메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 10, Issue 3, 2004, Pages 117-156

Methodology in jurisprudence

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 31144473725     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325204040200     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (62)

References (137)
  • 1
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • (1st ed., 1961; 2nd ed. with Postscript, Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz, eds., ). All page references to this work are given according to the pagination in the 2nd edition.
    • H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (1st ed., 1961; 2nd ed. with Postscript, Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz, eds., 1994). All page references to this work are given according to the pagination in the 2nd edition.
    • (1994) THE CONCEPT OF LAW
    • HART, H.L.A.1
  • 2
    • 85022406071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE CONCEPT OF LAW note 1, at
    • HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW note 1, at 1.
    • HART , pp. 1
  • 4
    • 85022353683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent interest in methodology in legal theory also owes much to Ronald Dworkin's work and especially to the discussions of methodology that feature in his explanation of the nature and role of constructive interpretation in DWORKIN note 1, at
    • HART, Recent interest in methodology in legal theory also owes much to Ronald Dworkin's work and especially to the discussions of methodology that feature in his explanation of the nature and role of constructive interpretation in DWORKIN note 1, at 239-241.
    • HART , pp. 239-241
  • 5
    • 85022362740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, while Hart's claim that his account attempts to be general in this sense seems uncontroversial, his success in his self-proclaimed task and indeed the possibility of success in principle in that task are much more contentious. note 1, at 240. The internal quotation is from DWORKIN, Of course, while Hart's claim that his account attempts to be general in this sense seems uncontroversial, his success in his self-proclaimed task and indeed the possibility of success in principle in that task are much more contentious. note 3, at
    • HART, Of course, while Hart's claim that his account attempts to be general in this sense seems uncontroversial, his success in his self-proclaimed task and indeed the possibility of success in principle in that task are much more contentious. note 1, at 240. The internal quotation is from DWORKIN, Of course, while Hart's claim that his account attempts to be general in this sense seems uncontroversial, his success in his self-proclaimed task and indeed the possibility of success in principle in that task are much more contentious. note 3, at 102.
    • HART , pp. 102
  • 7
    • 85022446199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW 1-37 (J.L. Coleman, ed., ), at
    • J. Raz, Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison, in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW 1-37 (J.L. Coleman, ed., 2001), at 26.
    • (2001) Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison , pp. 26
    • Raz, J.1
  • 8
    • 84881116610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/law-interpretivist/, esp. sects. 1 and
    • N. Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/law-interpretivist/ (2003), esp. sects. 1 and 2.
    • (2003) Interpretivist Theories of Law , pp. 2
    • Stavropoulos, N.1
  • 9
    • 85022392555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretivist Theories of Law note 1, at
    • HART, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 1, at 240.
    • HART , pp. 240
  • 10
    • 0009445978 scopus 로고
    • in LAW AND INTERPRETATION (A. Marmor, ed., ), at 100: “the most satisfactory jurisprudential theories turn out not to be purely descriptive and value-free, as Hart claimed.”
    • See, e.g., S.R. Perry, Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory, in LAW AND INTERPRETATION (A. Marmor, ed., 1995), at 100: “the most satisfactory jurisprudential theories turn out not to be purely descriptive and value-free, as Hart claimed.”
    • (1995) Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 11
    • 85022376760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory, note 1, at
    • HART, Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory, note 1, at 242-244.
    • HART , pp. 242-244
  • 12
    • 85022427134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART note 1, at 244. This is discussed further in Section II.
    • HART, HART note 1, at 244. This is discussed further in Section II.
    • HART
  • 14
    • 85022374394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART note 3 note 1, These issues are discussed further in Section III.
    • HART, HART note 3 note 1, at 248-250. These issues are discussed further in Section III.
    • HART , pp. 248-250
  • 15
    • 85022418257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART note 1, For the semantic-sting argument, see DWORKIN, HART note 3, chaps. 1 and 2
    • HART, HART note 1, at 244-248. For the semantic-sting argument, see DWORKIN, HART note 3, chaps. 1 and 2.
    • HART , pp. 244-248
  • 16
    • 85022431726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The argument is intended by Dworkin to apply both to propositions of law and to the concept of law. note 1, This issue is addressed in Section V.
    • HART, The argument is intended by Dworkin to apply both to propositions of law and to the concept of law. note 1, at 246. This issue is addressed in Section V.
    • HART , pp. 246
  • 21
    • 0347613404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It should be noted that although these theorists share a common position to the extent that they all believe that successful legal theory must be evaluative but need not involve the legal theorist in moral or political evaluation and justification of law, there are important differences between their respective views. Unfortunately, these cannot be discussed in any detail here.
    • J. DICKSON, EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY (2001). It should be noted that although these theorists share a common position to the extent that they all believe that successful legal theory must be evaluative but need not involve the legal theorist in moral or political evaluation and justification of law, there are important differences between their respective views. Unfortunately, these cannot be discussed in any detail here.
    • (2001) EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY
    • DICKSON, J.1
  • 23
    • 85022349389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS note 24, at
    • FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS note 24, at 12.
    • FINNIS1
  • 24
    • 85022351697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS note 1, passim, but see esp. 55-61, 88-91, 105-110, and the Postscript
    • HART, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS note 1, passim, but see esp. 55-61, 88-91, 105-110, and the Postscript, 242-244.
    • HART , pp. 242-244
  • 25
    • 85022444111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART note 1, at
    • HART, HART note 1, at 203.
    • HART , pp. 203
  • 27
    • 85022375855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Finnis's account of human well-being and the role of law in securing it note 23, chaps. 2 and
    • DICKSON, For Finnis's account of human well-being and the role of law in securing it note 23, chaps. 2 and 3.
    • DICKSON1
  • 28
    • 85022449990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see DICKSON, For Finnis's account of human well-being and the role of law in securing it note 23, at 3, 35, and 35 note
    • I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY, see DICKSON, For Finnis's account of human well-being and the role of law in securing it note 23, at 3, 35, and 35 note 9.
    • I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY , pp. 9
  • 29
    • 85022396104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY note 23, at
    • DICKSON, I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY note 23, at 32-39.
    • DICKSON1
  • 30
    • 85022419463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY note 23, at 64, and, more generally, chaps. 2, 3, 6, and 7. See further DICKSON, I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY note
    • DICKSON, I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY note 23, at 64, and, more generally, chaps. 2, 3, 6, and 7. My views on the above issues cannot be fully explained or defended here. See further DICKSON, I note this point in EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY note 23.
    • My views on the above issues cannot be fully explained or defended here , Issue.23
    • DICKSON1
  • 31
    • 85022370260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My views on the above issues cannot be fully explained or defended here. note 23, at
    • DICKSON, My views on the above issues cannot be fully explained or defended here. note 23, at 135.
    • DICKSON1
  • 32
    • 85022435674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I attempt to explain the methodological commitments of legal theory that aspires to give a general account of the nature of law in all legal systems.
    • In EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY, I attempt to explain the methodological commitments of legal theory that aspires to give a general account of the nature of law in all legal systems.
    • EVALUATION AND LEGAL THEORY
  • 34
    • 84972620169 scopus 로고
    • 17 PHIL. SOC. SCI., at 15. This article offers a thoughtful analysis of different possible types of legal theory and claims that an evaluative but not morally evaluative approach to legal theory is a tenable position.
    • L. Green, The Political Content of Legal Theory, 17 PHIL. SOC. SCI., 1-20 (1987), at 15. This article offers a thoughtful analysis of different possible types of legal theory and claims that an evaluative but not morally evaluative approach to legal theory is a tenable position.
    • (1987) The Political Content of Legal Theory , pp. 1-20
    • Green, L.1
  • 35
    • 85022366254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Political Content of Legal Theory note 22, at
    • WALUCHOW, The Political Content of Legal Theory note 22, at 22.
    • WALUCHOW1
  • 36
    • 85022399106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above.
    • See note 30, above.
    • note 30
  • 37
    • 85022368216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 97; Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism 4 LEGAL THEORY 427, reprinted in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. 2001), at 311; Perry, Holmes v. Hart: The Bad Man in Legal Theory, in “THE PATH OF LAW” AND ITS INFLUENCE (S. Burton, ed., 2000), at
    • See e.g., S.R. Perry, note 30 note 11, at 97; Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism 4 LEGAL THEORY 427 (1998), reprinted in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. 2001), at 311; Perry, Holmes v. Hart: The Bad Man in Legal Theory, in “THE PATH OF LAW” AND ITS INFLUENCE (S. Burton, ed., 2000), at 156.
    • (1998) note 30 note 11 , pp. 156
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 39
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 321.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism , pp. 321
    • Perry1
  • 40
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 314.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism , pp. 314
    • Perry1
  • 41
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, secs. IV-I.
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, secs. IV-I.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism
    • Perry1
  • 42
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 326.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism , pp. 326
    • Perry1
  • 43
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, secs. IV and V.
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, secs. IV and V.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism
    • Perry1
  • 44
    • 85022445019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed., 2001), at 371, note 10, and 378; Michael Moore, Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript 4 LEGAL THEORY 301-327, reprinted in M. Moore, EDUCATING ONESELF IN PUBLIC (2000), at 79; Brian Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate: The Methodology Problem in Jurisprudence, 48 AM. J. JURIS. 17-51 (2003).
    • See, e.g., Liam Murphy, The Political Question of the Concept of Law, in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed., 2001), at 371, note 10, and 378; Michael Moore, Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript 4 LEGAL THEORY 301-327 (1998), reprinted in M. Moore, EDUCATING ONESELF IN PUBLIC (2000), at 79; Brian Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate: The Methodology Problem in Jurisprudence, 48 AM. J. JURIS. 17-51 (2003).
    • (1998) The Political Question of the Concept of Law
    • Murphy, L.1
  • 45
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Political Question of the Concept of Law note 39, at
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, The Political Question of the Concept of Law note 39, at 349.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism , pp. 349
    • Perry1
  • 46
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 327.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism , pp. 327
    • Perry1
  • 47
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 337 (emphasis in original).
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 337 (emphasis in original).
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism
    • Perry1
  • 48
    • 33845709518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at
    • Perry, Hart's Methodological Positivism, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 39, at 339.
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism , pp. 339
    • Perry1
  • 49
    • 85022399066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Methodological Positivism note 19, at
    • Hart, Hart's Methodological Positivism note 19, at 39.
    • Hart , pp. 39
  • 51
    • 85022400417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 76 TEX. L. REV. 267, at 285.See also B. Leiter, Legal Realism, Hard Positivism, and the Limits of Conceptual Analysis, inHART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed., 2001), at 355; Leiter, Naturalism and Naturalized Jurisprudence, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY (B. Bix, ed., 1998), at 79; Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered 111 ETHICS (2001), at 278; Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Andrei Marmor also argues that such a dichotomy is spurious in MARMOR note
    • B. Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence, 76 TEX. L. REV. 267 (1997), at 285.See also B. Leiter, Legal Realism, Hard Positivism, and the Limits of Conceptual Analysis, inHART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed., 2001), at 355; Leiter, Naturalism and Naturalized Jurisprudence, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY (B. Bix, ed., 1998), at 79; Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered 111 ETHICS (2001), at 278; Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Andrei Marmor also argues that such a dichotomy is spurious in MARMOR note 46.
    • (1997) Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence , pp. 46
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 52
    • 0039040024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence note 53, at
    • Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism, Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence note 53, at 286.
    • Rethinking Legal Realism , pp. 286
    • Leiter1
  • 53
    • 85022356602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a detailed taxonomy of different types of naturalism and their potential roles in legal theory, see B. Leiter, Naturalism in Legal Philosophy, STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lawphil-naturalism/
    • Leiter's views are much more subtle than I can express in this brief summary. For a detailed taxonomy of different types of naturalism and their potential roles in legal theory, see B. Leiter, Naturalism in Legal Philosophy, STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lawphil-naturalism/ (2002).
    • (2002) Leiter's views are much more subtle than I can express in this brief summary
  • 54
    • 0039039967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Leiter's views are much more subtle than I can express in this brief summary. note 46, sec. III; see also B. Leiter, in OBJECTIVITY IN LAW AND MORALS 66 (B. Leiter, ed., ).
    • See Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Leiter's views are much more subtle than I can express in this brief summary. note 46, sec. III; see also B. Leiter, Objectivity, Morality and Adjudication, in OBJECTIVITY IN LAW AND MORALS 66 (B. Leiter, ed., 2001).
    • (2001) Objectivity, Morality and Adjudication
    • Leiter1
  • 55
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Objectivity, Morality and Adjudication note 46, sec. II
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Objectivity, Morality and Adjudication note 46, sec. II, 40-43.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 40-43
  • 56
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 40.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 40
  • 57
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 43.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 43
  • 58
    • 85022437867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and, more generally, chap. 2. See also the discussion of indirectly evaluative legal theory earlier in this section.
    • DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, at 32-33, and, more generally, chap. 2. See also the discussion of indirectly evaluative legal theory earlier in this section.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23 , pp. 32-33
    • DICKSON1
  • 59
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23 note 46, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23 note 46, at 42.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 42
  • 60
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 40. See also DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 40. See also DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, at 41-44.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 41-44
  • 61
    • 85022421914 scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 42. The internal quotation is from J. Raz, in J. RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 42. The internal quotation is from J. Raz, Authority, Law and Morality, in J. RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN (1994), at 237.
    • (1994) Authority, Law and Morality , pp. 237
  • 62
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Authority, Law and Morality note 46, at 43 (emphasis in original).
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Authority, Law and Morality note 46, at 43 (emphasis in original).
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate
  • 63
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 43. The internal quotation is from DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 43. The internal quotation is from DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, at 9.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 9
  • 67
    • 85022421150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jules Coleman also notes the unfortunate connotations of Hart's use of the term in COLEMAN note 23, at 37 and
    • See DICKSON, Jules Coleman also notes the unfortunate connotations of Hart's use of the term in COLEMAN note 23, at 37 and 38-49.
    • DICKSON1
  • 69
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Jules Coleman also notes the unfortunate connotations of Hart's use of the term in COLEMAN note 23 note 46, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Jules Coleman also notes the unfortunate connotations of Hart's use of the term in COLEMAN note 23 note 46, at 43.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 43
  • 70
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • again, Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at
    • See, again, Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 43.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 43
  • 71
    • 85022351797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23 at
    • DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23 at 43.
    • DICKSON1
  • 72
    • 85022361937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, esp. at 60-64 and
    • DICKSON, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 23, esp. at 60-64 and 134-137.
    • DICKSON1
  • 73
  • 74
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 42.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 42
  • 75
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 42.
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate , pp. 42
  • 76
    • 85022360697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 43 (emphasis in original).
    • Leiter, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 46, at 43 (emphasis in original).
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate
  • 77
    • 85022428831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 1, at
    • HART, Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate note 1, at 244.
    • HART , pp. 244
  • 78
    • 85022425348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART note 1, at
    • HART, HART note 1, at 243.
    • HART , pp. 243
  • 79
    • 85022395126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HART note 19, at
    • HART, HART note 19, at 39.
    • HART , pp. 39
  • 80
    • 85022367421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • my remarks on this issue at the close of Sections II.A and II.B above. note 1, at
    • HART, my remarks on this issue at the close of Sections II.A and II.B above. note 1, at 248-249.
    • HART , pp. 248-249
  • 85
    • 85022384066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, Postema on Law's Autonomy and Public Practical Reasons: a critical comment note 3, at 190: see also his reinterpretation of legal positivism as “conventionalism” in DWORKIN, Postema on Law's Autonomy and Public Practical Reasons: a critical comment note 3, chap. 4; and his cursory dismissal of the alternative task of legal theory postulated by the critical legal studies movement in DWORKIN, Postema on Law's Autonomy and Public Practical Reasons: a critical comment note 3, at
    • See, e.g., DWORKIN, Postema on Law's Autonomy and Public Practical Reasons: a critical comment note 3, at 190: “A conception of law must explain how what it takes to be law provides a general justification for the exercise of coercive power by the state”; see also his reinterpretation of legal positivism as “conventionalism” in DWORKIN, Postema on Law's Autonomy and Public Practical Reasons: a critical comment note 3, chap. 4; and his cursory dismissal of the alternative task of legal theory postulated by the critical legal studies movement in DWORKIN, Postema on Law's Autonomy and Public Practical Reasons: a critical comment note 3, at 271-274.
    • “A conception of law must explain how what it takes to be law provides a general justification for the exercise of coercive power by the state”; , pp. 271-274
  • 87
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “A conception of law must explain how what it takes to be law provides a general justification for the exercise of coercive power by the state”; note 20 note 9, sec. 1.
    • See Stavropoulos, “A conception of law must explain how what it takes to be law provides a general justification for the exercise of coercive power by the state”; note 20 note 9, sec. 1.
    • Stavropoulos
  • 88
    • 85022385834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (unpublished manuscript, Oxford ), part I, that legal positivists take the starting point for legal theoretical inquiry to focus on the questions: In virtue of what are laws part of a legal system and from whom (or from which institution) do such laws emanate? and that so doing already loads the dice in favor of the positivist understanding of law as systems of rules emanating from sources of a particular kind.
    • It is Stavropoulos's view in Interpretivism (unpublished manuscript, Oxford 2004), part I, that legal positivists take the starting point for legal theoretical inquiry to focus on the questions: In virtue of what are laws part of a legal system and from whom (or from which institution) do such laws emanate? and that so doing already loads the dice in favor of the positivist understanding of law as systems of rules emanating from sources of a particular kind.
    • (2004) It is Stavropoulos's view in Interpretivism
  • 89
    • 85022388509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretivist Theories of Law, It is Stavropoulos's view in Interpretivism note 9, sec. 1.
    • This formulation is taken from Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, It is Stavropoulos's view in Interpretivism note 9, sec. 1.
    • This formulation is taken from Stavropoulos
  • 90
    • 85022360559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos, This formulation is taken from Stavropoulos note 9, sec. 4.
    • Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, This formulation is taken from Stavropoulos note 9, sec. 4.
    • Interpretivist Theories of Law
  • 91
    • 85022360559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, see Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 9, secs. 3, 4, and
    • On this point, see Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 9, secs. 3, 4, and 7.
    • Interpretivist Theories of Law , pp. 7
  • 93
    • 85022360559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 9, secs. 3, 4, and 7, and Stavropoulos, Interpretivism, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 91, sec. I.
    • Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 9, secs. 3, 4, and 7, and Stavropoulos, Interpretivism, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 91, sec. I.
    • Interpretivist Theories of Law
  • 94
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretivism, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 91, sec. I.
    • Stavropoulos, Interpretivism, Interpretivist Theories of Law note 91, sec. I.
    • Stavropoulos
  • 95
    • 85022350639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos note 46, at
    • Murphy, Stavropoulos note 46, at 371.
    • Murphy , pp. 371
  • 96
    • 85022411052 scopus 로고
    • In DICKSON Murphy note 23, chap. 5, I discuss Frederick Schauer's version of the position, which I term a “beneficial moral consequences argument.” Schauer's argument can be found in F. Schauer, Positivism as Pariah, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LEGAL POSITIVISM (R.P. George, ed., 1996); and Schauer, Positivism through Thick and Thin, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY (B. Bix. ed., 1998). Neil MacCormick is also a proponent of this kind of view; see MacCormick, 20 VAL. U.L. REV.
    • In DICKSON Murphy note 23, chap. 5, I discuss Frederick Schauer's version of the position, which I term a “beneficial moral consequences argument.” Schauer's argument can be found in F. Schauer, Positivism as Pariah, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LEGAL POSITIVISM (R.P. George, ed., 1996); and Schauer, Positivism through Thick and Thin, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY (B. Bix. ed., 1998). Neil MacCormick is also a proponent of this kind of view; see MacCormick, A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law 20 VAL. U.L. REV. 1-41 (1985).
    • (1985) A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law , pp. 1-41
  • 97
    • 85022411889 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law note 46, at 372 and
    • Murphy, A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law note 46, at 372 and 376.
    • Murphy , pp. 376
  • 98
    • 85022420761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Murphy note 46, at 372, 382-383, and
    • Murphy, Murphy note 46, at 372, 382-383, and 389.
    • Murphy , pp. 389
  • 99
    • 85022429104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Murphy note 46, at
    • Murphy, Murphy note 46, at 383.
    • Murphy , pp. 383
  • 100
    • 85022350813 scopus 로고
    • On the difference between hard and soft (or inclusive) positivism, see L. Green, available at http://plato.stanford. edu/entries/legal-positivism/. On different interpretations of the social thesis, see J. RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW, chap. 3.
    • On the difference between hard and soft (or inclusive) positivism, see L. Green, Legal Positivism, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, available at http://plato.stanford. edu/entries/legal-positivism/. On different interpretations of the social thesis, see J. RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW (1979), chap. 3.
    • (1979) Legal Positivism, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
  • 102
    • 85022439956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Positivism, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY note 103 note 46, at
    • Murphy, Legal Positivism, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY note 103 note 46, at 391.
    • Murphy , pp. 391
  • 104
    • 85022355864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The internal quotation marks are Murphy's and do not signal a quotation from any other work. note 46, at 371. see HART, The internal quotation marks are Murphy's and do not signal a quotation from any other work. note 1, at
    • Murphy, The internal quotation marks are Murphy's and do not signal a quotation from any other work. note 46, at 371. Hart makes this claim in THE CONCEPT OF LAW; see HART, The internal quotation marks are Murphy's and do not signal a quotation from any other work. note 1, at 240.
    • Hart makes this claim in THE CONCEPT OF LAW , pp. 240
    • Murphy1
  • 108
    • 85022384462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am following Stavropoulos's interpretation of Dworkin's position in Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds note 9, secs. 1 and
    • In ascribing to Dworkin a theory about the nature of law, I am following Stavropoulos's interpretation of Dworkin's position in Stavropoulos, Interpretivist Theories of Law, Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds note 9, secs. 1 and 2.
    • ascribing to Dworkin a theory about the nature of law , pp. 2
  • 109
    • 85022363720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see DICKSON, ascribing to Dworkin a theory about the nature of law note 23, chap. 5.
    • For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue, see DICKSON, ascribing to Dworkin a theory about the nature of law note 23, chap. 5.
    • For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue
  • 110
    • 85022419500 scopus 로고
    • see P. Soper, Legal Theory and the Claim of Authority, 18 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 214 P. Soper, Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds, For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue note 110; W. WALUCHOW, For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue note 22, at 86-98. I also press this objection against Frederick Schauer in DICKSON, For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue note 23, chap. 5.
    • For versions of this objection, see P. Soper, Legal Theory and the Claim of Authority, 18 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 214 (1989); P. Soper, Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds, For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue note 110; W. WALUCHOW, For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue note 22, at 86-98. I also press this objection against Frederick Schauer in DICKSON, For further consideration of Dworkin's stance on this issue note 23, chap. 5.
    • (1989) For versions of this objection
  • 113
    • 85022449485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For versions of this objection note 46 note 1 note 1, at
    • HART, For versions of this objection note 46 note 1 note 1, at 116.
    • HART , pp. 116
  • 114
    • 85022431060 scopus 로고
    • HART note 99, and cf. D. Lyons, in RONALD DWORKIN AND CONTEMPORARY JURISPRUDENCE(Marshall Cohen, ed., ); P. Soper, Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds, HART note
    • See MacCormick, HART note 99, and cf. D. Lyons, Moral Aspects of Legal Theory, in RONALD DWORKIN AND CONTEMPORARY JURISPRUDENCE(Marshall Cohen, ed., 1984); P. Soper, Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds, HART note 110.
    • (1984) Moral Aspects of Legal Theory , pp. 110
    • MacCormick1
  • 115
    • 85022423759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The argument is intended to apply both to propositions of law and to the concept of law. note 1, at
    • HART, The argument is intended to apply both to propositions of law and to the concept of law. note 1, at 246.
    • HART , pp. 246
  • 116
    • 85022409599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. ), at
    • T.A.O. Endicott, Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting, in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. 2001), at 41.
    • (2001) Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting , pp. 41
    • Endicott, T.A.O.1
  • 117
    • 70449979726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Semantics, (J.L. Coleman, ed. 2001), at 59, but see esp. sec. B; and J. Raz, Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: a Partial Comparison, in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. ), esp. 12.
    • In N. Stavropoulos, Hart's Semantics, in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. 2001), at 59, but see esp. sec. B; and J. Raz, Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: a Partial Comparison, in HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW (J.L. Coleman, ed. 2001), esp. 12.
    • (2001) HART'S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW
    • Stavropoulos, N.1
  • 118
    • 85022423034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I mean no more than that he takes the argument to be on target. As is mentioned later in this section, Raz does not believe that the argument is successful against criterial explanations of the concept of law because in his view it is false that, as the semanticsting argument claims, such explanations cannot account adequately for disagreement about law.
    • In stating that Raz believesHart's approach to legal theory to be “stung” by the semanticsting argument, I mean no more than that he takes the argument to be on target. As is mentioned later in this section, Raz does not believe that the argument is successful against criterial explanations of the concept of law because in his view it is false that, as the semanticsting argument claims, such explanations cannot account adequately for disagreement about law.
    • stating that Raz believesHart's approach to legal theory to be “stung” by the semanticsting argument
  • 119
    • 31144474957 scopus 로고
    • stating that Raz believesHart's approach to legal theory to be “stung” by the semanticsting argument note 121, at 7. See also, e.g., J. Raz, in RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN, at 195, sec. I.
    • Raz, stating that Raz believesHart's approach to legal theory to be “stung” by the semanticsting argument note 121, at 7. See also, e.g., J. Raz, The Problem about the Nature of Law, in RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN (1994), at 195, sec. I.
    • (1994) The Problem about the Nature of Law
    • Raz1
  • 120
    • 85022360314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 31, 36, 39; HART, The Problem about the Nature of Law note 1, at
    • See, e.g., DWORKIN, The Problem about the Nature of Law note 3, at 31, 36, 39; HART, The Problem about the Nature of Law note 1, at 245-246.
    • The Problem about the Nature of Law note 3 , pp. 245-246
    • DWORKIN1
  • 121
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Problem about the Nature of Law note 3 note 121, at
    • Stavropoulos, The Problem about the Nature of Law note 3 note 121, at 73-75.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 73-75
  • 122
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos note 121, at 74-75. On this point, see also Raz, Stavropoulos note 121, at
    • Stavropoulos, Stavropoulos note 121, at 74-75. On this point, see also Raz, Stavropoulos note 121, at 16-18.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 16-18
  • 123
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos note 121, at
    • Stavropoulos, Stavropoulos note 121, at 73-79.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 73-79
  • 125
    • 85022359687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos note 121 note 121, at
    • Raz, Stavropoulos note 121 note 121, at 26.
    • Raz1
  • 127
    • 85022447106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretivism Stavropoulos note 121 note 91 note 3, chaps. 6 and
    • DWORKIN, Interpretivism Stavropoulos note 121 note 91 note 3, chaps. 6 and 7.
    • DWORKIN1
  • 128
    • 0041694283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on these points, see Stavropoulos, Interpretivism Stavropoulos note 121 note 91 note 91, part II. See also Stavropoulos, Interpretivism Stavropoulos note 121 note 91 note 121, at 81-85. This more recent work builds on Stavropoulos's attempts to argue that the concept of law is deep in the sense outlined above by drawing an analogy from the nature of natural kind concepts in N. Stavropoulos
    • For more on these points, see Stavropoulos, Interpretivism Stavropoulos note 121 note 91 note 91, part II. See also Stavropoulos, Interpretivism Stavropoulos note 121 note 91 note 121, at 81-85. This more recent work builds on Stavropoulos's attempts to argue that the concept of law is deep in the sense outlined above by drawing an analogy from the nature of natural kind concepts in N. Stavropoulos, OBJECTIVITY IN LAW (1996).
    • (1996) OBJECTIVITY IN LAW
  • 129
    • 85022434026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • OBJECTIVITY IN LAW note 121, at
    • Raz, OBJECTIVITY IN LAW note 121, at 14.
    • Raz1
  • 131
    • 85022398525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These arguments cannot be discussed here. note 3, at
    • DWORKIN, These arguments cannot be discussed here. note 3, at 44.
    • DWORKIN1
  • 132
    • 85022397382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These arguments cannot be discussed here. note 3, at
    • DWORKIN, These arguments cannot be discussed here. note 3, at 39-46.
    • DWORKIN1
  • 135
    • 0000692309 scopus 로고
    • MIND, LANGUAGE AND REALITY: PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS (Vol. 2, 1975); S. Kripke, NAMING AND NECESSITY
    • See H. Putnam, The Meaning of “Meaning,” in MIND, LANGUAGE AND REALITY: PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS 215-271 (Vol. 2, 1975); S. Kripke, NAMING AND NECESSITY (1980).
    • (1980) The Meaning of “Meaning,” , pp. 215-271
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 136
    • 85022412810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Meaning of “Meaning,” note 137, at
    • Coleman and Simchen, The Meaning of “Meaning,” note 137, at 19.
    • Coleman1    Simchen2
  • 137
    • 85022442803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Meaning of “Meaning,” note 137, at
    • Coleman and Simchen, The Meaning of “Meaning,” note 137, at 21-28.
    • Coleman1    Simchen2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.