메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 25, Issue 1, 2004, Pages 61-74

The double life of double effect

Author keywords

Double effect; Incidental harming; Instrumental harming; Palliative care; Terminal sedation

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; COURT; DEATH; HUMAN; LIFESPAN; MEDICAL ETHICS; MEDICAL PRACTICE; PALLIATIVE THERAPY; PHYSICIAN; SEDATION; UNITED STATES; ANALYTICAL APPROACH; DEATH AND EUTHANASIA; ETHICS; EUTHANASIA; INTRACTABLE PAIN; JURISPRUDENCE; LEGAL APPROACH; LEGAL ASPECT; TERMINAL CARE; VACCO V. QUILL;

EID: 3042676372     PISSN: 13867415     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/B:META.0000025095.73394.34     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (27)
  • 1
    • 4344682706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Respondents were three physicians who practice in New York Timothy E. Quill, Samuel C. Klagsbrun, and Howard A. Grossman, Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief accessed August
    • The Respondents were three physicians who practice in New York: Timothy E. Quill, Samuel C. Klagsbrun, and Howard A. Grossman, Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief, http://www.compassionindying.org/legal.cidbref1.html pp. 1-31, accessed August 23, 2003.
    • (2003) , vol.23 , pp. 1-31
  • 2
    • 4344649859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • S. Ct. 793 (1997).
    • (1997)
  • 3
    • 4344710567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief, p. 1.
    • , Issue.1
  • 4
    • 4344717010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief, p. 1.
  • 5
    • 4344595723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief, p. 1.
  • 6
    • 4344619931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief, p. 3.
  • 7
    • 4344679066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief
    • Vacco v. Quill Respondents' Brief, p. 3.
  • 8
    • 4344628607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 800.
    • (1997) , pp. 800
  • 9
    • 4344708104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 801.
    • (1997) , pp. 801
  • 10
    • 4344583994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 citation to testimony of Dr. Leon Kass omitted
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), pp. 801-802, citation to testimony of Dr. Leon Kass omitted.
    • (1997) , pp. 801-802
  • 11
    • 4344567087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 citation to testimony of Dr. Leon Kass omitted
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 802, citation to testimony of Dr. Leon Kass omitted.
    • (1997) , pp. 802
  • 12
    • 4344663014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 802.
    • (1997) , pp. 802
  • 13
    • 4344590709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), pp. 802-803.
    • (1997) , pp. 802-803
  • 14
    • 4344631711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), pp. 750-751.
    • (1997) , pp. 750-751
  • 15
    • 4344585403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 751.
    • (1997) , pp. 751
  • 16
    • 4344661114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 751.
    • (1997) , pp. 751
  • 17
    • 4344582189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), n. 11, p. 807.
    • (1997) , Issue.11 , pp. 807
  • 18
    • 4344658346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), n. 12, p. 808.
    • (1997) , Issue.12 , pp. 808
  • 19
    • 4344690734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), pp. 791-792.
    • (1997) , pp. 791-792
  • 20
    • 4344647022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 792.
    • (1997) , pp. 792
  • 21
    • 4344589981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), pp. 736-737.
    • (1997) , pp. 736-737
  • 22
    • 4344622517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 S. Ct. 793
    • 521 S. Ct. 793 (1997), p. 737.
    • (1997) , pp. 737
  • 23
    • 0024732716 scopus 로고
    • "Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect"
    • Warren Quinn presents such a version of DE in at 335
    • Warren Quinn presents such a version of DE in "Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect," Philosophy & Public Affairs 18 (1989): 334-351, at 335.
    • (1989) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.18 , pp. 334-351
  • 24
    • 4344594260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • St. Thomas Aquinas imposes this constraint on the justification for killing an assailant in self-defense: "an act may be rendered unlawful, if it be out of proportion to the end. Wherefore if a man, in self-defense, uses more than necessary violence, it will be unlawful" Summa Theologica II-II, qu. 64, art. 7, "Of Killing"
    • St. Thomas Aquinas imposes this constraint on the justification for killing an assailant in self-defense: "an act may be rendered unlawful, if it be out of proportion to the end. Wherefore if a man, in self-defense, uses more than necessary violence, it will be unlawful" Summa Theologica II-II, qu. 64, art. 7, "Of Killing".
  • 25
    • 4344634751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Traditionally, DE is cited to explain why terror bombing, which aims to kill civilians as a means of demoralizing and weakening the enemy in order to win the war is not justified, while strategic bombing, which also kills civilians, perhaps even the same number of civilians, but as a side effect of striking military targets may be justified. If the terror bomber could say: "I really intended only to demoralize the enemy and persuade them to surrender, if I could have brought that about without actually killing so many people I would have. I certainly would not have adopted alternative means to kill civilians if I had terrorized but failed to kill them" and if this were taken to be an application of DE, then DE would not only not prohibit his action, it would justify it!
    • Traditionally, DE is cited to explain why terror bombing, which aims to kill civilians as a means of demoralizing and weakening the enemy in order to win the war is not justified, while strategic bombing, which also kills civilians, perhaps even the same number of civilians, but as a side effect of striking military targets may be justified. If the terror bomber could say: "I really intended only to demoralize the enemy and persuade them to surrender, if I could have brought that about without actually killing so many people I would have. I certainly would not have adopted alternative means to kill civilians if I had terrorized but failed to kill them" and if this were taken to be an application of DE, then DE would not only not prohibit his action, it would justify it!
  • 26
    • 0005014689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Doing Away with Double Effect"
    • This strange state of affairs, one in which DE is cited to justify practices that traditional versions of DE must condemn, is not restricted to debates about palliative care. There is a similar duality in the other traditional applications of DE. To many people, DE's supposed permissions have always seemed more plausible and compelling than DE's supposed prohibitions, and these prohibitions have always been hard to reconcile with what DE has supposedly permitted. Most egregious in this respect is the justification provided for actions like killing an assailant in self-defense and sacrificing one's life heroically to save others. These seem to be clear cases in which causing a morally grave effect as part of a means to a good end is permissible because the action causing the morally grave regretted effect is aimed at only instrumentally. I argue for this view at greater length in my
    • This strange state of affairs, one in which DE is cited to justify practices that traditional versions of DE must condemn, is not restricted to debates about palliative care. There is a similar duality in the other traditional applications of DE. To many people, DE's supposed permissions have always seemed more plausible and compelling than DE's supposed prohibitions, and these prohibitions have always been hard to reconcile with what DE has supposedly permitted. Most egregious in this respect is the justification provided for actions like killing an assailant in self-defense and sacrificing one's life heroically to save others. These seem to be clear cases in which causing a morally grave effect as part of a means to a good end is permissible because the action causing the morally grave regretted effect is aimed at only instrumentally. I argue for this view at greater length in my "Doing Away with Double Effect," Ethics 111 (2001): 219-255.
    • (2001) Ethics , vol.111 , pp. 219-255
  • 27
    • 4344660478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Terminal Killing, Mercy Sedation"
    • Consider these candid reflections of a palliative care physician regarding a patient who moaned for seventeen hours after the initiation of terminal sedation "by following the established guidelines for pain and suffering medication titration, the end of life seemed to be inexorably and senselessly delayed." 26, cf. 1
    • Consider these candid reflections of a palliative care physician regarding a patient who moaned for seventeen hours after the initiation of terminal sedation "by following the established guidelines for pain and suffering medication titration, the end of life seemed to be inexorably and senselessly delayed." Mark J. Lema "Terminal Killing, Mercy Sedation," American Society of Anesthesiologists Newsletter 64, (2000) 8: 26, cf. 1.
    • (2000) American Society of Anesthesiologists Newsletter , vol.64 , pp. 8
    • Lema, M.J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.