메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 5, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 1-20

Only one cheer for Sokal and Bricmont: Or, scientism is no response to relativism

Author keywords

Bricmont; Epistemic relativism; Intellectual impostures; Philosophy of science; Relativism; Science; Sokal; Two cultures

Indexed keywords


EID: 27944471239     PISSN: 13564765     EISSN: 15728692     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/a:1009609519077     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (2)

References (61)
  • 2
    • 85080705340 scopus 로고
    • Rationality/Science
    • Chomsky is referring to a remark by another contributor to the Z Papers debate, hence the scare quotes
    • Noam Chomsky (1992-3), 'Rationality/Science' in Z Papers Special Issue, http://www.zmag.org/zmag/articles/chompomoart. html, p. 5: Chomsky is referring to a remark by another contributor to the Z Papers debate, hence the scare quotes.
    • (1992) Z Papers Special Issue , pp. 5
    • Chomsky, N.1
  • 3
    • 85080682425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chomsky describes his piece on postmodernism as a "personal quest for help". After the passage quoted, he continues, "... no one seems to be able to explain to me why the latest post-this-and-that is not (for the most part) truism, error, or gibberish, and I do not know how to proceed. Perhaps the explanation lies in some personal inadequacy, like tonedeafness". Chomsky, Z Papers Special Issue op. cit., 5-6.1 sympathise. However, perhaps I should add that, where I do discuss postmodernism, I take what I say to apply to typical or standard cases. There are always exceptions. If Foucault counts as a postmodernist then his Discipline and Punish is one.
    • Z Papers Special Issue , pp. 5-6
    • Chomsky1
  • 4
    • 84917299385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • spring/summer
    • Social Text 46/7 (spring/summer 1996), 217-52. The article is reprinted as an appendix to Sokal and Bricmont, 199-240. They give a brief account of the 'affair' in their Introduction: 1 ff.
    • (1996) Social Text , vol.46 , Issue.7 , pp. 217-252
  • 5
    • 85080635678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We are in his [Sokal's] debt
    • Lewis Wolpert
    • Some of the overstatements with which its publication was greeted by the press are reproduced on the back cover. Examples are, "We are in his [Sokal's] debt" (Lewis Wolpert, Independent on Sunday),
    • Independent on Sunday
  • 6
    • 85080675794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont have dared to say what no one else would
    • Jon Henley
    • and "Sokal and Bricmont have dared to say what no one else would" (Jon Henley, Guardian).
    • Guardian
  • 7
    • 85080781340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, ix-x.
    • Sokal and Bricmont, ix-x.
  • 8
  • 9
    • 0004279625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Viking
    • Well, perhaps I should give just one example. Consider, then, how the sociobiologist Matt Ridley fatuously credits John Rawls with the neglect of an 'evolutionary perspective'. According to Ridley, Rawls could have learnt from recent studies of "how the complex societies of monkeys and apes work" (Wow!): Matt Ridley, The Origins of Virtue (Harmondsworth: Viking, 1996), 156.
    • (1996) The Origins of Virtue , pp. 156
    • Ridley, M.1
  • 10
    • 85080683490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not quite the way Sokal and Bricmont themselves define "relativism". According to them, it is "any philosophy that claims that the truth or falisty of a statement is relative to an individual or a social group" -51. Still, I am not too worried because most versions of relativism they attack don't match their own definition either.
  • 11
    • 85080749756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There is a fairly clear parallel with language here. Just as the sounds can be heard only as music, as a contrapuntal sequence, and as resolved by a major chord, by inheritors of a certain musical tradition, so Japanese writing can be seen as forming words only by someone who knows Japanese. Anyone else will only see marks on a page. To this, Bob Brecher has responded by pointing out that descriptions of the music as contrapuntal, or the writing as Japanese words, can be recognised as true by someone 'for' whom they are not true. (One person can say of another, "He hears those noises as music", or "She sees those marks as words".) Of course, Brecher is right, but what is the implication for the version of cultural relativism at issue here? A defender of that relativism could respond that Brecher has noticed something which is only to be expected, and which results from the fact that any realistic definition of "culture" must recognise that a culture is not a hermetically sealed entity, so that the inheritor of one culture can learn to understand another, and so on. If so, is relativism really undermined? There is clearly room for discussion here, but nothing which need detain us at present, for I am not out to defend cultural relativism beyond suggesting that it can have a certain prima facie plausibility.
  • 12
    • 85080795234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 52
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 52.
  • 15
    • 0001817653 scopus 로고
    • Relativism, Rationalism, and the Sociology of Knowledge
    • Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes, eds., Oxford: Blackwell
    • Of course, each of these writers gives a different account of what it is for a description to 'work', but it is unnecessary to consider these differences here. Sokal and Bricmont also criticise Barnes's and Bloor's "strong programme" for the sociology of knowledge. For this, see Barry Barnes and David Bloor, "Relativism, Rationalism, and the Sociology of Knowledge", in Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes, eds., Rationality and Relativism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981). Apparently, Barnes and Bloor hold that "there is no sense attached to the idea that some standards or beliefs are really rational as distinct from merely locally accepted as such" (ibid., 27). This does not strike me as a position I would want to defend.
    • (1981) Rationality and Relativism
    • Barnes, B.1    Bloor, D.2
  • 18
    • 0004187130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Verso, [1975]
    • See Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (London: Verso, 1978 [1975]). Feyerabend writes, for example, that "there are circumstances when it is advisable to introduce, elaborate, and defend ad hoc hypotheses, or hypotheses which contradict well-established and generally accepted experimental results, or hypotheses whose content is smaller than the content of the existing and empirically adequate alternative, or self-inconsistent hypotheses, and so on": 23-4.
    • (1978) Against Method
    • Feyerabend, P.1
  • 19
    • 85080700066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 51
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 51.
  • 20
    • 0004187130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Method Ibid., 58. I'm glad Sokal decided to become a physicist and not a lawyer. What he calls having proven beyond reasonable doubt is what I would call having circumstantial evidence.
    • Against Method , pp. 58
  • 21
    • 0004187130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Method Ibid., 61. Of course, however successful at generating predictions a theory may be, it doesn't follow that there can't be equally successful competing theories.
    • Against Method , pp. 61
  • 22
    • 85080640355 scopus 로고
    • Private Thoughts
    • Elizabeth Anscombe and Peter Geach, eds., London: Nelson
    • See René Descartes (1619), Private Thoughts, in Elizabeth Anscombe and Peter Geach, eds., Descartes: Philosophical Writings (London: Nelson, 1954), p. 3.
    • (1619) Descartes: Philosophical Writings , pp. 3
    • Descartes, R.1
  • 23
    • 85080681216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The status of possibility (ii) is ambivalent. It depends what else you believe. If you believe (i) you will see it as representing the possibility of there being tentative explanations which await final confirmation or refutation. On the other hand, if you believe (iii) and/or (iv) you will see it as representing an unsurprising cosequence of incommensurability.
  • 24
    • 0043123247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • September 21 Letters page
    • The Guardian, September 21 1998, Letters page.
    • (1998) The Guardian
  • 25
    • 85080788001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Invoking the naturalistic fallacy isn't much help here. If the responsibility for our actions is borne by our selves, not our genes, it is incumbent on sociobiology to explain how come. For examples of this move see Ridley, The Guardian op. cit., 253ff
    • The Guardian
    • Ridley1
  • 26
    • 0004270927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin
    • and Pinker, How the Mind Works (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1997), 50ff.
    • (1997) How the Mind Works
    • Pinker1
  • 27
    • 85080642660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 178
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 178.
  • 28
    • 85080790757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, my earlier discussion of the truth of "the grass is green", etcetera, suggests that they won't. If I am right, it is always possible that there will arise new categories of proposition whose truth is relative to different entities.
  • 29
    • 85080674404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Sokal and Bricmont take pains to stress that there are "canons of rationality that are or (should be) common to all scholarly disciplines" (6) and that they can appeal to these, ".. .even though neither of us holds a diploma in philosophy" (51). I think they are right, and I assume they would extend a similar courtesy to me.
  • 30
    • 53149086204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How the Mind Works Ibid., 56-7. It may be relevant to mention here that Sokal and Bricmont are making the point that, in their opinion, the principles of good methodological practice cannot be codified in a definitive way.
    • How the Mind Works , pp. 56-57
  • 31
    • 85080765484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I skirt around any difficulties which may be raised by positivism or the possibility of Cartesian scepticism here
    • I skirt around any difficulties which may be raised by positivism or the possibility of Cartesian scepticism here.
  • 33
    • 85080725579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 95
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 95.
  • 34
    • 0003855402 scopus 로고
    • London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson
    • For another example, see Richard Dawkins, River Out of Eden (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1995), 31-2. Dawkins writes, "Show me a cultural relativist and I'll show you a hypocrite. Airplanes built according to scientific principles work ... Airplanes built to tribal or mythological specifications, such as the dummy planes of the cargo cults in jungle clearings or the beeswaxed wings of Icarus, don't."
    • (1995) River out of Eden , pp. 31-32
    • Dawkins, R.1
  • 35
    • 0007320290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • For my comments on this see my Free Speech (London: Routledge, 1998), 99ff.
    • (1998) Free Speech
  • 36
    • 84895046371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • According to Rorty, truth, being a property of descriptions and not of the world, "cannot be out there": Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 5. Of course, truth is such a property, but then - maybe - it is a property of descriptions in the way that being a left hand is a property of some hands; that is, in a way which depends on its relation to something independent of and beyond the thing itself.
    • Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity , pp. 5
  • 37
    • 85080646545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 30
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 30.
  • 39
    • 0003967815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So, I don't accept the (postmodernistic) position for which Rorty argues in Contingency, Irony, Solidarity, according to which intellectual change is a question of the persuasion of some by others through a process of description and re-description. This places reason on a level with other forms of persuasion.
    • Contingency, Irony, Solidarity
  • 40
    • 3042821543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit.
    • On this, see my Free Speech, op. cit., 104-13.
    • Free Speech , pp. 104-113
  • 41
    • 85080759882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 73: shades of J.S. Mill
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 73: shades of J.S. Mill!!
  • 42
    • 0010794348 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin
    • I suppose Sokal and Bricmont's account roughly characterises the way a historian might try to determine whether, say, the Battle of Hastings took place on a Thursday or a Friday, or the number of men in William's army. But it couldn't possibly do justice to, say, Simon Schama's brilliant discussion of the cultural and historical significiance of Louis David's Death of Marat. For this, see Simon Schama, Citizens (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1989), 742ff.
    • (1989) Citizens
    • Schama, S.1
  • 43
    • 85080647453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 180-81
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 180-81.
  • 44
    • 79954709565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizens Ibid., 177.
    • Citizens , pp. 177
  • 45
    • 79954709565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizens Ibid., 54.
    • Citizens , pp. 54
  • 46
    • 79954709565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizens Ibid., 34.
    • Citizens , pp. 34
  • 47
    • 79954709565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizens Ibid., 59.
    • Citizens , pp. 59
  • 48
    • 79954709565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizens Ibid., 65.
    • Citizens , pp. 65
  • 49
    • 0004152379 scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 174ff. Harmondsworth: Penguin, chapter 12
    • For their discussion of the "two cultures" debate, see Sokal and Bricmont, 174ff. For Eysenck on psychoanalysis, see H.J. Eysenck, Uses and Abuses of Psychology (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1953), chapter 12, 221-41.
    • (1953) Uses and Abuses of Psychology , pp. 221-241
    • Eysenck, H.J.1
  • 50
    • 85080776217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin, [1959]
    • R.D. Laing, The Divided Se//(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1960 [1959]), 31. According to Laing, Freud would often draw the same analogy.
    • (1960) The Divided Se// , pp. 31
    • Laing, R.D.1
  • 52
    • 33645619360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why God Plays Dice
    • August 22
    • Mark Buchanan, "Why God Plays Dice", New Scientist, August 22 1998, 27.
    • (1998) New Scientist , pp. 27
    • Buchanan, M.1
  • 53
    • 85080686951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 51
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 51.
  • 57
    • 85080679646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the preface to Kuhn, op. cit., vff
    • See the preface to Kuhn, op. cit., vff.
  • 58
    • 85080645977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 196
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 196.
  • 59
    • 85080675742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I think all readers of Res Publica will be able to think of relativist thinkers whose ideas have influenced the twentieth century Zeitgeist. My own list would include, at least, Einstein, the postmodernists and Wittgenstein.
  • 60
    • 85080772454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 50-51
    • Sokal and Bricmont, 50-51.
  • 61
    • 85080706343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I should like to thank Bob Brecher for his useful comments on an earlier version of this piece
    • I should like to thank Bob Brecher for his useful comments on an earlier version of this piece.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.