메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 114, Issue 1-2, 2003, Pages 47-79

Doxastic compatibilism and the ethics of belief

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33746162589     PISSN: 00318116     EISSN: 15730883     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/a:1024409201289     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (116)

References (69)
  • 1
    • 33746115901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voluntary Belief and Epistemic Evaluation
    • Matthias Steup, New York: Oxford University Press
    • This conclusion has also been argued for by Richard Feldman, Carl Ginet, Matthias Steup, and Bruce Russell. See Feldman, 'Voluntary Belief and Epistemic Evaluation', in Matthias Steup, Knowledge, Truth, and Duty (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 77-92,
    • (2001) Knowledge, Truth, and Duty , pp. 77-92
    • Feldman1
  • 2
    • 0040509318 scopus 로고
    • Epistemic Obligations
    • 'Epistemic Obligations', Philosophical Perspectives 2 (1988), pp. 235-256,
    • (1988) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.2 , pp. 235-256
  • 4
    • 33645163818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deciding to Believe
    • Steup, New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Ginet, 'Deciding to Believe', in Steup, Knowledge, Truth, and Duty (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 63-76.
    • (2001) Knowledge, Truth, and Duty , pp. 63-76
    • Ginet1
  • 5
    • 33751522329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doxastic Voluntarism and Epistemic Deontology
    • See Steup, 'Doxastic Voluntarism and Epistemic Deontology', Acta Analytica, 15 (2000), 25-56.
    • (2000) Acta Analytica , vol.15 , pp. 25-56
    • Steup1
  • 7
    • 33746149113 scopus 로고
    • The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification
    • William Alston defends a version of this argument against epistemic deontologism in 'The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification', Philosophical Perspectives 2 (1988)
    • (1988) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.2
  • 8
    • 0040511355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • and Alvin Plantinga defends a version of this argument in Warrant: The Current Debate (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Warrant: The Current Debate
  • 9
    • 55449087624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I mentioned, I think deontologism entails the view that we have epistemic obligations. So, if the argument shows that we don't have epistemic obligations, then it shows that epistemic deontologism is false. I do not think internalism entails the view that we have epistemic obligations. Alston and Plantinga clearly believe that internalism does entail epistemic obligations. Defending my claim about the independence of internalism is a topic of another paper. Nothing I say in this paper depends on this claim.
  • 10
    • 33746149113 scopus 로고
    • The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification
    • See William Alston, 'The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification', Philosophical Perspectives 2 (1988), 258-259.
    • (1988) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.2 , pp. 258-259
    • Alston, W.1
  • 11
    • 0642317790 scopus 로고
    • Concepts of Epistemic Justification
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • Alston, 'Concepts of Epistemic Justification', in his Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 91-92.
    • (1989) Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge , pp. 91-92
    • Alston1
  • 12
    • 0005011544 scopus 로고
    • 'Ought' Conversationally Implies 'Can'
    • April
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, ''Ought' Conversationally Implies 'Can'' Philosophical Review XCIII(2) (April 1984), 249-261.
    • (1984) Philosophical Review , vol.93 , Issue.2 , pp. 249-261
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 14
    • 55449109050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, p. 252
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, p. 252.
  • 15
    • 55449102696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stocker, p. 312
    • Stocker, p. 312.
  • 16
    • 0004094919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This criticism was suggested to me by several people, including Ted Drange, Michael Huemer, and an anonymous referee for Philosophical Studies.
    • Philosophical Studies
  • 17
    • 55449096231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This criticism was suggested to me by Michael Huemer, Michael McKenna, and Matthias Steup.
  • 18
    • 0004094919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An alternative response to this case is to modify the 'ought' implies 'can' principle as follows: "If S has an obligation to do A at time t, then S is able, at some time t*, to do A voluntarily at t". This is an interesting way to respond to the Sinnott-Armstrong case under consideration here. It preserves 'ought' implies 'can' while also granting that the guy does, at 6 p.m., still have an obligation to pick up his friend. As interesting as this modification is, it will not help in the cases I discuss later in this paper where a person has an obligation that they are never able to satisfy. This modification was suggested by an anonymous referee for Philosophical Studies.
    • Philosophical Studies
  • 19
    • 33746149113 scopus 로고
    • The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification
    • footnote 6
    • Alston, 'The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification', Philosophical Perspectives 2 (1988), footnote 6, p. 295.
    • (1988) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.2 , pp. 295
    • Alston1
  • 20
    • 55449119641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One might be tempted to say she should not have gone into your house in the first place and that is where the blame traces back to. If you are tempted to make this objection, assume that she is taken to a party at your house against her will.
  • 22
    • 55449136254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Richard Feldman raised this objection in a discussion we had about this topic.
  • 23
    • 55449128433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sarah McGrath raised this point at the 2002 Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference. Mark Heller seconded her point. Although I did not appreciate their help at first, I do now.
    • 2002 Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference
  • 24
    • 55449100085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This job comes with enough obligations I cannot always fulfill. For example, sometimes I am unable to be an excellent teacher. I do the best I can, but I fall short of teaching the way I ought to be teaching. Do you think my chair would be impressed if I explained that I had no obligation to teach well since I couldn't teach well during a particularly bad semester?
  • 25
    • 55449089601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, in all of these cases, if the tasks could be accomplished without special training, one would, according to my view, have the obligation to do the task. For example suppose all it took to put out a fire was pouring a cup of water on a small flame. Then everyone has the obligation to do that - even those who are tied to trees and are unable to do so.
  • 26
    • 55449135688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is the sort of obligation Richard Feldman calls "role oughts". I discuss Feldman's ideas about role oughts in section 4 of this paper.
  • 27
    • 55449105631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Bruce Russell proposed the following objection. Any day now, it will be my birthday. Suppose my friend Bruce, who lives in Detroit, promises that he will fly with his arms to Morgantown, WV, to attend my birthday party. It is physically impossible for him to fly this way. It looks like according to my view, he has this obligation despite the fact that the act is physically impossible for him to perform. This is a tricky objection. On an ordinary understanding of the example, I don't think he has the obligation to fly like a bird to visit me. This is because I don't think his "promise" would really be a promise. I would not believe him or expect him to come to my party. If the example is told in such a way that the "promise" is a legitimate promise, then I do think he has the obligation.
  • 31
    • 55449095695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steup
    • Bruce Russell also defends this claim in 'Epistemic and Moral Duty', in Steup, pp. 34-48.
    • Epistemic and Moral Duty , pp. 34-48
  • 33
    • 0040509320 scopus 로고
    • Evidentialism
    • I am assuming that evidentialism is true. For a careful articulation and defense of evidentialism see Richard Feldman and Earl Conee, 'Evidentialism', Philosophical Studies (1985), 15-34.
    • (1985) Philosophical Studies , pp. 15-34
    • Feldman, R.1    Conee, E.2
  • 34
    • 67650027165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amherst, NY:Prometheus Press
    • Theodore Drange, Nonbelief and Evil (Amherst, NY:Prometheus Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Nonbelief and Evil
    • Drange, T.1
  • 35
    • 55449114373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Alston's work is an exception.
  • 41
    • 55449085892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Another problem with this defense of involuntarism is that is seems to assume that one does A freely only if one does x because one decided to do A. I will challenge this assumption in the last paragraph of this section and discuss it further in sections 6, 7, and 8 of this paper. Basically, I think a free act must be done intentionally and that need not include any explicit decision or intention to do the act.
  • 42
    • 55449085626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is worth noting that Alston clearly believes that being able to do otherwise is a necessary condition for a free action.
  • 43
    • 55449116894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On my view, S's doing A intentionally does not imply that S has any beliefs about the likelihood of success at doing A.
  • 44
    • 55449104792 scopus 로고
    • London and New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • See part I of Louis P. Pojman's Religious Belief and the Will (London and New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1986) for a discussion of doxastic voluntarism in the history of philosophy.
    • (1986) Religious Belief and the Will , Issue.1 PART
    • Pojman, L.P.1
  • 50
    • 33846784592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobartian Voluntarism: Grounding a Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification
    • June
    • Mark Heller, 'Hobartian Voluntarism: Grounding a Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 81, no. 2 (June 2000), pp. 130-141.
    • (2000) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.81 , Issue.2 , pp. 130-141
    • Heller, M.1
  • 51
    • 0344031800 scopus 로고
    • Lewis' Ethics of Belief
    • P.A. Schilpp (ed.), LaSalle, IL: Open Court
    • Roderick Chisholm, 'Lewis' Ethics of Belief', in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of C.I. Lewis (LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1968),
    • (1968) The Philosophy of C.I. Lewis
    • Chisholm, R.1
  • 52
    • 0004126207 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
    • Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edition (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1977).
    • (1977) Theory of Knowledge, 2nd Edition
  • 56
    • 55449122368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steup, p. 33
    • Steup, p. 33.
  • 57
    • 55449090173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steup, p. 33
    • Steup, p. 33.
  • 58
    • 55449120935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steup, p. 34
    • Steup, p. 34.
  • 59
    • 55449130968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steup, p. 35
    • Steup, p. 35.
  • 61
    • 55449118341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In Richard Feldman's written comments on my paper. April 22, 2002.
  • 62
    • 55449108474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This criticism applies to Ginet's view as well.
  • 63
    • 55449108752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although I am not putting this forward as an analysis of freedom, I do think I am giving a necessary condition for a free action.
  • 64
    • 55449098551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Again, I do not think doing x intentionally involves beliefs. Thus, I can avoid a regress of beliefs about beliefs.
  • 65
    • 55449136253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Except for in cases like the Case of the Human Cannonball. See section 8.
  • 66
  • 67
    • 0010110035 scopus 로고
    • Deciding to Believe
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, 'Deciding to Believe', Problems of the Self (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
    • (1973) Problems of the Self
    • Williams, B.1
  • 68
    • 55449128737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doxastic Voluntarism and the Ethics of Belief
    • Steup and Alston's
    • Similar problems arise for Robert Audi's comparison of the forming of a belief to the formation of a wet ring left from a glass of water and Alston's comparison of believing to the secretion of gastric juices. See Audi 'Doxastic Voluntarism and the Ethics of Belief', in Steup and Alston's 'The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification'.
    • The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification
    • Audi1
  • 69
    • 55449101231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A lot of people have given me excellent comments on this paper and I am grateful to all of them. Theodore Drange, Adam Elga, Richard Feldman, Michael Huemer, Ned Markosian, Michael McKenna, Bruce Russell, David Sosa, and Matthias Steup gave me written comments on my paper. I have had many enjoyable and helpful discussions about the issues in this paper. For those discussions, I'd like to thank all of the people who gave me written comments and the participants at the 2002 Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference, Craig Duncan, Kristin Kuntz, James Lynch, Al Mele, and Heidi Payne. I am grateful to have had the opportunity to present a few of these ideas at the 1999 Rutgers Epistemology Conference.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.