메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 65-89

How to argue for and against sport hunting

(1)  Curnutt, Jordan a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 3142640670     PISSN: 00472786     EISSN: 14679833     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9833.1996.tb00238.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (77)
  • 1
    • 1842500012 scopus 로고
    • Wadsworth chapter 7
    • A useful discussion of the relationships between "action ethics" and "virtue ethics" is found in Louis Pojman, Ethics, Wadsworth, 1990: chapter 7.
    • (1990) Ethics
    • Pojman, L.1
  • 3
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고
    • writes chapter 2
    • J.S. Mill writes in Utilitarianism, 1861, chapter 2: "the motive has nothing to do with the morality of the action, though much with the worth of the agent." Thinking Vere's act to be wrong whatever his motive is ironic for Mill, since the execution of Billy was justified by utilitarian reasons.
    • (1861) Utilitarianism
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 4
    • 84887323398 scopus 로고
    • Bitter harvest
    • John G. Mitchell, "Bitter Harvest," Audubon, 81, no. 3 (1979): 61-65, lists the typical purposes and goals of sport hunts.
    • (1979) Audubon , vol.81 , Issue.3 , pp. 61-65
    • Mitchell, J.G.1
  • 5
    • 84928835693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental ethics and the case for hunting
    • Roger King, "Environmental Ethics and the Case for Hunting," Environmental Ethics, 13 (1991): 59-85,
    • (1991) Environmental Ethics , vol.13 , pp. 59-85
    • King, R.1
  • 6
    • 0003494698 scopus 로고
    • his first published
    • has identified another strand of pro-hunting argument which he calls "The Primitivist Defense." This defense is most closely associated with Jose Ortega Y Gasset and his Meditations on Hunting, (first published 1943),
    • (1943) Meditations on Hunting
    • Gasset, J.O.Y.1
  • 7
    • 0003867910 scopus 로고
    • Scribner's
    • but has found a more recent champion in Paul Shepard's The Tender Carnivore and the Sacred Game, Scribner's, 1973. The Primitivist thesis is that killing is not the point of hunting; only by hunting can man return to his original, unsullied state as predator and escape the influence of modern life which corrupts this primordial condition. King points out that many of Ortega's own examples of hunting have nothing to do with this and much more to do with simply killing animals (pp. 74-75). I can here only express skepticism that an atavistic goal represents any more of a moral defense of hunting than such an appeal would represent a moral defense of defecating wherever and whenever I please.
    • (1973) The Tender Carnivore and the Sacred Game
    • Shepard's, P.1
  • 8
    • 0004288674 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • Although an incomplete hunt - one in which an animal is neither killed nor wounded-would not involve violations of these rights, one might want to argue that it would violate a right not to be deceived. A hunter stalking an animal typically attempts to mislead it about his presence, location, or intentions. Paul Taylor maintains that moral agents are required to avoid deceiving animals in this way, but he does not frame the issue in terms of moral rights (Respect for Nature, Princeton, 1986:179-86). Since we are not concerned with incomplete hunts here, we do not need to discuss this matter further.
    • (1986) Respect for Nature , pp. 179-186
  • 9
    • 0343195309 scopus 로고
    • On the morality of hunting
    • Ann Causey, "On the Morality of Hunting," Environmental Ethics, 11 (1989): 327-43;
    • (1989) Environmental Ethics , vol.11 , pp. 327-343
    • Causey, A.1
  • 10
    • 84929229529 scopus 로고
    • Sport hunting: Moral or immoral?
    • Theodore Vitali, "Sport Hunting: Moral or Immoral?" Environmental Ethics, 12 (1990): 69-82.
    • (1990) Environmental Ethics , vol.12 , pp. 69-82
    • Vitali, T.1
  • 11
    • 0010156571 scopus 로고
    • The joy of killing
    • "The Joy of Killing," Between the Species, (1991): 121-28. Pluhar does not present an argument against hunting in this paper.
    • (1991) Between the Species , pp. 121-128
  • 12
    • 79851499322 scopus 로고
    • Yale University Press
    • For example: Leonard Nelson, A System of Ethics, Yale University Press, 1956;
    • (1956) A System of Ethics
    • Nelson, L.1
  • 13
    • 33751317295 scopus 로고
    • The nature and value of rights
    • Joel Feinberg, "The Nature and Value of Rights," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 4 (1970): 243-57;
    • (1970) The Journal of Value Inquiry , vol.4 , pp. 243-257
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 14
    • 0004808243 scopus 로고
    • The rights of animals and unborn generations
    • William T. Blackstone, ed., University of Georgia
    • "The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations," Philosophy & Environmental Crisis, William T. Blackstone, ed., University of Georgia, 1974: 43-68,
    • (1974) Philosophy & Environmental Crisis , pp. 43-68
  • 15
    • 84887335618 scopus 로고
    • Human duties and animal rights
    • Acropolis Books
    • and "Human Duties and Animal Rights" On the Fifth Day, R. Morris and M. Fox, eds., Acropolis Books, 1978: 45-69;
    • (1978) On the Fifth Day , pp. 45-69
    • Morris, R.1    Fox, M.2
  • 16
    • 69949123565 scopus 로고
    • Do animals have A right to liberty?
    • T., Regan & P. Singer, eds., Prentice Hall
    • James Rachels, "Do Animals Have A Right to Liberty?" Animal Rights and Human Obligations, T., Regan & P. Singer, eds., Prentice Hall, 1976: 205-223;
    • (1976) Animal Rights and Human Obligations , pp. 205-223
    • Rachels, J.1
  • 17
    • 84938049284 scopus 로고
    • The rights of wild things
    • Stephen R.L. Clark, "The Rights of Wild Things," Inquiry, 22 (1979): 171-78;
    • (1979) Inquiry , vol.22 , pp. 171-178
    • Clark, S.R.L.1
  • 18
    • 0010836055 scopus 로고
    • The rights of the nonhuman world
    • R. Elliot and A. Gare, eds., Open University Press
    • Mary Anne Warren, "The Rights of the Nonhuman World," Environmental Philosophy, R. Elliot and A.Gare, eds., Open University Press, 1983: 109-134;
    • (1983) Environmental Philosophy , pp. 109-134
    • Warren, M.A.1
  • 19
    • 84887371679 scopus 로고
    • Moral autonomy, self-determination and animal rights
    • Robert Elliot, "Moral Autonomy, Self-Determination and Animal Rights," The Monist, 70 (1987): 83-97;
    • (1987) The Monist , vol.70 , pp. 83-97
    • Elliot, R.1
  • 20
    • 0004285576 scopus 로고
    • University of California
    • and of course Tom Regan, in many journal articles but especially in The Case for Animal Rights, University of California, 1983.
    • (1983) The Case for Animal Rights
  • 22
    • 0038569791 scopus 로고
    • Moral rights and animals
    • "Moral Rights and Animals," Inquiry 11, (1979): 23-54,
    • (1979) Inquiry , vol.11 , pp. 23-54
  • 27
    • 84938052280 scopus 로고
    • Self-consciousness and the rights of nonhuman animals
    • Richard A. Watson, "Self-Consciousness and the Rights of Nonhuman Animals," Environmental Ethics, 1 (1979): 99-129;
    • (1979) Environmental Ethics , vol.1 , pp. 99-129
    • Watson, R.A.1
  • 31
    • 41549124370 scopus 로고
    • Do animals have rights?
    • Tibor Machan, "Do Animals Have Rights?" Public Affairs Quarterly, 5 (1991): 163-73.
    • (1991) Public Affairs Quarterly , vol.5 , pp. 163-173
    • Machan, T.1
  • 32
    • 0005006734 scopus 로고
    • Rowman & Allanheld
    • And some authors who have written comprehensive treatments of the rights issue seem to leave the question of the identity of rightsholders open. I believe both Carl Wellman, A Theory of Rights, Rowman & Allanheld, 1985,
    • (1985) A Theory of Rights
    • Wellman, C.1
  • 33
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press
    • and Judith Thomson, The Realm of Rights, Harvard University Press, 1990, can be read in this way. There is yet another possible stance here: one could also accept the affective criteria and argue that animals do not qualify as rightsholders on these grounds either. R.G. Frey does so in Interests and Rights, Clarendon, 1980, but he is also an agnostic about rights, for humans or animals (see chapter one). I will have more to say about Frey in the last section of this paper.
    • (1990) The Realm of Rights
    • Thomson, J.1
  • 34
    • 0004259456 scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed., Avon
    • His major statement is Animal Liberation, 2nd ed., Avon, 1990.
    • (1990) Animal Liberation
  • 35
    • 0003560902 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge chapters 3-5
    • See also his Practical Ethics, Cambridge, 1979, chapters 3-5.
    • (1979) Practical Ethics
  • 36
    • 84887325692 scopus 로고
    • Hunter-inflicted wounding in white-tailed deer
    • The best evidence for the incidence of pain and suffering is found in the many studies which have been conducted on hunting-caused animal crippling. A few examples: a four-year study in Iowa revealed that 27% of white-tailed deer taken by hunters were not killed outright but were mortally wounded, their bodies retrieved later; see F.A. Stormer, et al., "Hunter-Inflicted Wounding in White-Tailed Deer," Wildlife Society Bulletin 7, (1979): 11-13.
    • (1979) Wildlife Society Bulletin , vol.7 , pp. 11-13
    • Stormer, F.A.1
  • 37
    • 0345221066 scopus 로고
    • Recuperation from crippling in ducks
    • Over a three-year period, research on duck hunting in Minnesota showed a 15% crippling rate; see R.E. Kirby, et al., "Recuperation from Crippling in Ducks," Wildlife Society Bulletin 9, (1981): 151-52.
    • (1981) Wildlife Society Bulletin , vol.9 , pp. 151-152
    • Kirby, R.E.1
  • 38
    • 0000706559 scopus 로고
    • A preliminary evaluation of cripple losses in waterfowl
    • An early study of hunter wounding showed a 24% crippling rate in mallards; see F.C. Bellrose, "A Preliminary Evaluation of Cripple Losses in Waterfowl," Transactions of the North American Wildlife Conference, 18 (1953): 358-59.
    • (1953) Transactions of the North American Wildlife Conference , vol.18 , pp. 358-359
    • Bellrose, F.C.1
  • 40
    • 0003703584 scopus 로고
    • U.S. Department of the Interior, U.S. Fish and Wildlife Service
    • See National Survey of Fishing, Hunting, and Wildlife Associated Recreation, U.S. Department of the Interior, U.S. Fish and Wildlife Service, 1991. For example, in 1991 Minnesota hunters produced $290 million in direct expenditures; this includes licensing fees, equipment, and trip-related expenses such as food, gas, and lodging (pp. 8-9).
    • (1991) National Survey of Fishing, Hunting, and Wildlife Associated Recreation
  • 41
    • 6244272512 scopus 로고
    • The morality of hunting
    • makes this point
    • Robert Loftin makes this point in "The Morality of Hunting," Environmental Ethics, 6 (1984): 244-45.
    • (1984) Environmental Ethics , vol.6 , pp. 244-245
    • Loftin, R.1
  • 42
    • 80053727326 scopus 로고
    • University of Arizona Press
    • For one poignant example, see David Brown, The Wolf in the Southwest, University of Arizona Press, 1984.
    • (1984) The Wolf in the Southwest
    • Brown, D.1
  • 45
    • 3142640669 scopus 로고
    • Animal liberationism, ecocentrism, and the morality of sport hunting
    • Loftin's defense is also not touched by the criticism of Maurice Wade in "Animal Liberationism, Ecocentrism, and the Morality of Sport Hunting," Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 17 (1990): 15-27. Wade thinks the major problem is that utilitarianism could justify huntinghumans (p. 18). Loftin's argument (see below) could not have this consequence. Curiously, although both King and Wade cite Loftin's paper, neither ever mentions this argument.
    • (1990) Journal of the Philosophy of Sport , vol.17 , pp. 15-27
    • Wade, M.1
  • 46
    • 84947816183 scopus 로고
    • Killing humans and killing animals
    • Singer, "Killing Humans and Killing Animals," Inquiry, 22 (1979): 151-52.
    • (1979) Inquiry , vol.22 , pp. 151-152
  • 47
    • 84887391106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 19
    • "Killing Humans and Killing Animals": 156, note 19, though Singer is willing "to give the chicken the benefit of the doubt."
    • Killing Humans and Killing Animals , pp. 156
  • 49
    • 0004234207 scopus 로고
    • Temple University Press
    • See Environmental Ethics, Temple University Press, 1988: 88-93.
    • (1988) Environmental Ethics , pp. 88-93
  • 50
    • 0004246047 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • See Round River, Oxford University Press, 1953,
    • (1953) Round River
  • 51
    • 0004134903 scopus 로고
    • The University of Wisconsin Press
    • for firsthand accounts of some of Leopold's hunts, and the numerous entries for Leopold as hunter in Curt Meine, Aldo Leopold, His Life and Work, The University of Wisconsin Press, 1988.
    • (1988) Aldo Leopold, his Life and Work
    • Meine, C.1
  • 52
    • 84887370376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The University of Wisconsin Press, 1986 (first published 1933)
    • The University of Wisconsin Press, 1986 (first published 1933).
  • 53
  • 54
    • 84887361542 scopus 로고
    • Joint Legislative Budget Committee
    • There is some reason for skepticism about these monetary benefits. During fiscal 1993, the budget of the Arizona Game and Fish Department was about $16.5 million but only $500,000 (3%) was spent on the acquisition of waterfowl habitat. And that money came from a Capital Outlay Bill from the State Legislature: taxpayers in general, not hunters in particular. See State of Arizona Appropriations Report, Joint Legislative Budget Committee, 1994: 462-63. Although some have argued that hunting is ecologically destructive, the evidence suggests otherwise (see below).
    • (1994) State of Arizona Appropriations Report , pp. 462-463
  • 56
    • 33751505350 scopus 로고
    • Brazil's imperiled rain forest
    • For a specific case of the environmentally devastating effects of human population spillover, apropos, to my Afrikaaner hunters argument, see Paul Ehrlich, "Brazil's Imperiled Rain Forest," National Geographic, 174 (1988): 772-817.
    • (1988) National Geographic , vol.174 , pp. 772-817
    • Ehrlich, P.1
  • 57
    • 0004170579 scopus 로고
    • Simon & Schuster
    • For a full-blown treatment of the problem, see his (with 'Ann Ehrlich) The Population Explosion, Simon & Schuster, 1991.
    • (1991) The Population Explosion
    • Ehrlich, A.1
  • 58
    • 0003562160 scopus 로고
    • State University of New York Press
    • In Defense of the Land Ethic, State University of New York Press, 1989: 93.
    • (1989) Defense of the Land Ethic , pp. 93
  • 59
    • 84887350859 scopus 로고
    • The North kaibab deer herd
    • Arizona Fish and Game Department
    • Callicott: 21. The reference to a single deer is ecologically naive; the killing of just one deer would have no effect whatever on an ecosystem degraded by overpopulation. More likely some dozens or even hundreds would have to be killed. The infamous case of a population irruption on the Kaibab Plateau of northern Arizona in the 1920s saw thousands of deer destroyed before the ecosystem was restabilized. For details, see John Russo, The North Kaibab Deer Herd, Wildlife Bulletin 7 (1967), Arizona Fish and Game Department.
    • (1967) Wildlife Bulletin , vol.7
    • Russo, J.1
  • 60
    • 0003675303 scopus 로고
    • Callicott: 52-57. The concept of a mixed community is borrowed from University of Georgia Press chapter 10
    • Callicott: 52-57. The concept of a mixed community is borrowed from Mary Midgley, Animals and Why They Matter, University of Georgia Press, 1983: chapter 10.
    • (1983) Animals and Why They Matter
    • Midgley, M.1
  • 61
    • 84887391100 scopus 로고
    • Book III section 1
    • A Treatise of Human Nature, 1739, Book III, part iii, section 1.
    • (1739) A Treatise of Human Nature , Issue.PART III
  • 63
    • 1842380460 scopus 로고
    • On a case for animal rights
    • both 31-49
    • and Jan Narveson, "On a Case for Animal Rights," both in The Monist, 70 (1987): 15-30, 31-49;
    • (1987) The Monist , vol.70 , pp. 15-30
    • Narveson, J.1
  • 64
    • 84979434949 scopus 로고
    • The case against animal rights
    • David Ost, "The Case Against Animal Rights," The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24 (1986): 365-73;
    • (1986) The Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.24 , pp. 365-373
    • Ost, D.1
  • 65
    • 84887344022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review of tom regan, the case for animal rights
    • repr.
    • and J. Baird Callicott, "Review of Tom Regan, The Case For Animal Rights,", repr. in In Defense of the Land Ethic:, 39-47.
    • Defense of the Land Ethic , pp. 39-47
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 66
    • 84887339315 scopus 로고
    • Ecology, morality, and hunting
    • Humana Press
    • "Ecology, Morality, and Hunting," Ethics and Animals, H.B. Miller and W. Williams, eds., Humana Press, 1983:183-97.
    • (1983) Ethics and Animals , pp. 183-197
    • Miller, H.B.1    Williams, W.2
  • 67
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • Harm to Others, Oxford University Press, 1984: 33.
    • (1984) Harm to Others , pp. 33
  • 68
    • 0004426394 scopus 로고
    • Clarendon
    • Interests and Rights, Clarendon, 1980: 72. Actually, Frey holds that desiring x requires that "I believe that I am deficient in respect of" x. There is reason to think that this is inaccurate. There seems to be nothing wrong with saying that a man can desire his wife, patience, health, and friendship while at the same time having all of these. To get around this problem, and maintain Frey's point, I have amended the belief statement to a weaker claim, leaving it open what exactly A believes about x.
    • (1980) Interests and Rights , pp. 72
  • 69
    • 0004808243 scopus 로고
    • The rights of animals and unborn generations
    • makes W.T. Blackstone, ed., University of Georgia Press
    • The view is taken from a remark Joel Feinberg makes in "The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations," Philosophy & Environmental Crisis, W.T. Blackstone, ed., University of Georgia Press, 1974: 52. There, Feinberg (not known as a philosopher of mind) simply asserts that desires "presuppose something like belief, or cognitive awareness" (emphasis altered).
    • (1974) Philosophy & Environmental Crisis , pp. 52
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 70
    • 84887335205 scopus 로고
    • Precedent Publishing editor Joel Marks comments
    • In his "Introduction" to The Ways of Desire, Precedent Publishing, 1986, editor Joel Marks comments (p. 13) that although the relationship between desire and belief "has long been sensed⋯it has seldom been the subject of scrutiny in its own right."
    • (1986) The Ways of Desire , pp. 13
  • 71
    • 0004091673 scopus 로고
    • MIT Press
    • For example, Robert Stalnaker, Inquiry, MIT Press, 1984:15.
    • (1984) Inquiry , pp. 15
    • Stalnaker, R.1
  • 72
    • 85079714597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defining desire
    • Dennis Stampe, "Defining Desire," The Ways of Desire", 149-73. Nor is there any mention here of a linguistic requirement.
    • The Ways of Desire , pp. 149-173
    • Stampe, D.1
  • 73
    • 84938052677 scopus 로고
    • Do animals have beliefs?
    • Do Animals Have Beliefs?" Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 57 (1979): 15-28.
    • (1979) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.57 , pp. 15-28
  • 74
    • 84887395404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sketched on
    • Stich's "belief-desire psychological theory" (sketched on pp. 15-17) suggests a close connection between the two. Stich himself does not draw any moral consequences in this article.
    • Belief-desire Psychological Theory , pp. 15-17
  • 75
  • 76
    • 84887372234 scopus 로고
    • SDeath, misfortune, and species inequality
    • SDeath, Misfortune, and Species Inequality," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10 (1980): 57-58. The concept of a "categorical desire" is adopted from Bernard Williams. I am taking "misfortune" and "harm" as synonymous, though Cigman herself never equates the two.
    • (1980) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.10 , pp. 57-58
  • 77
    • 0004140706 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Thomas Nagel's definitive statement of the problem, along with his solution, is found in Mortal Questions, Cambridge, 1979: 1-10.
    • (1979) Mortal Questions , pp. 1-10


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.