-
1
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, ig71), p. 7.
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 7
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
2
-
-
84937266898
-
Where the action is: On the site of distributive justice
-
G. A. Cohen, "Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice," Philosophy & Public Affuirs 26 (1997): 3-30;
-
(1997)
Philosophy & Public Affuirs
, vol.26
, pp. 3-30
-
-
Cohen, G.A.1
-
3
-
-
0011478290
-
Institutions and the demands of justice
-
Liam Murphy, "Institutions and the Demands of Justice," Philosophy 6 Public Afairs, 27 (1998): 251-91.
-
(1998)
Philosophy & Public Afairs
, vol.27
, pp. 251-291
-
-
Murphy, L.1
-
4
-
-
33747064435
-
On the site of distributive justice: Reflections on cohen and murphy
-
One defense from which I learned is
-
One defense from which I learned is Thomas Pogge, "On the Site of Distributive Justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy," Philosophy C Public Affuirs 29 (2000): 137-69;
-
(2000)
Philosophy & Public Affuirs
, vol.29
, pp. 137-169
-
-
Pogge, T.1
-
5
-
-
0004248343
-
-
I am also indebted to Pogge's earlier development of a Rawlsian basic structure view in his (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,)
-
I am also indebted to Pogge's earlier development of a Rawlsian basic structure view in his Realizing Rawls (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 15-47.
-
(1989)
Realizing Rawls
, pp. 15-47
-
-
-
6
-
-
1042287753
-
Equality or priority?
-
The opposition between deontological and teleological or consequentialist ethical views does not offer a notably stable or informative map of many of the disagreements that are routinely referred to it. So I should mention that it will not really do any work in my arguments. I will argue for a version of the view that parties to social interaction treat one another unfairly unless they aim for equality, and that fair treatment in interaction is their reason to aim for equality. Some people think that people should aim for equality only because it is a better outcome ( ed. Matthew Clayton and Andrew Williams [Hampshire: St. Martins Press])
-
The opposition between deontological and teleological or consequentialist ethical views does not offer a notably stable or informative map of many of the disagreements that are routinely referred to it. So I should mention that it will not really do any work in my arguments. I will argue for a version of the view that parties to social interaction treat one another unfairly unless they aim for equality, and that fair treatment in interaction is their reason to aim for equality. Some people think that people should aim for equality only because it is a better outcome (cf. Derek Parfit, "Equality or Priority?" in The Ideal of Equality, ed. Matthew Clayton and Andrew Williams [Hampshire: St. Martins Press, 20001).
-
(2000)
The Ideal of Equality
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
7
-
-
78751651938
-
-
If you think that these two views are incompatible, and that it is helpful to mark their opposition with the labels of "deontology" and "teleology," that's great. But don't worry if you disagree. (You might disagree, for example, if you define teleological views as holding that you can represent right action as maximizing some real-valued function of humanly alterable variables, and if you think that interactive fairness is a possible argument of such a function.) I am using "deontology" as a convenient conventional label for the view that I defend, and I will not directly pit that view against the claim that equality is to be sought because it is a better outcome.
-
If you think that these two views are incompatible, and that it is helpful to mark their opposition with the labels of "deontology" and "teleology," that's great. But don't worry if you disagree. (You might disagree, for example, if you define teleological views as holding that you can represent right action as maximizing some real-valued function of humanly alterable variables, and if you think that interactive fairness is a possible argument of such a function.) I am using "deontology" as a convenient conventional label for the view that I defend, and I will not directly pit that view against the claim that equality is to be sought because it is a better outcome.
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
78751676803
-
-
this respect I echo arguments of
-
In this respect I echo arguments of Pogge, Realizing, pp. 20-28
-
Realizing
, pp. 20-28
-
-
Pogge1
-
10
-
-
78751677226
-
-
I will discuss distributive justice in the distribution of unspecified goods, without prejudice among alternative ways of filling in that blank. The distributive principle that I defend, a version of Rawls's difference principle, is egalitarian and not prioritarian in the following sense of that distinction: Egalitarian judgments of the justness of distributions make ineliminable reference to the relative positions of pairs of people; prioritarian views do not. (If these judgments can be represented by comparing the values of functions, prioritarian judgments can be represented by functions that are additively separable in individual good levels, and egalitarian judgments cannot
-
I will discuss distributive justice in the distribution of unspecified goods, without prejudice among alternative ways of filling in that blank. The distributive principle that I defend, a version of Rawls's difference principle, is egalitarian and not prioritarian in the following sense of that distinction: Egalitarian judgments of the justness of distributions make ineliminable reference to the relative positions of pairs of people; prioritarian views do not. (If these judgments can be represented by comparing the values of functions, prioritarian judgments can be represented by functions that are additively separable in individual good levels, and egalitarian judgments cannot;
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0003493317
-
-
[Cambridge, Mass.: Basil Blackwell,].) In undertaking to account for the value of equality, then, I plan to account for such relativity-regarding judgments, but not for the rightness of "levelling down," since I don't think that it is right
-
see John Broome, Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time [Cambridge, Mass.: Basil Blackwell, 1991], pp. 177-84.) In undertaking to account for the value of equality, then, I plan to account for such relativity-regarding judgments, but not for the rightness of "levelling down," since I don't think that it is right.
-
(1991)
Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time
, pp. 177-184
-
-
Broome, J.1
-
12
-
-
78751672180
-
-
The label of dualism is due to
-
The label of dualism is due to Murphy, "Institutions," p. 254.
-
Institutions
, pp. 254
-
-
Murphy1
-
13
-
-
0011366663
-
Incentives, inequality, and community
-
Cohen, "Action"; earlier installments are , ed. Grethe B. Peterson, (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press,)
-
Cohen, "Action"; earlier installments are G. A. Cohen, "Incentives, Inequality, and Community," in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Volume 13, ed. Grethe B. Peterson, (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1992), pp. 263-329
-
(1992)
The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
, vol.13
, pp. 263-329
-
-
Cohen, G.A.1
-
14
-
-
84971851093
-
The pareto argument for inequality
-
G. A. Cohen, "The Pareto Argument for Inequality," Social Philosophy and Poky 12 (1995): 165-85;
-
(1995)
Social Philosophy and Poky
, vol.12
, pp. 165-185
-
-
Cohen, G.A.1
-
15
-
-
0003579435
-
-
later page references for Cohen's "Incentives" are to its reprinting, (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press,)
-
later page references for Cohen's "Incentives" are to its reprinting in Equal Freedom, ed. Stephen Darwall (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1995), pp. 331-97.
-
(1995)
Equal Freedom
, pp. 331-197
-
-
Darwall, S.1
-
16
-
-
78751675484
-
-
These deeply resistible assumptions about the organization of production in a just society are, for Cohen, argumentative concessions to the defenders of wage differentials; in Section IX I briefly consider how the picture changes when we revoke them
-
These deeply resistible assumptions about the organization of production in a just society are, for Cohen, argumentative concessions to the defenders of wage differentials; in Section IX I briefly consider how the picture changes when we revoke them.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
27844521507
-
The basic structure as subject
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, "The Basic Structure as Subject," in Political Liberalism (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993), pp. 268-69;
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
, pp. 268-269
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
18
-
-
0003437941
-
-
New York Oxford University Press, 60-62
-
Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York Oxford University Press, 1991), pp. 53-54, 60-62.
-
(1991)
Equality and Partiality
, pp. 53-54
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
19
-
-
78751668934
-
-
As I have said in Section I, I do not claim to be defending any of Rawlsk views. But I have conceded that externalization is an important Rawlsian commitment, and I have announced that I am abandoning that idea in my own arguments about basic structure. So it might seem that to group my arguments with Rawls in any way is to misappropriate Rawls
-
As I have said in Section I, I do not claim to be defending any of Rawlsk views. But I have conceded that externalization is an important Rawlsian commitment, and I have announced that I am abandoning that idea in my own arguments about basic structure. So it might seem that to group my arguments with Rawls in any way is to misappropriate Rawls;
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
78751673373
-
-
I should explain why I suppose that I am still in the same neighborhood. I believe that Rawls's preoccupation with basic structure reflects not one but at least two distinct moral ideas. One idea is externalization. A second is the thought that social structures constituting societywide distributional mechanisms give rise to a set of sui generis obligations binding on the people who inhabit them, and that justice or a big, self-contained piece of justice consists in the satisfaction of those obligations. I am going to work on the second of these ideas. See Section V for a further attempt to locate the contrast between them
-
I should explain why I suppose that I am still in the same neighborhood. I believe that Rawls's preoccupation with basic structure reflects not one but at least two distinct moral ideas. One idea is externalization. A second is the thought that social structures constituting societywide distributional mechanisms give rise to a set of sui generis obligations binding on the people who inhabit them, and that justice or a big, self-contained piece of justice consists in the satisfaction of those obligations. I am going to work on the second of these ideas. See Section V for a further attempt to locate the contrast between them.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
78751658677
-
-
I am not going to elaborate the ways in which choice and context might justify framing
-
I am not going to elaborate the ways in which choice and context might justify framing;
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
78751665993
-
-
I will argue that both kinds of justification necessarily fail in respect of the socially interdependent framing to which I turn next in the text, so for my purposes it does not matter how these suggestions are fleshed out
-
I will argue that both kinds of justification necessarily fail in respect of the socially interdependent framing to which I turn next in the text, so for my purposes it does not matter how these suggestions are fleshed out.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
0003867020
-
-
Justification under this constraint resembles in one way Thomas Scanlon's contractualist justification of moral principles () [Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,)). Scanlonian people are to look for principles that no one can reject who is herself looking for such principles. The latter proviso on rejection is grounded on the assumption that everyone is interested in finding principles for the general regulation of behavior; the constraint that I am discussing has as its narrower foundation the assumption that everyone must justify using her interaction with others to produce goods for herself
-
Justification under this constraint resembles in one way Thomas Scanlon's contractualist justification of moral principles (What We Owe to Each Other) [Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998)). Scanlonian people are to look for principles that no one can reject who is herself looking for such principles. The latter proviso on rejection is grounded on the assumption that everyone is interested in finding principles for the general regulation of behavior; the constraint that I am discussing has as its narrower foundation the assumption that everyone must justify using her interaction with others to produce goods for herself.
-
(1998)
What We Owe to Each Other
-
-
-
24
-
-
0142201962
-
Equality
-
New York Cambridge University Press
-
Thomas Nagel, "Equality," in his Mortal Questions (New York Cambridge University Press, 1979), p. 23.
-
(1979)
Mortal Questions
, pp. 23
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
25
-
-
78751654860
-
-
This set need not exhaust the physically and social-structurally limited range of possible structures. As I will mention in Section V, we might need to throw out some possible structures because they fail other requirements of justifiable framing
-
This set need not exhaust the physically and social-structurally limited range of possible structures. As I will mention in Section V, we might need to throw out some possible structures because they fail other requirements of justifiable framing.
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
78751673530
-
-
For convenience I cast it in terms of a requirement of equality rather than the maximin defended in N, but the section's arguments are general to a larger class of egalitarian requirements including both
-
For convenience I cast it in terms of a requirement of equality rather than the maximin defended in N, but the section's arguments are general to a larger class of egalitarian requirements including both.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
0013220692
-
Equality
-
compare
-
compare Dennis McKerlie, "Equality," Ethics 106 (1996): 274-296.
-
(1996)
Ethics
, vol.106
, pp. 274-296
-
-
McKerlie, D.1
-
30
-
-
0004223708
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), pp. 1-3.
-
(2000)
Sovereign Virtue
, pp. 1-3
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
32
-
-
84879965572
-
-
Nozick, Anarchy, pp. 185-86.
-
Anarchy
, pp. 185-186
-
-
Nozick1
-
33
-
-
84879965572
-
-
Nozick, Anarchy, pp. 189-97.
-
Anarchy
, pp. 189-197
-
-
Nozick1
-
34
-
-
84936020353
-
-
Berkeley: University of California
-
Brian Barry, Theories of Justice (Berkeley: University of California, 1989), pp. 234-54.
-
(1989)
Theories of Justice
, pp. 234-254
-
-
Barry, B.1
-
36
-
-
0003929738
-
-
Cohen's admission of an individual prerogative in the context of his incentives argument ("Incentives," p. 370) was prompted by criticism from Samuel Scheffler, and follows Scheffler's more general proposals for "an agent-centered prerogative" (New York Oxford University Press, )
-
Cohen's admission of an individual prerogative in the context of his incentives argument ("Incentives," p. 370) was prompted by criticism from Samuel Scheffler, and follows Scheffler's more general proposals for "an agent-centered prerogative" in Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism (New York Oxford University Press, 1982).
-
(1982)
The Rejection of Consequentialism
-
-
Scheffler1
-
38
-
-
0347020447
-
-
(New York, Oxford University Press,),. Murphy offers this observation of complacency in a discussion of beneficence, not justice
-
Liam Murphy, Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory (New York, Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 3-4. Murphy offers this observation of complacency in a discussion of beneficence, not justice.
-
(2000)
Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory
, pp. 3-4
-
-
Murphy, L.1
-
44
-
-
77949408036
-
-
See especially
-
See especially Pogge, "Reflections," pp. 149-52;
-
Reflections
, pp. 149-152
-
-
Pogge1
-
45
-
-
0009184104
-
Incentives, inequality, and publicity
-
Andrew Williams, "Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity," Philosophy & Public Affairs 27 (1998), pp. 225-47.
-
(1998)
Philosophy & Public Affairs
, vol.27
, pp. 225-247
-
-
Williams, A.1
-
46
-
-
78751656758
-
-
A reviewer for this journal points out that this objection does not get started if strict equality is replaced as the distributive ideal by some weaker prioritarian goal. For then the ideal tax structure will preserve some inequality, so that under it there exist strictly worseoff people whose interests give skilled workers reason to work long hours. I suppose that this way out is open to Cohen, but it considerably lowers the stakes in his critique of Rawls
-
A reviewer for this journal points out that this objection does not get started if strict equality is replaced as the distributive ideal by some weaker prioritarian goal. For then the ideal tax structure will preserve some inequality, so that under it there exist strictly worseoff people whose interests give skilled workers reason to work long hours. I suppose that this way out is open to Cohen, but it considerably lowers the stakes in his critique of Rawls.
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
33750151408
-
-
355-72
-
Cohen, "Incentives," pp. 339-47,355-72.
-
Incentives
, pp. 339-347
-
-
Cohen1
-
48
-
-
77949408036
-
-
reaches a similar interpretation of Cohen's proposal and objects to it on grounds related to those given in the next paragraph of the text
-
Pogge ("Reflections," p. 150) reaches a similar interpretation of Cohen's proposal and objects to it on grounds related to those given in the next paragraph of the text.
-
Reflections
, pp. 150
-
-
Pogge1
|