메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 4, 2005, Pages 565-585

Between advantage and virtue: Aristotle's theory of political friendship

(1)  Irrera, Elena a  

a NONE   (Italy)

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 31144478345     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (15)

References (118)
  • 1
    • 31144434553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • How can the Aristotelian account of friendship contribute to an understanding of the notion of politikē philia? The aim of this paper is to sketch out a general description of political friendship in the light of Aristotle's well-known distinction between friendships of utility, friendships of pleasure and friendships between virtuous people drawn in Book VIII of the Nicomachean Ethics. I shall define the boundaries of political friendship through the analysis of resemblances to and differences from both friendship according ethical excellence and friendship grounded in mere utility. Political friendship seems to be a kind of advantage-friendship sui generis, where the search for utility does not prevent people from displaying other-regarding qualities like cooperation, trust and loyalty, that are typical of friendship according to ethical excellence. I will also show that activity according to justice replaces the form of mAttendutual and intimate love that should subsist in a friendship based on ethical virtue.
  • 4
    • 0011517507 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on the forms of friendship
    • See J.M. Cooper, 'Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship', Review of Metaphysics, 30 (1977), pp. 619-48, p. 645. However, it is worth noticing that Cooper deems the topic of friendship to be 'of decisive significance for an understanding of Aristotle's moral theory' (p. 648).
    • (1977) Review of Metaphysics , vol.30 , pp. 619-648
    • Cooper, J.M.1
  • 6
    • 0003772614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Stern-Gillet, Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship, pp. 153-4: 'The answer to these perplexities [i.e. those upon the relevance of political friendship in Aristotle's thought] lies, I submit, not in Aristotle's unconcern with civic friendship but in his assumption that civic friendship is but the reflection, in the lives of individuals, of the constitution of the state. Considered in itself, civic friendship is neither noble nor pettily contractual, neither disinterested nor manipulative, neither stable nor unsteady. It is the constitution of the state which, to a large extent, determines not only the nature and the extent of the civic bond but also its moral worth. Like the criteria of good citizenship, those of civic friendship, according to this interpretation, will vary with the constitutions. While sound constitutions encourage all citizens to have regard for each other, defective and deviant ones prompt rulers to be solely concerned with securing a balance of power...There is little in common between the kinds of civic friendship that these constitutions generate.'
    • Aristotle's Philosophy of Friendship , pp. 153-154
    • Stern-Gillet1
  • 7
    • 31144437289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1161a10-b12.
    • NE VIII
  • 8
    • 31144475544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. S. Broadie and C.J. Rowe, trans. C.J. Rowe (Oxford)
    • All the passages of the Nicomachean Ethics quoted in this paper will be taken from Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translation, Introduction, and Commentary, ed. S. Broadie and C.J. Rowe, trans. C.J. Rowe (Oxford, 2002).
    • (2002) Translation, Introduction, and Commentary
    • Aristotle1    Ethics, N.2
  • 9
    • 31144442099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1155a3-5.
    • NE VIII
  • 11
    • 84877986371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In more than one case Aristotle implies a conceptual distinction between 'mere living' (zēr) and 'living well' (eu zēn); see for instance Politics I, 1252b29-30,
    • Politics I
  • 12
    • 0004080299 scopus 로고
    • trans. E. Barker (Oxford)
    • where it is said that the polis 'grows for the sake of mere life', but 'it exists for the sake of a good life' (Aristotle. Politics, trans. E. Barker (Oxford, 1948));
    • (1948) Politics
    • Aristotle1
  • 13
    • 31144468237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Politics, III, 1280b33-5);
    • Politics , vol.3
  • 14
    • 31144458516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Politics, I, 1253b24-5 (with reference to the art of acquiring property Aristotle says: 'it is impossible to live well, or indeed to live at all, unless the necessary conditions are present').
    • Politics , vol.1
  • 17
    • 31144474042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1155a5-9.
    • NE VIII
  • 18
    • 31144431539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EE VII, 1234b31-4.
    • EE VII
  • 21
    • 31144474786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • On Aristotle's frequent appeal to and confidence in endoxa see T.H. Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford, 2002), pp. 30-1.
    • (2002) Aristotle's First Principles , pp. 30-31
    • Irwin, T.H.1
  • 22
    • 31144471756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of to kalon occurs many times in Aristotle's ethical works, especially in the Nicomachean Ethics, where he repeatedly stresses that acting according to ethical excellences is a fine thing (see for instance NE II, 1109a29-30, where it is said that getting the intermediate in actions and passions is a rare thing and something fine; see also its relationship with voluntariness of actions at NE III, 1113b). As for the employment of to kalon in Aristotle's metaphysical thought,
    • NE II
  • 23
  • 24
    • 84900313099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where to kalon (alongside to agathon), is mentioned as the principle of knowledge and movement; see also Metaph. A, 1072a27-30, where the object of desire, which coincides with the object of nous, is what appears fine to us, and the primary object of boulēsis is what is objectively fine (to on kalon);
    • Metaph. A
  • 25
    • 31144470594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • again, at Metaph. A, 1074b24,
    • Metaph. A
  • 26
    • 31144471505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it is said that the divine nous thinks to kalon rather than anything whatever; finally, see Metaph. M, 1078a31-b5, where Aristotle claims that to kalon can be found not only in actions, but even in immovable things, and its supreme forms are orderly arrangement (taxis), proportion (symmetria) and definiteness (to ōrismenon).
    • Metaph. M
  • 30
    • 31144466994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE I, 1102a9-10.
    • NE i
  • 31
    • 31144463055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. EE VII, 1234b22-5.
    • EE VII
  • 32
    • 31144437050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1155b18-19.
    • NE VIII
  • 34
    • 0004303513 scopus 로고
    • (Garden City, NY), Arendt defines respect as 'a regard for the person from the distance which th space of the world puts between us'
    • See Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Garden City, NY, 1958), p. 218. Arendt defines respect as 'a regard for the person from the distance which the space of the world puts between us'.
    • (1958) The Human Condition , pp. 218
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 36
    • 31144475306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression 'kata symbebēkos' is often employed in Aristotle's Metaphysics as distinct from expressions employed to qualify ousia, like 'to kath' hauto'. See for instance Metaph. A, 1017a7-8,
    • Metaph. A
  • 37
    • 0039373236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he claims that Being (to on) can be said 'accidentally' or 'for itself'; cf. Δ, 1015bl6-17; see also Γ, 1003b32-3; Γ, 1007a29-32. When Aristotle applies the notion of 'kata symbebēkos' to friendship, he seems to be referring to his idea that 'only character friends are essentially and without adventitious qualification' (Cooper, Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship, p. 636).
    • Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship , pp. 636
    • Cooper1
  • 38
    • 31144476063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1156b10.
    • NE VIII
  • 39
    • 31144438295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. NE VIII, 1156b7;
    • NE VIII
  • 42
    • 0009239708 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's account of friendship in the nicomachean ethics
    • S.A.D.M. Walker, 'Aristotle's Account of Friendship in the Nicomachean Ethics', Phronesis,24 (1979), pp. 180-96, p. 187.
    • (1979) Phronesis , vol.24 , pp. 180-196
    • Walker, S.A.D.M.1
  • 44
    • 31144474785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1156b7-9.
    • NE VIII
  • 45
    • 31144477190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NE VIII, 1155b31.
    • NE VIII
  • 47
    • 31144477427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhet. II, 1380b36-1381a1.
    • Rhet. II
  • 48
    • 31144444432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EE VII, 1241a1-14.
    • EE VII
  • 50
    • 31144467518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1158b5-10.
    • NE VIII
  • 51
    • 0009227512 scopus 로고
    • Oxford.
    • The treatment of resemblance between perfect friendship and friendships kata sumbebēkos in the Nicomachean Ethics seems to differ greatly from that provided in the Eudemian Ethics. See A.W. Price, Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle (Oxford. 1989), p. 131:
    • (1989) Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle , pp. 131
    • Price, A.W.1
  • 52
    • 31144457402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • prōtēphilia
    • 'It is characteristic of the Eudemian Ethics that it offers a more logical theory, or presentation of a theory, than does the Nicomachean about the relation between the varieties of friendship.' In the Eudemian Ethics friendship of goodness is described as 'primary' (see for instance EE VII, 1236b2: prōtēphilia),
    • EE VII
  • 53
    • 31144438294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • presumably in accordance with the meaning of 'primary' at EE VII, 1236a19-22:
    • EE VII
  • 54
    • 31144439703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The primary is that of which the definition is implicit in the definition of all, for example a surgical instrument is an instrument that a surgeon would use, whereas the definition of the instrument is not implicit in that of surgeon' (cf. Metaph. Z, 1028a34-6; M, 1077b3-4). As is claimed at EE VII, 1236a17-20, different kinds of friendships are defined exclusively with reference to one kind of friendship, i.e. the primary (pros mian [philian] . . . kai prōtēn).
    • Metaph. Z
  • 55
    • 31144460995 scopus 로고
    • Logic and Metaphysics in Some Earlier Works of Aristotle
    • ed. I. During and G.E.L Owen (Göteborg)
    • This kind of comparative analysis has led Owen to claim that friendships of utility and pleasure appear to be 'focally related', even in the Nicomachean Ethics (see G.E.L. Owen, Logic and Metaphysics in Some Earlier Works of Aristotle, in Aristotle and Plato in the Mid-Fourth Century, ed. I. During and G.E.L Owen (Göteborg, 1960), pp. 163-90, p. 169;
    • (1960) Aristotle and Plato in the Mid-fourth Century , pp. 163-190
    • Owen, G.E.L.1
  • 57
    • 31144446245 scopus 로고
    • Plato and Aristotle on friendship and altruism
    • By contrast, Annas claims that no trace of focal meaning, so prominent in the Eudemian Ethics, can be found in the Nicomachean account of friendship (see J. Annas, 'Plato and Aristotle on Friendship and Altruism', Mind, 86 (1977), pp. 532-54, p. 547).
    • (1977) Mind , vol.86 , pp. 532-54
    • Annas, J.1
  • 58
    • 31144456881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • tend to agree with Annas, although, on my view, a 'focal' approach might.be tracked down in NE VIII, 1157al-2,
    • NE VIII
  • 59
    • 31144469371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • similarly to EE VII, 1236a17-20.
    • EE VII
  • 60
    • 31144452016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. NE VIII, 1156b19-23, where Aristotle points out that 'every kind of friendship is because of some good or because of pleasure, either without qualification or for the person loving', and that 'the good without qualification is also pleasant without qualification'.
    • NE VIII
  • 61
    • 31144442649 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's analysis of friendship: Function and analogy, resemblance and focal meaning
    • See W. Fortenbaugh, 'Aristotle's Analysis of Friendship: Function and Analogy, Resemblance and Focal Meaning', Phronesis, 20 (1975), pp. 51-62, p. 56. Fortenbaugh maintains that on some occasions in the Nicomachean Ethics the three forms of friendship described by Aristotle appear to be analogically related. For an explanation and a criticism of Fortenbaugh's view,
    • (1975) Phronesis , vol.20 , pp. 51-62
    • Fortenbaugh, W.1
  • 64
    • 31144458756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See footnote above
    • See footnote above.
  • 66
    • 0039373236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooper, Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship, pp. 642-3. With reference to NE VIII, 1167a13-14 he claims: 'So what Aristotle denies here is that oio. precedes, and possibly turns into, a friendship of one of the derivative sorts; he does not deny that once such a relationship has begun eunoia develops within it'.
    • Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship , pp. 642-643
    • Cooper1
  • 67
    • 31144464692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EE VII, 1241a12-14.
    • EE VII
  • 68
    • 31144471257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's main intention here is that of showing that eunoia is not a sufficient condition of friendship
    • Aristotle's main intention here is that of showing that eunoia is not a sufficient condition of friendship.
  • 69
    • 0039373236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That well-wishing for the friend occurs in all three kinds of friendship identified by Aristotle is the thesis maintained by Cooper in Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship;
    • Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship
    • Cooper1
  • 70
    • 24944551753 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and altruism
    • however, I do not agree with Cooper when he claims that Aristotle really makes general well-wishing and well-doing out of concern for the other person's good a condition of any kind of friendship, even of advantage- and pleasure-friendships, without specifying the particular way in which friends reciprocally love themselves. His point is that Aristotle 'does not maintain that friendships of the derivative kinds are wholly self-centered: pleasure- and advantage-friendships are instead a complex and subtle mixture of self-seeking and unself-interested well-wishing and well-doing' (p. 626). Criticism against Cooper's view, to which I subscribe, is lodged by Kahn in C.H. Kahn, 'Aristotle and Altruism', Mind, 90 (1981), pp. 20-40, p. 21, footnote 1. Kahn thinks that the evidence provided by Cooper is inconclusive.
    • (1981) Mind , vol.90 , pp. 20-40
    • Kahn, C.H.1
  • 73
    • 0040816097 scopus 로고
    • Impersonal friends
    • For an opposite view see J.E. Whiting, 'Impersonal Friends', Monist, 74 (1991), pp. 3-29, p. 20.
    • (1991) Monist , vol.74 , pp. 3-29
    • Whiting, J.E.1
  • 74
    • 31144443644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • With refer ence to NE IX, 1167a10-18, Whiting claims that, in Aristotle's thought, characterfriendship alone is founded on eunoia.
    • NE IX
  • 75
  • 77
    • 31144467237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At NE V, 1129530-3 it is claimed that universal justice prescribes complete excellence of character to the highest degree, since the person who possesses it exercises his excellence in relation to other people, and not just by himself; such a view finds support in the common belief that justice is an allotrion agathon (
    • NE v , pp. 1129530-1129533
  • 78
    • 31144475543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see NE V, 1130a2-5). On the notion of allotrion agathon,
    • NE v
  • 79
    • 31144458755 scopus 로고
    • Bologna
    • see G. Zanetti, La Nozione di Giustizia in Aristotele (Bologna, 1993), p. 21: 'La giustizia universale si differenzia dalle altre virtù grazie al suo costitutivo rapportarsi all' altro: essa rappresenta dunque il fondamento intersoggettivo della virtù, la fondamentale interazione presupposta da Aristotele nella sua concezione della giustizia come virtù sociale, ponte teorico fra ciò ehe in epoca moderna sarebbero stati definiti come ambiti dell'etica e della politica'.
    • (1993) La Nozione di Giustizia in Aristotele , pp. 21
    • Zanetti, G.1
  • 81
    • 31144451256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NE V, 1130b30-1131a1.
    • NE v
  • 82
    • 84894346289 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's subdivisions of "particular justice"
    • See D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of "Particular Justice" ', Classical Review, 8 (1894), pp. 185-92, p. 185. Ritchie maintains that the concept of reciprocity is at the basis of those forms of particular justice; he coins the term 'Catallactic justice' with reference to the ground of reciprocity which makes the practice of particular justice possible. On his account of Catallactic justice see p. 192 of his article.
    • (1894) Classical Review , vol.8 , pp. 185-192
    • Ritchie, D.G.1
  • 85
    • 31144460477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EE VII, 1237b9-10.
    • EE VII
  • 86
    • 31144453580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1156a19-21.
    • NE VIII
  • 87
    • 31144467517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1156a21-4.
    • NE VIII
  • 89
    • 31144452014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1155a22-3.
    • NE VIII
  • 91
    • 31144457401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE 1162b16-21;
    • NE
  • 92
    • 31144443165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1163a9-16;
    • NE
  • 93
    • 31144450714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EE 1243a2-b38.
    • EE
  • 96
    • 31144463318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1280b32-5. Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles, pp. 399-406. See in particular p. 402: 'Since the city is comprehensive, seeking to plan for everything that is needed for the complete good, a rational agent has good reason to want to share in its deliberations. This argument implies that a virtuous person does not value the city simply because of its general concern with the expedient (Cf. EN 1160a9-14). Aristotle suggests that essentially political activities are them-selves part of the complete and happy life. If the city provides only the instrumental resources needed for a complete and happy life, it is not clear why the virtuous person values just action for its own sake'.
    • Aristotle's First Principles , pp. 399-406
    • Irwin1
  • 99
    • 31144479061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1156b7-9.
    • NE VIII
  • 100
    • 31144443645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will not treat the issue in detail; however, the notion of friend as allos autos has often been thought to represent 'the crucial concept which permits Aristotle to pass from virtuous self-love to an altruistic concern for the interests of others' (Kahn, Aristotle and Altruism, p. 29).
    • Aristotle and Altruism , pp. 29
    • Kahn1
  • 101
    • 0040029302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might also be taken as implying that the virtuous person's attitude towards herself might serve as a normative paradigm for her attitudes towards her friends (see Whiting, Impersonal Friends, p. 4),
    • Impersonal Friends , pp. 4
    • Whiting1
  • 103
    • 85056559025 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ
    • The idea of friend as 'allos autos' casts a new light on the relationships egoism and altruism. It seems that, on Aristotle's view, there is some compatibility between egoism (as involving rational desire towards what is good in absolute, e.g. ethical excellence) and altruism (conceived as a form of concern for the welfare of others for their own sake). See for instance T. Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism (Princeton, NJ, 1970).
    • (1970) The Possibility of Altruism
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 105
    • 84923961413 scopus 로고
    • Egoism as a theory of human motives
    • who speaks of 'self-referential altruism', i.e. a 'concern for others who have some special connection with oneself'; cf. pp. 84 f. (he has adopted this terminology from C.D. Broad, 'Egoism as a Theory of Human Motives', Hibbert Journal, 48 (1949-50), pp. 105-14).
    • (1949) Hibbert Journal , vol.48 , pp. 105-114
  • 106
    • 31144443645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The logical priority of egoism over altruism is stressed by Kahn, Aristotle and Altruism, p. 26
    • Aristotle and Altruism , pp. 26
    • Kahn1
  • 109
    • 31144443645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Kahn, Aristotle and Altruism, p. 31: 'The excellence and pleasure of the good life partially consists in the observation of moral activity; but we are better placed to observe the actions of others; hence the happy man will need others around him, who are like him in goodness and bound to him in friendship, so that he can observe their actions as akin to his own (1169b30-70a4)'.
    • Aristotle and Altruism , pp. 31
    • Kahn1
  • 111
    • 31144437796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1157b19-24.
    • NE VIII
  • 112
    • 31144473314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1158a10-12.
    • NE VIII
  • 114
    • 31144444192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. EEVII, 1237b10-13, where it is claimed that there is no stable friendship without confidence.
    • EEVII
  • 115
    • 31144472808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WE VIII, 1155a23-4.
    • WE VIII
  • 116
    • 31144450716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NE VIII, 1155a26-7.
    • NE VIII
  • 118
    • 31144432040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNIVERSITY OF DURHAM
    • UNIVERSITY OF DURHAM


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.