메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 7, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 35-57

Coercion and the nature of law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 31144460914     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s1352325201071026     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (55)

References (41)
  • 12
    • 0041577670 scopus 로고
    • For example, the enforcement of civil actions at one time in Roman law. B. Nicholas
    • For example, the enforcement of civil actions at one time in Roman law. B. Nicholas, AN INTRODUCTION TO ROMAN LAW 27 (1962).
    • (1962) AN INTRODUCTION TO ROMAN LAW , pp. 27
  • 16
    • 84974403769 scopus 로고
    • it is not coercive. W.A. Edmundson, Is Law Coercive?, 1 LEGAL THEORY 81 Edmundson, The first view focuses on the coercer's intention to deliberately set back the interests of those coerced unless the latter comply: It is the purposive diminution or invasion of another's interest which must be justified, quite apart from whether the other has a right to those interests. note 15, pt. 2, especially at 82-83, 123-24. But a rights-violation approach to coercion is not committed to this. One can acknowledge that there are rights (e.g., to be free from physical interference, or to one's current holdings, or to various advantages in the future) that can be justifiably overridden in certain circumstances. An interference with one's rights will be coercive if it would constitute a violation of one's rights in the absence of those (justifying) circumstances: The coerciveness is indicated by the need for such a justification to be present. One significant objection to Edmundson's position (as he is aware) is that it becomes difficult to leave room for the distinction between justified and unjustified coercion. For his attempt to meet this issue see id. at
    • Edmundson has argued that so long as the law's use of physical force and sanctions is morally legitimate, it is not coercive. W.A. Edmundson, Is Law Coercive?, 1 LEGAL THEORY 81 (1995); Edmundson, The first view focuses on the coercer's intention to deliberately set back the interests of those coerced unless the latter comply: It is the purposive diminution or invasion of another's interest which must be justified, quite apart from whether the other has a right to those interests. note 15, pt. 2, especially at 82-83, 123-24. But a rights-violation approach to coercion is not committed to this. One can acknowledge that there are rights (e.g., to be free from physical interference, or to one's current holdings, or to various advantages in the future) that can be justifiably overridden in certain circumstances. An interference with one's rights will be coercive if it would constitute a violation of one's rights in the absence of those (justifying) circumstances: The coerciveness is indicated by the need for such a justification to be present. One significant objection to Edmundson's position (as he is aware) is that it becomes difficult to leave room for the distinction between justified and unjustified coercion. For his attempt to meet this issue see id. at 94-96.
    • (1995) Edmundson has argued that so long as the law's use of physical force and sanctions is morally legitimate , pp. 94-96
  • 17
    • 85022442446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Edmundson has argued that so long as the law's use of physical force and sanctions is morally legitimate note 6, at
    • I consider some other qualification in Lamond, Edmundson has argued that so long as the law's use of physical force and sanctions is morally legitimate note 6, at 57-60.
    • I consider some other qualification in Lamond , pp. 57-60
  • 22
    • 85022392888 scopus 로고
    • 311-38 (especially 311-19) (G. Roth & C. Wittich eds., )
    • M. Weber, ECONOMY AND SOCIETY 34-35, 311-38 (especially 311-19) (G. Roth & C. Wittich eds., 1978)
    • (1978) ECONOMY AND SOCIETY 34-35
    • Weber, M.1
  • 23
    • 85022382437 scopus 로고
    • ch.4, especially at 97-98 (1997); T. Honoré, What is a Group?, in MAKING LAW BIND
    • See B.Z. Tamanaha, REALISTIC SOCIO-LEGAL THEORY ch.4, especially at 97-98 (1997); T. Honoré, What is a Group?, in MAKING LAW BIND 68 (1987).
    • (1987) REALISTIC SOCIO-LEGAL THEORY , pp. 68
    • Tamanaha, B.Z.1
  • 26
    • 0040223973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY (D. Patterson ed., ).
    • See, e.g., B. Leiter, Legal Realism, in A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY (D. Patterson ed., 1996).
    • (1996) Legal Realism
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 28
  • 29
    • 85022428540 scopus 로고
    • Law and Force note 4, at 93; Ronald Dworkin, in ISSUES IN CONTEMPORARY LEGAL PHILOSOPHY 15 (R. Gavison ed., ).
    • Dworkin, Law and Force note 4, at 93; Ronald Dworkin, Legal Theory and the Problem of Sense, in ISSUES IN CONTEMPORARY LEGAL PHILOSOPHY 15 (R. Gavison ed., 1987).
    • (1987) Legal Theory and the Problem of Sense
    • Dworkin1
  • 32
    • 0042196478 scopus 로고
    • see T. Honoré, The Dependence of Morality on Law, 13 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 1
    • For other connections between law and morality, see T. Honoré, The Dependence of Morality on Law, 13 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 1 (1993).
    • (1993) For other connections between law and morality
  • 33
    • 85022395522 scopus 로고
    • For a more extensive discussion of possible analyses of duties-not restricted to legal duties-see P.M.S. Hacker, in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE, SECOND SERIES (A.W.B. Simpson ed., ).
    • For a more extensive discussion of possible analyses of duties-not restricted to legal duties-see P.M.S. Hacker, Sanction Theories of Duty, in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE, SECOND SERIES (A.W.B. Simpson ed., 1973).
    • (1973) Sanction Theories of Duty
  • 34
    • 85022421483 scopus 로고
    • An analogy skilfully used by Philip Soper in, for example, 50 U. CHI. L. REV. 1170, 1195-1200 (1983); Making Sense of Modern Jurisprudence 22 CREIGHTON L. REV. 67, 83-87 (1988); Legal Theory and the Claim of Authority 18 PHIL. & PUB. AFF.
    • An analogy skilfully used by Philip Soper in, for example, Legal Theory and the Problem of Definition, 50 U. CHI. L. REV. 1170, 1195-1200 (1983); Making Sense of Modern Jurisprudence 22 CREIGHTON L. REV. 67, 83-87 (1988); Legal Theory and the Claim of Authority 18 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 209, 232-36 (1989).
    • (1989) Legal Theory and the Problem of Definition , vol.209 , pp. 232-236
  • 37
    • 85022380667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance, compulsory seat belt legislation in New Zealand that was, at first, not backed up with sanctions. note 31 note 6, at
    • I discuss this more fully in Lamond, For instance, compulsory seat belt legislation in New Zealand that was, at first, not backed up with sanctions. note 31 note 6, at 57-60.
    • I discuss this more fully in Lamond , pp. 57-60
  • 38
    • 85022425373 scopus 로고
    • See K. Greenawalt, CONFLICTS OF LAW AND MORALITY ch. 4 P. Soper, Law's Normative Claims, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW 229-39 (R.P. George ed., 1996); Edmundson, I discuss this more fully in Lamond note 15, ch. 2.
    • Though this account of law's claim has been disputed. See K. Greenawalt, CONFLICTS OF LAW AND MORALITY ch. 4 (1987); P. Soper, Law's Normative Claims, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW 229-39 (R.P. George ed., 1996); Edmundson, I discuss this more fully in Lamond note 15, ch. 2.
    • (1987) Though this account of law's claim has been disputed.
  • 39
    • 0004098751 scopus 로고
    • For example, the account of the state in R. Martin
    • For example, the account of the state in R. Martin, A SYSTEM OF RIGHTS 5-8 (1993).
    • (1993) A SYSTEM OF RIGHTS , pp. 5-8


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.