메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 9, Issue 2, 2003, Pages 99-124

A defence of hart's semantics as nonambitious conceptual analysis

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 31144439353     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325203000053     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (16)

References (36)
  • 5
    • 84899341019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in HART'S POSTSCRIPTS 59-98 (Jules Coleman, ed., ). (hereinafter “HS “).
    • Nicos Stavropoulos, Hart's Semantics, in HART'S POSTSCRIPTS 59-98 (Jules Coleman, ed., 2001). (hereinafter “HS “).
    • (2001) Hart's Semantics
    • Stavropoulos, N.1
  • 6
    • 85022433997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting, in HART'S POSTSCRIPTS 39-58 (Jules Coleman, ed., ), in which the author argues that Hart did not advocate either a criterial semantic theory nor any semantic theory at all, if a semantic theory is a general explanatory account of what makes an application of an expression correct.
    • His target is Timothy Endicott's essay, Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting, in HART'S POSTSCRIPTS 39-58 (Jules Coleman, ed., 2001), in which the author argues that Hart did not advocate either a criterial semantic theory nor any semantic theory at all, if a semantic theory is a general explanatory account of what makes an application of an expression correct.
    • (2001) His target is Timothy Endicott's essay
  • 7
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HS at
    • Stavropoulos, HS at 98.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 98
  • 9
    • 84870851413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Hart, CL, at 3-4.
    • CL , pp. 3-4
    • Hart1
  • 11
    • 85008211068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He claims, however, that analytical jurisprudence theorists have ignored the criticism of the analytic-synthetic distinction. See B. Leiter, Realism, Positivism and Conceptual Analysis, in 4 LEGAL THEORY 533-547, at
    • In legal theory, Brian Leiter has argued that conceptual analysis in jurisprudence is not immune from Quine's criticism. He claims, however, that analytical jurisprudence theorists have ignored the criticism of the analytic-synthetic distinction. See B. Leiter, Realism, Positivism and Conceptual Analysis, in 4 LEGAL THEORY 533-547, at 546 (1998).
    • (1998) legal theory, Brian Leiter has argued that conceptual analysis in jurisprudence is not immune from Quine's criticism , pp. 546
  • 12
    • 0040511745 scopus 로고
    • in CLARITY IS NOT ENOUGH (H.D. Lewis, ed., 1963); Saul Kripke,NAMING ANDNECESSITY (1972); Hilary Putnam,MIND, LANGUAGE ANDREALITY
    • W. Quine Two Dogmas of Empiricism, in CLARITY IS NOT ENOUGH (H.D. Lewis, ed., 1963); Saul Kripke,NAMING ANDNECESSITY (1972); Hilary Putnam,MIND, LANGUAGE ANDREALITY (1975).
    • (1975) Two Dogmas of Empiricism
    • Quine, W.1
  • 14
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HS at
    • Stavropoulos, HS at 70.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 70
  • 16
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HS at 70-71. In this paper, thought experiments, counterfactual situations, and possible cases are taken as being interchangeable.
    • Stavropoulos, HS at 70-71. In this paper, thought experiments, counterfactual situations, and possible cases are taken as being interchangeable.
    • Stavropoulos
  • 18
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HS at
    • Stavropoulos, HS at 73.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 73
  • 21
    • 85022353327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HS at
    • Stavropoulos, HS at 72-73.
    • Stavropoulos , pp. 72-73
  • 23
  • 24
  • 25
    • 85022376963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brian Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence, 76 TEX. L. REV., My article, Genuine Disagreements: A Realist Reconstruction of Dworkin, 4 OXFORD JOURNAL OF LEGAL STUDIES (2001), resorts to naturalized epistemology to reconstruct Dworkin's legal theory in realist terms.
    • Brian Leiter uses naturalized epistemology as a methodology for jurisprudence. See Brian Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence, 76 TEX. L. REV. (1997). My article, Genuine Disagreements: A Realist Reconstruction of Dworkin, 4 OXFORD JOURNAL OF LEGAL STUDIES (2001), resorts to naturalized epistemology to reconstruct Dworkin's legal theory in realist terms.
    • (1997) Brian Leiter uses naturalized epistemology as a methodology for jurisprudence
  • 28
    • 85022410347 scopus 로고
    • (1989) gives a detailed formulation of the semantic-properties-test argument. It is a variation of Moore's open argument in PRINCIPLIA ETHICA. It is also well explained in Harman, THE NATURE OF MORALITY, AN INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS
    • David Brink, MORAL REALISM AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS 160-161 (1989) gives a detailed formulation of the semantic-properties-test argument. It is a variation of Moore's open argument in PRINCIPLIA ETHICA. It is also well explained in Harman, THE NATURE OF MORALITY, AN INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS (1977).
    • (1977) MORAL REALISM AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS 160-161
    • Brink, D.1
  • 29
    • 85022440919 scopus 로고
    • In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, xxix : 238, focuses on the importance of being neutral with respect to different theoretical views.
    • Hart in his reply to J. Cohen in “Theory and Definition in Jurisprudence,” In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, xxix (1955): 238, focuses on the importance of being neutral with respect to different theoretical views.
    • (1955) Hart in his reply to J. Cohen in “Theory and Definition in Jurisprudence,”
  • 30
    • 84936526484 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Harvard Univ. Press, ), argues that the modern turn towards an inner self, which began with St. Augustine, followed by Descartes and Locke, explains the contemporary conception of art as a form of self-expression. It is arguable, therefore, that “art” is not a neutral concept but that its definition depends on the conception or theoretical framework presupposed by the theorist. Therefore the concept “art” or “morality” is the result of fragmented conceptual frameworks. Nowadays this latter radical assertion is seen as a commonplace in philosophical discussions.
    • Charles Taylor in THE SOURCES OF THE SELF (Cambridge, Harvard Univ. Press, 1989), argues that the modern turn towards an inner self, which began with St. Augustine, followed by Descartes and Locke, explains the contemporary conception of art as a form of self-expression. It is arguable, therefore, that “art” is not a neutral concept but that its definition depends on the conception or theoretical framework presupposed by the theorist. Therefore the concept “art” or “morality” is the result of fragmented conceptual frameworks. Nowadays this latter radical assertion is seen as a commonplace in philosophical discussions.
    • (1989) Charles Taylor in THE SOURCES OF THE SELF
  • 34
  • 36


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.