메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 23, Issue 2, 2006, Pages 185-209

Households and the fiscal system

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33745655228     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: 14716437     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052506060225     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (3)

References (62)
  • 1
    • 77954512867 scopus 로고
    • Federal income taxation and the family
    • Classic articles from the 1970s that note the long-standing lack of political stasis and theoretical consensus include Boris I. Bittker, "Federal Income Taxation and the Family," Stanford Law Review 27 (1975): 1389-1463;
    • (1975) Stanford Law Review , vol.27 , pp. 1389-1463
    • Bittker, B.I.1
  • 2
    • 0041119979 scopus 로고
    • Taxation of the family in a comprehensive and simplified income tax
    • Michael J. McItyre and Oliver Oldman, "Taxation of the Family in a Comprehensive and Simplified Income Tax," Harvard Law Revieiv 90 (1977): 1573-1630.
    • (1977) Harvard Law Revieiv , vol.90 , pp. 1573-1630
    • McItyre, M.J.1    Oldman, O.2
  • 3
    • 0030543639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Optimal distribution and the family
    • Among the very numerous more recent treatments of the subject are Louis Kaplow, "Optimal Distribution and the Family," Scandinavian Journal of Economics 98, no. 1 (1996): 75-92;
    • (1996) Scandinavian Journal of Economics , vol.98 , Issue.1 , pp. 75-92
    • Kaplow, L.1
  • 4
    • 0004084246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Edward J. McCaffery, Taxing Women (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996); and
    • (1996) Taxing Women
    • McCaffery, E.J.1
  • 5
    • 33745663134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doing something about marriage penalties: A guide for the perplexed
    • Lawrence Zelenak, "Doing Something about Marriage Penalties: A Guide for the Perplexed," Tax Law Review 54 (2000): 1-76
    • (2000) Tax Law Review , vol.54 , pp. 1-76
    • Zelenak, L.1
  • 6
    • 85055760449 scopus 로고
    • Sexism in the code: A comparative study of working wive and mothers
    • See, e.g., Grace Ganz Blumberg, "Sexism in the Code: A Comparative Study of Working Wive and Mothers," Buffalo Law Review 21 (1980): 49-98;
    • (1980) Buffalo Law Review , vol.21 , pp. 49-98
    • Blumberg, G.G.1
  • 7
    • 21344496167 scopus 로고
    • Love, money, and the IRS: Family, income-sharing, and the joint income tax return
    • Marjorie E. Komhauser, "Love, Money, and the IRS: Family, Income-Sharing, and the Joint Income Tax Return," Hastings Law Journal 45 (1993): 63-111;
    • (1993) Hastings Law Journal , vol.45 , pp. 63-111
    • Komhauser, M.E.1
  • 8
    • 0345880359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taxing housework
    • Nancy C. Staudt, "Taxing Housework," Georgetown Law Journal 84 (1996): 1571-1647;
    • (1996) Georgetown Law Journal , vol.84 , pp. 1571-1647
    • Staudt, N.C.1
  • 11
    • 0005481634 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Henry Simons, Personal Income Taxation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1938), 50. The adoption of an income tax in various Western European countries in the late nineteenth century, and in the United States in 1913, prompted extensive scholarly discussion of what "income" (typically assumed to be a desirable tax base on poorly specified grounds relating to the "ability to pay" concept) really meant. Simons championed the term's generalization to cover the market value of all consumption and changes in net worth, even in the absence of an observed market transaction such as a sale of appreciated property. The Haig-Simons income ideal held a dominant position in U.S. legal tax scholarship from at least the 1950s through the 1980s, although more recently it has increasingly been challenged by support for consumption taxation.
    • (1938) Personal Income Taxation , pp. 50
    • Simons, H.1
  • 14
    • 51449124550 scopus 로고
    • A 'Comprehensive tax base' as a goal of income tax reform
    • Boris I. Bittker, "A 'Comprehensive Tax Base' as a Goal of Income Tax Reform," Harvard law Review 80 (1967): 974.
    • (1967) Harvard Law Review , vol.80 , pp. 974
    • Bittker, B.I.1
  • 16
    • 0004084246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., McCaffery, Taxing Women. I have also examined these issues in earlier work.
    • Taxing Women
    • McCaffery1
  • 18
    • 33745636201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • and Daniel N. Shaviro, Who Should Pay for Medicare? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004), 69-71, 128-30, and 134-35.
    • (2004) Who Should Pay for Medicare? , pp. 69-71
    • Shaviro, D.N.1
  • 20
    • 33745666324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Families, tax treatment of
    • Joseph Cordes et al., Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press
    • Kaplow, "Families, Tax Treatment of," in Joseph Cordes et al., Encyclopedia of Taxation and Tax Policy (Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press, 1999);
    • (1999) Encyclopedia of Taxation and Tax Policy
    • Kaplow1
  • 21
    • 33745661739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taxation
    • A. Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell, eds., (forthcoming)
    • and Louis Kaplow, "Taxation," in A. Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell, eds., Handbook of Law and Economics (forthcoming).
    • Handbook of Law and Economics
    • Kaplow, L.1
  • 22
    • 84861616009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • But see Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell, fairness Versus Welfare (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), arguing for welfarism.
    • (2002) Fairness Versus Welfare
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 23
    • 33745668049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The form of utilitarianism that I apply is hedonic rather than preference-based, and thus permits overriding people's observed preferences if we have sufficient grounds for believing that they are making mistakes from the standpoint of their own welfare. (Their preferences would, however, typically serve as powerful empirical evidence regarding what best serves their welfare.) In addition, I assume a utilitarian aim of maximizing total rather than average welfare. I concede that there are grave difficulties with the view that people's mental states can generally (even assuming full information) be given cardinal or even ordinal welfare rankings, reflecting the diversity of our psychological sensations and experiences.
  • 25
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press
    • See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971).
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 26
    • 0001698009 scopus 로고
    • Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risktaking
    • John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of RiskTaking," Journal of Political Economy 61 (1953): 434.
    • (1953) Journal of Political Economy , vol.61 , pp. 434
    • Harsanyi, J.1
  • 27
    • 33745652381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, positing a veil of ignorance is an extra step relative to simply valuing everyone's welfare equally in the world we actually observe, a step requiring justification and potentially raising such questions about its "thickness" as what degree of risk aversion people should be deemed to have if they do not know who they are. From a utilitarian standpoint, however, the veil of ignorance is merely a way of expressing morally required indifference between oneself and other people. Treating 14 oneself as equally likely to be A or B is a way of treating A's and B's welfare as equally important, rather than importing selfish bias if one knows that in fact one is A. See Journal of Political Economy, ibid., 453;
    • Journal of Political Economy , pp. 453
  • 29
    • 33745637551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I discuss later with respect to having children, a social insurance rationale potentially applies even to risks within one's control, but this may greatly raise the stakes regarding moral hazard issues.
  • 31
    • 33745649444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A transfer system such as Medicaid further reflects a view that medical needs are distributionally important independent of income.
  • 32
    • 33745676871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • More precisely, this reason for giving the money to A would apply without regard to the parties' relative well-being levels. This is not to deny that one's overall distributional decision might reflect both this reason for giving money to A and information about the parties' relative well-being levels.
  • 33
    • 33745654622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This example ignores the possibility of inducing people with higher life expectancies to work longer or save a larger proportion of their lifetime earnings for retirement. It also does not take account of moral hazard, which could take the form of under-saving given one's above-average life expectancy because one knows that the retirement system will make up the difference.
  • 34
    • 33745661292 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • Robert Nozick, Anarch/, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 41. This objection will not arise here, as I will be emphasizing differences in people's preferences and circumstances that do not raise issues of differing intensity as to their overall sets of preferences. The second common criticism pertains to expensive tastes, or the concern, first raised by Kenneth Arrow, and developed most notably by Ronald Dworkin, that it is unfair to favor individuals by reason of their having freely chosen tastes that are unusually expensive to satisfy.
    • (1974) Anarch/, State, and Utopia , pp. 41
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 35
    • 0000083090 scopus 로고
    • Some ordinalist-utilitarian notes on Rawls's theory of justice
    • See Kenneth J. Arrow, "Some Ordinalist-Utilitarian Notes on Rawls's Theory of Justice," Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 245;
    • (1973) Journal of Philosophy , vol.70 , pp. 245
    • Arrow, K.J.1
  • 36
    • 0000791830 scopus 로고
    • What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources
    • Ronald Dworkin, "What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources," Philosophy and Public Affairs 10, no. 3 (1981): 283. Anne Alstott, writing about households with children from the standpoint of liberal egalitarianism, treats this as an objection that needs to be met on nonutilitarian grounds that relate to parents' responsibility for their choices and to effects on children's development.
    • (1981) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.10 , Issue.3 , pp. 283
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 40
    • 0004084246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An example of using household information without joint filing is the federal income tax treatment of minor children, who must file their own returns if they have sufficient income, but may be claimed by their parents as dependents and also may be taxed on certain unearned income at the parents' marginal rate. A proposed example of using household information along with separate filing is McCaffery's proposal that spouses file separate returns but with a "more generous rate schedule, or greater deductions, for the lesserearning spouse." McCaffery, Taxing Women, 277.
    • Taxing Women , pp. 277
    • McCaffery1
  • 41
    • 33745673217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In some past literature, relevant pooling and allocation have been defined more narrowly. For example, Kornhauser, "Love, Money, and the IRS," 97, argues that viewing households as economic units requires "assum[ing] that the family is a monolithic, homogeneous group in which all members share the same tastes and resources, including income, equally.... True pooling presumes equality, if not in contributions to the pool, then at least in free access to the pool."
    • Love, Money, and the IRS , pp. 97
    • Kornhauser1
  • 42
    • 33645116758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Doubleday
    • Given the practice of polygamy at various times and places in world history, and indeed its apparent survival in portions of Utah (see Jon Krakauer, Under the Banner of Heaven: A Story of Violent Faith [New York: Doubleday, 2003]), a more universal definition would have to permit extension of this definition beyond the case of two individuals who form a couple.
    • (2003) Under the Banner of Heaven: A Story of Violent Faith
    • Krakauer, J.1
  • 46
    • 33745660406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Internal Revenue Code section 152, defining dependents for federal income tax purposes relating to the allowance of deductions for personal exemptions, for an example of a rule addressing children's and other relatives' household status.
  • 47
    • 0040443991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press
    • Intrafamily asset transfers for this purpose became sufficiently prominent that Congress in 1996 enacted a new law creating criminal penalties in cases where the transfers were designed to circumvent the Medicaid asset limit. See 42 U.S.C. sections 1396a and 1396p; and Helen Hershkoff and Stephen Loffredo, The Rights of the Poor (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1997), 184.
    • (1997) The Rights of the Poor , pp. 184
    • Hershkoff, H.1    Loffredo, S.2
  • 49
    • 33745656480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the importance of this principle, compare "Federal Income Taxation and the Family", ibid., 1438, describing proposals to abandon it as "nothing less than astonishing," with
    • Federal Income Taxation and the Family , pp. 1438
  • 50
    • 0004084246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCaffery, Taxing Women, 25: "Taxing equalearning couples equally is terribly unfair, because in fact it leads to massive discrimination against women."
    • Taxing Women , pp. 25
    • McCaffery1
  • 52
    • 0347423599 scopus 로고
    • Equity, efficiency, and income tax theory: Do misallocations drive out inequities?
    • As Bittker famously pointed out, marketplace responses to a non-neutral tax rule may eliminate the inequity problem, leaving only inefficiency. See Boris I. Bittker, "Equity, Efficiency, and Income Tax Theory: Do Misallocations Drive Out Inequities?" San Diego Law Review 16 (1979): 735-48.
    • (1979) San Diego Law Review , vol.16 , pp. 735-748
    • Bittker, B.I.1
  • 53
    • 33745643018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A further important issue is the effect of taxation on decisions to marry, involving encouragement of forming a one-earner couple and discouragement of forming a two-earner couple.
  • 54
    • 0000238106 scopus 로고
    • Optimal tax treatment of the family: Married couples
    • See Michael J. Boskin and Eytan Sheshanski, "Optimal Tax Treatment of the Family: Married Couples," Journal of Public Economics 20 (1983): 281-97;
    • (1983) Journal of Public Economics , vol.20 , pp. 281-297
    • Boskin, M.J.1    Sheshanski, E.2
  • 55
    • 0039342140 scopus 로고
    • Social security and the american family
    • Lawrence H. Summers, ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • and Michael J. Boskin and Douglas J. Puffert, "Social Security and the American Family," in Lawrence H. Summers, ed., Tax Policy and the Economy, Vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987).
    • (1987) Tax Policy and the Economy , vol.1
    • Boskin, M.J.1    Puffert, D.J.2
  • 56
    • 0004084246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McCaffery, Taxing Women, 179-82, and sources cited therein. This is especially true for couples with children, because nonmarket work in the home is such an important form of household economic production.
    • Taxing Women , pp. 179-182
    • McCaffery1
  • 57
    • 33745649289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Taxing Women, ibid., 170-75. "Compensated elasticity" refers to that which is measured holding income constant, so as to focus on substitution effects, or responses to incentives at the margin, as opposed to people's changing preferences as income changes.
    • Taxing Women , pp. 170-175
  • 58
    • 33745652780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Internal Revenue Code section 21 provides a fairly limited childcare credit for twoearner married couples and heads of households with children, which I ignore in the text for ease of exposition.
  • 61
    • 0000778367 scopus 로고
    • A pure theory of local expenditures
    • See Charles M. Tiebout, "A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures," Journal of Political Economy 64 (1956): 416.
    • (1956) Journal of Political Economy , vol.64 , pp. 416
    • Tiebout, C.M.1
  • 62
    • 17444379698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can the progressivity of tax changes be measured in isolation?
    • See C. Eugene Steuerle, "Can the Progressivity of Tax Changes Be Measured in Isolation?" Tax Notes 100 (2003): 1187-88. As Steuerle notes, however, higher-income households get greater college education subsidies than lower-income households.
    • (2003) Tax Notes , vol.100 , pp. 1187-1188
    • Eugene Steuerle, C.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.