 20
-
On Higher-Order Logic and Natural Language
, pp. 2
-
-
-
30
-
-
84936216720
-
Where he cites his 'On Semantics'
-
where he cites his 'On Semantics', Linguistic Inquiry, 16 (1985), pp. 547-93
-
(1985)
Linguistic Inquiry
, vol.16
, pp. 547-593
-
-
-
31
-
-
0003577034
-
-
and Parsons, Events in the Semantics of English (MIT Press, 1990). In fact, however, Parsons (p. 187) says that predicates involving common nouns 'probably do not pick out events or states'. And even for Schein, not all predicates are predicates of events. For he turns 'is one of into the converse of the predicative relation, and this has no new place for event terms
-
(1990)
Events in the Semantics of English (MIT Press)
-
-
Parsons1
-
32
-
-
42349096570
-
Some Explanations in Reply to Mr Bradley
-
'That it is meaningless (as Mr Bradley contends) to regard a class as being or not being a member of itself, must be assumed for the avoidance of a more mathematical contradiction; but I cannot see that this could be meaningless if there were such things as classes': Russell, 'Some Explanations in Reply to Mr Bradley', Mind, 19 (1910), pp. 373-8, at p. 376
-
(1910)
Mind
, vol.19
, pp. 373-378
-
-
Russell1
-
33
-
-
0039170583
-
Investigations in the Foundations of Set Theory, F
-
tr. in J. van Heijenoort (ed.) at p. 200
-
E. Zermelo, 'Investigations in the Foundations of Set Theory, F (1908), tr. in J. van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel (Harvard UP, 1967), pp. 199-215, at p. 200
-
(1908)
From Frege to Gödel (Harvard UP)
, pp. 199-215
-
-
Zermelo, E.1
-
34
-
-
80053776879
-
-
In his rejoinder to Oliver's 'The Logic of Plurals', presented at the Oxford Philosophy Society, May 1997
-
The Logic of Plurals
-
-
-
35
-
-
80053667168
-
-
Various examples of 'collections': Parsons suggests an analysis of plural action sentences just like Castaneda's, except that he talks of groups instead of sets or sums. But he says next to nothing about the nature of them (Events in the Semantics of English, pp. 45-7)
-
Events in the Semantics of English
, pp. 45-47
-
-
-
36
-
-
80053811014
-
-
McCawley, who, as we have observed, changes the subject to sets, explains that his sets are not the same as those of mathematics, since he has no empty set and ignores the difference between an individual and its singleton ('The Role of Semantics in a Grammar', p. 146)
-
The Role of Semantics in a Grammar
, pp. 146
-
-
-
37
-
-
80053843388
-
Cresswell makes order count, for example, taking 'admire each other' to apply to ordered pairs
-
Dordrecht: Kluwer
-
Cresswell makes order count, for example, taking 'admire each other' to apply to ordered pairs: Semantical Essays: Possible Worlds and Their Rivals (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988), p. 138
-
(1988)
Semantical Essays: Possible Worlds and Their Rivals
, pp. 138
-
-
-
38
-
-
80053863114
-
-
David Lewis, who does, reformulates the argument using 'class-like thing' in place of 'set': Parts of Classes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), p. 68.
-
David Lewis, who does, reformulates the argument using 'class-like thing' in place of 'set': Parts of Classes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), p. 68
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
84925907074
-
A Theory of Aggregates
-
T. Burge, 'A Theory of Aggregates', Noûs, 11 (1977), pp. 97-117
-
(1977)
Noûs
, vol.11
, pp. 97-117
-
-
Burge, T.1
-
41
-
-
34248867913
-
Groups, I' and 'Groups, II
-
723-744
-
F. Landman, 'Groups, I' and 'Groups, II', both in Linguistics and Philosophy, 12 (1989), pp. 559-605 and 723-44
-
(1989)
Linguistics and Philosophy
, vol.12
, pp. 559-605
-
-
Landman, F.1
-
42
-
-
27244453484
-
Collective Readings of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases
-
P. Gärdenfors ed, Dordrecht: Reidel
-
J. Lønning, 'Collective Readings of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases', in P. Gärdenfors (ed.), Generalised Quantifiers (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1987), pp. 203-35
-
(1987)
Generalised Quantifiers
, pp. 203-235
-
-
Lønning, J.1
-
45
-
-
0041156247
-
Second-Order Logic Still Wild
-
M. Resnik, 'Second-Order Logic Still Wild', Journal of Philosophy, 85 (1988), pp. 75-87
-
(1988)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.85
, pp. 75-87
-
-
Resnik, M.1
|