메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 2, 2004, Pages 171-188

Teleofunctions and oncomice: The case for revising varner's value theory

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 3142533335     PISSN: 01634275     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/enviroethics200426228     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (4)

References (57)
  • 2
    • 0003622275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Notably recently in Philippa Foot, Natural Goodness (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Natural Goodness
    • Foot, P.1
  • 3
    • 84979330809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Biological Functions and Biological Interests
    • Gary Varner, "Biological Functions and Biological Interests," Southern Journal of Philosophy 281, no. 2 (1990): 251-70; In Nature's Interest?: Interests, Animal Rights, and Environmental Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998).
    • (1990) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.281 , Issue.2 , pp. 251-270
    • Varner, G.1
  • 4
    • 84979330809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Gary Varner, "Biological Functions and Biological Interests," Southern Journal of Philosophy 281, no. 2 (1990): 251-70; In Nature's Interest?: Interests, Animal Rights, and Environmental Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Nature's Interest?: Interests, Animal Rights, and Environmental Ethics
  • 5
    • 3142636646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review of in Nature's Interests?
    • Alan Carter, "Review of In Nature's Interests?" Mind 109, no. 435 (2000): 657-60.
    • (2000) Mind , vol.109 , Issue.435 , pp. 657-660
    • Carter, A.1
  • 6
    • 3142536605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review of in Nature's Interests?
    • Mark Rowlands, "Review of In Nature's Interests?" Philosophical Review 109, no. 4 (2000): 598-601. See also Warren Neill, "An Emotocentric Theory of Interests," Environmental Ethics, 20 (1998): 163-82.
    • (2000) Philosophical Review , vol.109 , Issue.4 , pp. 598-601
    • Rowlands, M.1
  • 7
    • 0004751216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Emotocentric Theory of Interests
    • Mark Rowlands, "Review of In Nature's Interests?" Philosophical Review 109, no. 4 (2000): 598-601. See also Warren Neill, "An Emotocentric Theory of Interests," Environmental Ethics, 20 (1998): 163-82.
    • (1998) Environmental Ethics , vol.20 , pp. 163-182
    • Neill, W.1
  • 8
    • 0000916983 scopus 로고
    • Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair
    • The most noteworthy criticism of biocentric individualism is that it is insufficient to establish a defense of ecosystems. See J. Baird Callicott, "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair," Environmental Ethics, 2 (1980): 311-38; "The Search for an Environmental Ethic," in Tom Regan, ed. Matters of Life and Death, 2d edition (New York: Random House, 1986): 381-42; "Moral Monism in Environmental Ethics Defended," Journal of Philosophical Research 19 (1994): 51-60.
    • (1980) Environmental Ethics , vol.2 , pp. 311-338
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 9
    • 0001315895 scopus 로고
    • The Search for an Environmental Ethic
    • New York: Random House
    • The most noteworthy criticism of biocentric individualism is that it is insufficient to establish a defense of ecosystems. See J. Baird Callicott, "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair," Environmental Ethics, 2 (1980): 311-38; "The Search for an Environmental Ethic," in Tom Regan, ed. Matters of Life and Death, 2d edition (New York: Random House, 1986): 381-42; "Moral Monism in Environmental Ethics Defended," Journal of Philosophical Research 19 (1994): 51-60.
    • (1986) Matters of Life and Death, 2d Edition , pp. 381-442
    • Regan, T.1
  • 10
    • 0002200461 scopus 로고
    • Moral Monism in Environmental Ethics Defended
    • The most noteworthy criticism of biocentric individualism is that it is insufficient to establish a defense of ecosystems. See J. Baird Callicott, "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair," Environmental Ethics, 2 (1980): 311-38; "The Search for an Environmental Ethic," in Tom Regan, ed. Matters of Life and Death, 2d edition (New York: Random House, 1986): 381-42; "Moral Monism in Environmental Ethics Defended," Journal of Philosophical Research 19 (1994): 51-60.
    • (1994) Journal of Philosophical Research , vol.19 , pp. 51-60
  • 11
    • 85039521320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Varner, In Nature's Interests, pp. 88-97. The idea is that ground projects are a set of goals and desires that in some sense define who one is. The idea comes from Bernard Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981). Other attempts at offering a hierarchy of interests include Nicholas Agar, "Biocentrism and the Concept of Life," Ethics 108 (1997): 147-68.
    • Nature's Interests , pp. 88-97
    • Varner1
  • 12
    • 0004231635 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Varner, In Nature's Interests, pp. 88-97. The idea is that ground projects are a set of goals and desires that in some sense define who one is. The idea comes from Bernard Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981). Other attempts at offering a hierarchy of interests include Nicholas Agar, "Biocentrism and the Concept of Life," Ethics 108 (1997): 147-68.
    • (1981) Moral Luck
    • Williams, B.1
  • 13
    • 0007531359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Biocentrism and the Concept of Life
    • Varner, In Nature's Interests, pp. 88-97. The idea is that ground projects are a set of goals and desires that in some sense define who one is. The idea comes from Bernard Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981). Other attempts at offering a hierarchy of interests include Nicholas Agar, "Biocentrism and the Concept of Life," Ethics 108 (1997): 147-68.
    • (1997) Ethics , vol.108 , pp. 147-168
    • Agar, N.1
  • 14
    • 85039517162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I mean here that we might best emend the term biocentric individualism to something like "teleocentric individualism," but since I argue below that there are as yet no known non-biological systems with the kind of complexity that I believe is needed for interests, my concern remains biological organisms, and I continue to use the established term of biocentric individualism.
  • 15
    • 84977316508 scopus 로고
    • Function and Design
    • Peter French, Theodore Uehling Jr., and Howard Wettstein, eds., Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
    • Philip Kitcher, "Function and Design," in Peter French, Theodore Uehling Jr., and Howard Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1993), vol. 18, pp. 379-97.
    • (1993) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.18 , pp. 379-397
    • Kitcher, P.1
  • 20
    • 0000103250 scopus 로고
    • A Modern History Theory of Functions
    • Peter Godfrey-Smith, "A Modern History Theory of Functions," Nous 28, no. 3 (1994): 344-62; Paul E. Griffiths, "Functional Analysis and Proper Functions," British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 44 (1993): 409-422; Philip Kitcher, "Function and Design"; Ruth G. Millikan, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1984); and White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambrige: MIT Press, 1993); K. Neander, "Functions as Selected Effects: the Conceptual Analyst's Defence," Philosophy of Science 58 (1991): 168-84.
    • (1994) Nous , vol.28 , Issue.3 , pp. 344-362
    • Godfrey-Smith, P.1
  • 21
    • 0001479221 scopus 로고
    • Functional Analysis and Proper Functions
    • Peter Godfrey-Smith, "A Modern History Theory of Functions," Nous 28, no. 3 (1994): 344-62; Paul E. Griffiths, "Functional Analysis and Proper Functions," British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 44 (1993): 409-422; Philip Kitcher, "Function and Design"; Ruth G. Millikan, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1984); and White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambrige: MIT Press, 1993); K. Neander, "Functions as Selected Effects: the Conceptual Analyst's Defence," Philosophy of Science 58 (1991): 168-84.
    • (1993) British Journal of the Philosophy of Science , vol.44 , pp. 409-422
    • Griffiths, P.E.1
  • 22
    • 85039512665 scopus 로고
    • Function and Design
    • Ruth G. Millikan, Cambridge: MIT Press
    • Peter Godfrey-Smith, "A Modern History Theory of Functions," Nous 28, no. 3 (1994): 344-62; Paul E. Griffiths, "Functional Analysis and Proper Functions," British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 44 (1993): 409-422; Philip Kitcher, "Function and Design"; Ruth G. Millikan, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1984); and White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambrige: MIT Press, 1993); K. Neander, "Functions as Selected Effects: the Conceptual Analyst's Defence," Philosophy of Science 58 (1991): 168-84.
    • (1984) Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories
    • Kitcher, P.1
  • 23
    • 0004133776 scopus 로고
    • Cambrige: MIT Press
    • Peter Godfrey-Smith, "A Modern History Theory of Functions," Nous 28, no. 3 (1994): 344-62; Paul E. Griffiths, "Functional Analysis and Proper Functions," British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 44 (1993): 409-422; Philip Kitcher, "Function and Design"; Ruth G. Millikan, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1984); and White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambrige: MIT Press, 1993); K. Neander, "Functions as Selected Effects: the Conceptual Analyst's Defence," Philosophy of Science 58 (1991): 168-84.
    • (1993) White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice
  • 24
    • 0001261899 scopus 로고
    • Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defence
    • Peter Godfrey-Smith, "A Modern History Theory of Functions," Nous 28, no. 3 (1994): 344-62; Paul E. Griffiths, "Functional Analysis and Proper Functions," British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 44 (1993): 409-422; Philip Kitcher, "Function and Design"; Ruth G. Millikan, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1984); and White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambrige: MIT Press, 1993); K. Neander, "Functions as Selected Effects: the Conceptual Analyst's Defence," Philosophy of Science 58 (1991): 168-84.
    • (1991) Philosophy of Science , vol.58 , pp. 168-184
    • Neander, K.1
  • 26
    • 84875323550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Varner is also concerned to accomplish a third task, the defense of the normative claim that the interests are prima facie deserving of moral consideration. As already noted, his discussion of this point is beyond the scope of this paper. See ibid., pp. 71-74.
    • Nature's Interest , pp. 71-74
  • 29
    • 85039537776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In fact, it is plausible that some forms of software have ancestors in the relevant sense, when genetic programming or extensions of genetic algorithms are involved. I return to the issue of artifacts in sec. 6.
  • 30
    • 0002471463 scopus 로고
    • Wright on Functions
    • C. Boorse, "Wright on Functions," Philosophical Review 85 (1976): 70-86.
    • (1976) Philosophical Review , vol.85 , pp. 70-86
    • Boorse, C.1
  • 33
    • 0023631608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coexpression of MMTV/v-Ha-ras and MMTV/c-myc Genes in Transgenic Mice: Synergistic Action of Oncogenes in Vivo
    • For the Harvard oncomouse, see E. Sinn, W. Muller, P. Pattengale, I. Tepler, R. Wallace, and P. Leder, "Coexpression of MMTV/v-Ha-ras and MMTV/c-myc Genes In Transgenic Mice: Synergistic Action of Oncogenes In Vivo," Cell 49 (1987): 465. A source for references and details on shaker-2 mice is the Mouse Genome Database, Mouse Genome Informatics Web Site, The Jackson Laboratory, Bar Harbor, Maine, http://www.informatics.jax.org.
    • (1987) Cell , vol.49 , pp. 465
    • Sinn, E.1    Muller, W.2    Pattengale, P.3    Tepler, I.4    Wallace, R.5    Leder, P.6
  • 34
    • 0023631608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mouse Genome Informatics Web Site, The Jackson Laboratory, Bar Harbor, Maine
    • For the Harvard oncomouse, see E. Sinn, W. Muller, P. Pattengale, I. Tepler, R. Wallace, and P. Leder, "Coexpression of MMTV/v-Ha-ras and MMTV/c-myc Genes In Transgenic Mice: Synergistic Action of Oncogenes In Vivo," Cell 49 (1987): 465. A source for references and details on shaker-2 mice is the Mouse Genome Database, Mouse Genome Informatics Web Site, The Jackson Laboratory, Bar Harbor, Maine, http://www.informatics.jax.org.
    • Mouse Genome Database
  • 35
    • 3142574696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Derived with some first-order logic from Varner, In Nature's Interest, p. 68.
    • Nature's Interest , pp. 68
    • Varner1
  • 39
    • 85039521295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Special thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this point.
  • 40
    • 0001893409 scopus 로고
    • Teleology Revisited
    • Ernest Nagel, "Teleology Revisited," Journal of Philosophy 74, 5 (1977): 261-301; Gerhard Schlosser, "Self-Re-Production and Functionality: A Systems-Theoretical Approach to Teleological Explanation," Syntheses 116 (1998): 303-54;. Gerd Sommerhoff, Analytical Biology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1950).
    • (1977) Journal of Philosophy , vol.74 , Issue.5 , pp. 261-301
    • Nagel, E.1
  • 41
    • 0006137259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-Re-Production and Functionality: A Systems-Theoretical Approach to Teleological Explanation
    • Ernest Nagel, "Teleology Revisited," Journal of Philosophy 74, 5 (1977): 261-301; Gerhard Schlosser, "Self-Re-Production and Functionality: A Systems-Theoretical Approach to Teleological Explanation," Syntheses 116 (1998): 303-54;. Gerd Sommerhoff, Analytical Biology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1950).
    • (1998) Syntheses , vol.116 , pp. 303-354
    • Schlosser, G.1
  • 42
    • 0004020693 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Ernest Nagel, "Teleology Revisited," Journal of Philosophy 74, 5 (1977): 261-301; Gerhard Schlosser, "Self-Re-Production and Functionality: A Systems-Theoretical Approach to Teleological Explanation," Syntheses 116 (1998): 303-54;. Gerd Sommerhoff, Analytical Biology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1950).
    • (1950) Analytical Biology
    • Sommerhoff, G.1
  • 45
    • 0011666465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Complex Systems Theory of Teleology
    • "Self-Re-Production and Functionality." See also Wayne Christensen, "A Complex Systems Theory of Teleology," Biology and Philosophy 11 (1996): 301-20.
    • (1996) Biology and Philosophy , vol.11 , pp. 301-320
    • Christensen, W.1
  • 46
    • 85033753679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 305. In addition to recognizing the necessity that the structure of the system must be relatively complex (if X and F produce each other in a tight, trivial loop, then we are disinclined to think of F as a teleofunction), Schlosser also points out that the system must have some temporal complexity or duration: the cycles of production must be more than one loop, and we should identify a system as homeostatic and therefore interestingly self-organizing only if it is homeostatic for some amount of time. This too is a matter-of-degree issue which, though requiring further analysis, poses no serious difficulty for the view.
    • Biology and Philosophy , pp. 305
  • 48
    • 85039524501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That the theory refers to types is important in part because (as noted above) some structures can have functions that are never exercised. The structure still has the teleofunction because the structure can play that role; and we are able to see that it can play that role because other instances of the structure exercise that role in other instances of its type (e.g., in other individuals of that species).
  • 49
    • 0004248679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Edmund T. Rolls, The Brain and Emotion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 205.
    • (1999) The Brain and Emotion , pp. 205
    • Rolls, E.T.1
  • 50
    • 85039520154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Special thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging this clarification.
  • 51
    • 85039540114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Pace Heidegger, there is a sense in which not just human beings, but all organisms, are homeless.
  • 52
    • 85039530657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An ambiguity must be noted here, to avoid a potential misunderstanding: this kind of systematic teleofunction reaches across a number of instances of kinds - such as a number of individual bees which have stingers. Thus, for example, a species is an appropriate kind of category since it is a population sustained over time; however, if the purpose in question served some smaller population, here we would understand "population" not as a collection of organisms at a moment, but rather as an ongoing, reproducing, group.
  • 53
    • 84945329741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Radical Solution to the Species Problem
    • See Michael Ghiselin, "A Radical Solution to the Species Problem," Systematic Zoology 23 (1974): 536-44; Metaphysics and the Origin of Species (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997); David Hull, "Are Species Really Individuals?" Systematic Zoology 25 (1976): 174-91; "A Matter of Individuality," Philosophy of Science 45 (1978): 335-60; Science as a Process (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1988).
    • (1974) Systematic Zoology , vol.23 , pp. 536-544
    • Ghiselin, M.1
  • 54
    • 84945329741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Albany: State University of New York Press
    • See Michael Ghiselin, "A Radical Solution to the Species Problem," Systematic Zoology 23 (1974): 536-44; Metaphysics and the Origin of Species (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997); David Hull, "Are Species Really Individuals?" Systematic Zoology 25 (1976): 174-91; "A Matter of Individuality," Philosophy of Science 45 (1978): 335-60; Science as a Process (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1988).
    • (1997) Metaphysics and the Origin of Species
  • 55
    • 84963040886 scopus 로고
    • Are Species Really Individuals?
    • See Michael Ghiselin, "A Radical Solution to the Species Problem," Systematic Zoology 23 (1974): 536-44; Metaphysics and the Origin of Species (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997); David Hull, "Are Species Really Individuals?" Systematic Zoology 25 (1976): 174-91; "A Matter of Individuality," Philosophy of Science 45 (1978): 335-60; Science as a Process (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1988).
    • (1976) Systematic Zoology , vol.25 , pp. 174-191
    • Hull, D.1
  • 56
    • 84945329741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Matter of Individuality
    • See Michael Ghiselin, "A Radical Solution to the Species Problem," Systematic Zoology 23 (1974): 536-44; Metaphysics and the Origin of Species (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997); David Hull, "Are Species Really Individuals?" Systematic Zoology 25 (1976): 174-91; "A Matter of Individuality," Philosophy of Science 45 (1978): 335-60; Science as a Process (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1988).
    • (1978) Philosophy of Science , vol.45 , pp. 335-360
  • 57
    • 84945329741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: Chicago University Press
    • See Michael Ghiselin, "A Radical Solution to the Species Problem," Systematic Zoology 23 (1974): 536-44; Metaphysics and the Origin of Species (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997); David Hull, "Are Species Really Individuals?" Systematic Zoology 25 (1976): 174-91; "A Matter of Individuality," Philosophy of Science 45 (1978): 335-60; Science as a Process (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) Science As a Process


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.