메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 35, Issue 3, 2004, Pages 341-369

In defense of pragmatic contextualism: Wittgenstein and Dewey on meaning and agreement

(1)  Medina, Jose a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33646550905     PISSN: 0031806X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9191.2004.00177.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (21)

References (45)
  • 3
  • 5
    • 0003023231 scopus 로고
    • Objectivity, Value Judgement, and Theory Choice
    • Chicago: U of Chicago P
    • Objectivity, Value Judgement, and Theory Choice. The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Scientific Change, ed. Thomas Kuhn (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1977) 320-39.) have emphasized, there are also non-epistemic factors that contribute to narrow down the set of hypotheses that are considered reasonable or plausible in science at any particular time given the socio-historical conditions that affect the development of the discipline in question. It is important to note that the issue of plausibility and rational acceptability goes beyond epistemic warrant
    • (1977) The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Scientific Change , pp. 320-339
    • Kuhn, T.1
  • 7
    • 0002955924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. J. Dewey, (Carbondale: Southern Illinois U of P, 1998) as PI and EN, respectively. All other references are given by year of publication
    • and to Dewey's Experience and Nature, The Latter Works, 1925-1953, Vol 1: 1925. ed. J. Dewey, (Carbondale: Southern Illinois U of P, 1998) as PI and EN, respectively. All other references are given by year of publication
    • Experience and Nature, The Latter Works, 1925-1953 , vol.1 , pp. 1925
    • Dewey1
  • 11
    • 33746572822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wittgenstein and Nonsense: Psychologism, Kantianism, and the Habitus
    • See Jose Medina, Wittgenstein and Nonsense: Psychologism, Kantianism, and the Habitus, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, (11) 2003a, 293-318
    • (2003) International Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.11 , pp. 293-318
    • Medina, J.1
  • 12
    • 60949247936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On being "other-Minded": Wittgenstein, Davidson, and Logical Aliens
    • and Jose Medina, On being "Other-Minded": Wittgenstein, Davidson, and Logical Aliens, International Philosophical Quarterly (43) 2003b, 463-75
    • (2003) International Philosophical Quarterly , vol.43 , pp. 463-475
    • Medina, J.1
  • 13
    • 0003891615 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: U of Chicago P, Of course, this convergence is no accident but the result of the long interaction between Dewey and Mead at the University of Michigan and the University of Chicago
    • Mead, Mind, Self, and Society, (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1934), Of course, this convergence is no accident but the result of the long interaction between Dewey and Mead at the University of Michigan and the University of Chicago
    • (1934) Mind, Self, and Society
    • Mead1
  • 16
    • 1342324248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Albany NY: SUNY Press and Medina, Wittgenstein and Nonesense
    • I have offered a critique of this interpretation in Jose Medina, The Unity of Wittgenstein's Philosophy, (Albany NY: SUNY Press, 2002) and Medina, Wittgenstein and Nonesense
    • (2002) The Unity of Wittgenstein's Philosophy
    • Medina, J.1
  • 17
    • 0009153821 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT P and The New Wittgenstein 2002 eds, and, London and New York: Routledge
    • See Diamond, The Realistic Spirit. Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and The Mind, (Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 1988) and The New Wittgenstein, eds. Crary and Read, (London and New York: Routledge 2002)
    • (1988) The Realistic Spirit. Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and The Mind
    • Diamond1
  • 19
    • 79954777980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sleeper correctly points out that for Dewey, pace Peirce. "the 'interpretant' of a 'sign' is not just another 'sign' " (2001, p. 138). However, here too I want to take exception to one part of Sleeper's analysis of the contrast between Dewey and Peirce. He contends that "what Dewey is arguing is that we get our semiotic from our semantics, not our semantics from our semiotic" (p. 139). But this is (at best) misleading because the most fundamental level of Dewey's view of language is pragmatics, not semantics. Although Sleeper recognizes that social action is at the core of Dewey's account of language and communication, his realist interpretation gives a conceptual priority to semantics that it should not have
    • (2001) Interpretant' of a 'sign' is not just another 'sign' , pp. 138
  • 20
    • 0003943906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP
    • There are also unlearned elements that constitute preconditions for the participation in linguistic activities. The very possibility of training requires certain unlearned spontaneous reactions on the part of the trainee, which support the learning process. In this respect, Wittgenstein calls our attention to the "natural reactions" that are prerequisite for the pupil being trainable in the practice (cf. Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958b), pp. 89-90, p. 93, and p. 105). In a similar vein, in the passage quoted above, Dewey talks about innate reactions to the movement of the pointing gesture as the requisite starting-point of the learning process. (It must be pointed out, however, that whether these reactions are in fact innate has been called into question by recent research in developmental psychology. See, for instance, Tomasello, The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1999).)
    • (1999) The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition
    • Tomasello1
  • 21
    • 0002434186 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP It is also present in Mead's account of pointing 1934, chapter 2, which is very similar to Dewey's
    • This account of intersubjective mediation through language has been made popular by Davidson's idea of triangulation (Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001) 2001, pp. 86-88, pp. 117-21, and pp. 128-9). This idea of triangulation was already present in Vygotsky's genetic account of linguistic competence: "The path from object to child and from child to object passes through another person" Vygotsky, Mind in Society, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1978) 30. It is also present in Mead's account of pointing (1934, chapter 2), which is very similar to Dewey's
    • (1978) Mind in Society , pp. 30
    • Vygotsky1
  • 22
    • 1342303023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Predication
    • Joseph Margolis, The Politics of Predication, Philosophical Forum (27) 1996, 195-219
    • (1996) Philosophical Forum , vol.27 , pp. 195-219
    • Margolis, J.1
  • 23
    • 1342324242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • University Park: Pennsylvania State UP
    • What, After All, Is a Work of Art? (University Park: Pennsylvania State UP, 1999)
    • (1999) What, After All, Is a Work of Art
  • 30
    • 84998014148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Identity Trouble: Disidentification and the Problem of Difference
    • Jose Medina, Identity Trouble: Disidentification and the Problem of Difference, Philosophy and Social Criticism. (29): 2003c, 657-82
    • (2003) Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol.29 , pp. 657-682
    • Medina, J.1
  • 32
    • 79954792342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We can find such an explanation in the material-inferentialist account recently developed and defended by Brandom, Making it Explicit (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1994). As I have argued elsewhere, Wittgenstein also offers an account of the special semantic stability of certain terms in his discussions of logic, mathematics, and "grammar." See Medina, The Unity and Medina, Wittgenstein and Nonsense
    • The Unity and Medina, Wittgenstein and Nonsense
    • Medina1
  • 33
    • 0001288391 scopus 로고
    • It would be a mistake to assimilate Dewey's distinction to the popular distinction in philosophy of language between speaker's meaning and semantic meaning. See Strawson On Referring, Mind, 1950, 320-14
    • (1950) On Referring, Mind , pp. 320-414
    • Strawson1
  • 34
    • 79954752613 scopus 로고
    • Donnellan Reference and Definite Descrptions
    • Donnellan Reference and Definite Descrptions, Philosophical Review, 1966, 281-304
    • (1966) Philosophical Review , pp. 281-304
  • 35
    • 79954867114 scopus 로고
    • Putnam Meaning and Reference
    • and Searle Expression and Meaning Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts, (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1985)
    • Putnam Meaning and Reference, Journal of Philosophy, 1973, 699-711, and Searle Expression and Meaning Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts, (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1985). Although there may be some surface similarities between this distinction and Dewey's, there are crucial differences. One of these differences is that, for Dewey, both proximate and ultimate meanings are social through and through, whereas in the traditional distinction, there is a divide between social (semantic) meanings and individualistic (speaker's) meanings
    • (1973) Journal of Philosophy , pp. 699-711
  • 36
  • 38
    • 79954658989 scopus 로고
    • Logic: A Theory of Inquiry and Wittgenstein's
    • esp, Oxford: Blackwell
    • See esp. Dewey's Logic: A Theory of Inquiry and Wittgenstein's Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1978)
    • (1978) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics
    • Dewey1
  • 39
    • 84953743021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This convergence between Dewey's and Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics is recognized by Sleeper, He points out that both Dewey and Wittgenstein view action as fundamental for the study of the logical foundations of mathematics, which should provide an account of the emergence of mathematical systems from ordinary practices and activities such as counting and measuring. See esp. Sleeper The Necessity, pp. 156-7
    • The Necessity , pp. 156-167
    • Sleeper1
  • 40
    • 1342289534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anthropologism, Naturalism, and the Pragmatic Study of Language
    • Drawing on conversation analysis, I have also developed an argument to this effect in Jose Medina, Anthropologism, Naturalism, and the Pragmatic Study of Language, Journal of Pragmatics (36): 2004, 549-73
    • (2004) Journal of Pragmatics , Issue.36 , pp. 549-573
    • Medina, J.1
  • 41
    • 79954822170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the full elaboration of this point and the development of my notion of contextual determinacy through conversation analysis, see Medina, Anthropologism
    • Anthropologism
    • Medina1
  • 42
    • 0003665678 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA
    • Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1982) community view of meaning and rule following seems to come close to this semantic view
    • (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language
    • Kripke1
  • 43
    • 0040737302 scopus 로고
    • The Individual Strikes Back
    • and it has been read in this way by many. For instance, in his critique of Kripke, Blackburn attributes this kind of social conventionalism to him, in The Individual Strikes Back, Synthese, (58); 1984, 281-301
    • (1984) Synthese , Issue.58 , pp. 281-301
  • 44
  • 45
    • 79954949994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Unity of Wittgenstein's Philosophy as well as
    • 6.1 of, and On Being Other minded
    • See 6.1 of Medina, The Unity of Wittgenstein's Philosophy as well as Wittgenstein and Nonsense and On Being Other minded
    • Wittgenstein and Nonsense
    • Medina1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.