메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 25, Issue 3, 2005, Pages 393-417

Taking disagreement seriously: Courts, legislatures and the reform of tort law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 27744559660     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqi021     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (29)

References (83)
  • 1
    • 1642530039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Commonwealth of Australia, (Canberra, September) (hereafter referred to as 'Review'). Declaration of interest: the author was a member of the review panel
    • Commonwealth of Australia, Review of the Law of Negligence (Canberra, September 2002) (hereafter referred to as 'Review'). Declaration of interest: The author was a member of the review panel.
    • (2002) Review of the Law of Negligence
  • 2
    • 27544449332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Reforming Tort Law in Australia'
    • For a discussion see
    • For a discussion see P. Cane, 'Reforming Tort Law in Australia' (2003) 27 Melbourne ULR 649.
    • (2003) Melbourne ULR , vol.27 , pp. 649
    • Cane, P.1
  • 3
    • 84963693209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Is Mrs Donoghue's Snail in Mortal Peril?
    • The Hon Justice Peter Underwood
    • The Hon Justice Peter Underwood, 'Is Mrs Donoghue's Snail in Mortal Peril? (2004) 12 Torts LJ 39.
    • (2004) Torts LJ , vol.12 , pp. 39
  • 4
    • 0039292373 scopus 로고
    • 'Common Law and Legislation'
    • The basic arguments are old. See, e.g. at
    • The basic arguments are old. See, e.g. R. Pound, 'Common Law and Legislation' (1908) 21 Harvard L Rev 383 at 404.
    • (1908) Harvard L. Rev. , vol.21 , pp. 383-404
    • Pound, R.1
  • 5
    • 27744576893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2000] 2 AC 59.
    • (2000) AC , vol.2 , pp. 59
  • 6
    • 27744515576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2002] QB 226.
    • (2002) QB , pp. 226
  • 7
    • 33645832273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [2004] 1 AC 309.
    • (2004) AC , vol.1 , pp. 309
  • 8
    • 27744514329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cattanach v Melchior
    • The decision has been partially reversed by legislation in New South Wales (Civil Liability Act 2002 ss 70, 71) and Queensland (Civil Liability Act 2003, as 49A, 49B)
    • Cattanach v Melchior (2003) 215 CLR 1. The decision has been partially reversed by legislation in New South Wales (Civil Liability Act 2002, ss 70, 71) and Queensland (Civil Liability Act 2003, as 49A, 49B).
    • (2003) CLR , vol.215 , pp. 1
  • 9
    • 27744509131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harriton v Stephens
    • Harriton v Stephens (2004) NSWLR 694.
    • (2004) NSWLR , pp. 694
  • 10
    • 27744597142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Since the High Court is not bound by its own decisions or those of any other court, as used by Kirby J this term must refer to something like 'a consensus of relevant judicial opinion as reflected in published reasons for decision'.
  • 11
    • 27744514329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at [70]-[75]
    • (2003) 215 CLR 1 at [70]-[75].
    • (2003) CLR , vol.215 , pp. 1
  • 12
    • 84891273879 scopus 로고
    • 'The Ratio of the Ratio Decidendi'
    • J. Stone, 'The Ratio of the Ratio Decidendi' (1959) 22 MLR 597.
    • (1959) MLR , vol.22 , pp. 597
    • Stone, J.1
  • 13
    • 18444373958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Melody and Law's Mindfulness of Time'
    • Concerning legal melody see
    • Concerning legal melody see G.J. Postema, 'Melody and Law's Mindfulness of Time' (2004) 17 Ratio Juris 203.
    • (2004) Ratio Juris , vol.17 , pp. 203
    • Postema, G.J.1
  • 14
    • 27744475105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law'
    • See the Hon Justice
    • See the Hon Justice Dyson Heydon, 'Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law' (2004) 10 Otago LR 493.
    • (2004) Otago LR , vol.10 , pp. 493
    • Dyson, H.1
  • 15
    • 0344720325 scopus 로고
    • 'Common Law and Statute Law'
    • For a classic discussion see
    • For a classic discussion see P.S. Atiyah, 'Common Law and Statute Law' (1985) 48 MLR 1.
    • (1985) MLR , vol.48 , pp. 1
    • Atiyah, P.S.1
  • 16
    • 27744576893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McFarlane v Tayside Health Board
    • McFarlane v Tayside Health Board (2000) 2 AC 59, 82
    • (2000) AC , vol.2 , pp. 59-82
  • 17
    • 1142309223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Misconceptions about Wrongful Conception'
    • criticized, e.g. by
    • criticized, e.g. by L.C.H Hoyano, 'Misconceptions about Wrongful Conception' (2002) 65 MLR 883.
    • (2002) MLR , vol.65 , pp. 883
    • Hoyano, L.C.H.1
  • 18
    • 27744594443 scopus 로고
    • 'Conventional Morality and Judicial Standards'
    • For a useful catalogue see 339
    • For a useful catalogue see W. Sadurski, 'Conventional Morality and Judicial Standards', 73 Virginia LR 339, 351-54 (1989).
    • (1989) Virginia LR , vol.73 , pp. 351-354
    • Sadurski, W.1
  • 19
    • 84934562843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a careful statement of such an approach see (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press) esp. 14-26, From my perspective, Eisenberg does not take disagreement seriously enough
    • For a careful statement of such an approach see M.A. Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1988), esp. 14-26, 149-53. From my perspective, Eisenberg does not take disagreement seriously enough.
    • (1988) The Nature of the Common Law , pp. 149-153
    • Eisenberg, M.A.1
  • 20
    • 27744509131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2004) 59 NSWLR 694.
    • (2004) NSWLR , vol.59 , pp. 694
  • 21
    • 27744548970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at [24].
    • (2004) NSWLR , vol.59 , pp. 24
  • 22
    • 84934562843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, as Eisenberg argues, application of a common law rule by a judge who has formal power to develop or change it involves a (typically implicit) reaffirmation of the arguments that supported adoption of the rule: see (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press) esp. 14-26, From my perspective, Eisenberg does not take disagreement n 17 above, esp. 75-76, 151-54. note
    • Similarly, as Eisenberg argues, application of a common law rule by a judge who has formal power to develop or change it involves a (typically implicit) reaffirmation of the arguments that supported adoption of the rule: See Eisenberg, n 17 above, esp. 75-76, 151-54. In the common law, the content and justification of rules are inextricably intertwined. It is only by giving the formulation of a rule canonical status that this link can be broken. This characteristic of the common law explains the sense in which it is based on reason(ing), and why judges have an obligation to give reasons for their decisions.
    • (1988) The Nature of the Common Law , pp. 149-153
    • Eisenberg, M.A.1
  • 26
    • 27744514666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cattanach v Melchior
    • at 1 at See also [82]-[83]
    • Cattanach v Melchior at (2003) 215 CLR 1 at [74]. See also [82]-[83].
    • (2003) CLR , vol.215 , pp. 74
  • 27
    • 27744460375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As opposed to 'theoretical reasons' which are reasons, for belief
    • As opposed to 'theoretical reasons' which are reasons, for belief.
  • 28
    • 27744563208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Legality of Law'
    • The word 'norm' is sometimes used to refer to court orders as well as to the common law and statutory rules and principles that support them: e.g. 1 will distinguish between them and refer only to the latter as 'norms'
    • The word 'norm' is sometimes used to refer to court orders as well as to the common law and statutory rules and principles that support them: e.g. J. Gardner, 'The Legality of Law' (2004) 17 Ratio Juris 168. 1 will distinguish between them and refer only to the latter as 'norms'.
    • (2004) Ratio Juris , vol.17 , pp. 168
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 29
    • 27744587953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rule designating the side of the road on which to drive is a classic example
    • The rule designating the side of the road on which to drive is a classic example.
  • 30
    • 27744564261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not mean to imply by the word 'exist' any particular view about the nature of values, such as 'realism' as opposed to 'emotivism'. All I mean by saying that a norm exists outside the law is that there are people for whom it provides a reason for action regardless of whether it is a legal norm.
  • 31
    • 27744489821 scopus 로고
    • 'The Past and the Future of Judge-Made Law'
    • For a richly suggestive historical reflection on this theme see
    • For a richly suggestive historical reflection on this theme see S.F.C. Milsom, 'The Past and the Future of Judge-Made Law' (1981) 8 Monash LR 1.
    • (1981) Monash LR , vol.8 , pp. 1
    • Milsom, S.F.C.1
  • 32
    • 27744492301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Law is coercive but also, from a different perspective, it regulates the use of coercion ('self-help'). From this latter perspective, although legal coercion certainly needs to be justified, the very fact that its use is regulated by legal norms provides part of the justification, given the alternative of unregulated, extra-legal, 'private' coercion.
  • 33
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • In the philosophy of St Thomas Aquinas, 'determinatio' refers to the process of giving concrete content to abstract values: (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • In the philosophy of St Thomas Aquinas, 'determinatio' refers to the process of giving concrete content to abstract values: J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 284-89.
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 284-289
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 34
    • 27744607286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Law and Content-Independent Reasons'
    • Note that the concept of content-independence I am using is different from that discussed by
    • Note that the concept of content-independence I am using is different from that discussed by P. Markwick, 'Law and Content-Independent Reasons' (2000) 20 OJLS 579.
    • (2000) OJLS , vol.20 , pp. 579
    • Markwick, P.1
  • 35
    • 0042196478 scopus 로고
    • 'The Dependence of Morality on Law'
    • T. Honoré, 'The Dependence of Morality on Law' (1993) 13 OJLS 1.
    • (1993) OJLS , vol.13 , pp. 1
    • Honoré, T.1
  • 36
    • 0003880778 scopus 로고
    • There is certainly a theoretical argument for concluding that without dispute-resolving institutions, there can be no legal system: (Oxford: Clarendon Press) ch 6
    • There is certainly a theoretical argument for concluding that without dispute-resolving institutions, there can be no legal system: J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), ch 6.
    • (1979) The Authority of Law
    • Raz, J.1
  • 37
    • 27744594665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I use both of these terms broadly and generically to signify adjudicative bodies that have the power to legalize norms. Not all adjudicators recognized by the legal system have this power.
  • 38
    • 0013508044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The historical story is complicated, of course: (London: Butterworths, 4th edn)
    • The historical story is complicated, of course: J.H. Baker, An Introduction to English Legal History (London: Butterworths, 4th edn, 2002), 196-201
    • (2002) An Introduction to English Legal History , pp. 196-201
    • Baker, J.H.1
  • 39
    • 27744578330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Columbia University Press) ch 1 (and see 75 for the suggestion that legislation rides on the back of the common law)
    • S.F.C Milson, A Natural History of the Common Law (New York: Columbia University Press, 2003), ch 1 (and see 75 for the suggestion that legislation rides on the back of the common law).
    • (2003) A Natural History of the Common Law
    • Milson, S.F.C.1
  • 40
    • 27744440575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'What Are Appeal Courts For?
    • See also Lord of Earlsferry, 517
    • See also Lord Rodger of Earlsferry, 'What Are Appeal Courts For? (2004) 10 Otago LR 517, 517-19.
    • (2004) Otago LR , vol.10 , pp. 517-519
    • Rodger1
  • 41
    • 4043121443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law'
    • On the relationship between consistency (i.e. norm-governed behaviour) and 'formal' justice see
    • On the relationship between consistency (i.e. norm-governed behaviour) and 'formal' justice see J. Gardner, 'The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law' (2000) 53 Current Legal Problems 1.
    • (2000) Current Legal Problems , vol.53 , pp. 1
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 42
    • 27744514328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Witness the debate in US administrative law about the choice that regulatory agencies have between adjudicative and legislative law-making: (Durham, NC: Durham Academic Press 2nd edn)
    • Witness the debate in US administrative law about the choice that regulatory agencies have between adjudicative and legislative law-making: P.L. Strauss, Administrative Justice in the United States (Durham, NC: Durham Academic Press, 2nd edn, 2002), 258-62.
    • (2002) Administrative Justice in the United States , pp. 258-262
    • Strauss, P.L.1
  • 43
    • 21544480325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The European Court of Justice'
    • A good modern illustration is provided by the work of the European Court of Justice over the past 40 years or so in developing the main features of EC law. See, e.g. P. Craig and G. de Búrca (eds), (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • A good modern illustration is provided by the work of the European Court of Justice over the past 40 years or so in developing the main features of EC law. See, e.g. M Shapiro, 'The European Court of Justice' in P. Craig and G. de Búrca (eds), The Evolution of EU Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) The Evolution of EU Law
    • Shapiro, M.1
  • 45
    • 0013508044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Concerning the historical development of legislation and of the functional differentiation of the legislature and the courts The historical story is complicated, of course: (London: Butterworths, 4th edn)
    • Concerning the historical development of legislation and of the functional differentiation of the legislature and the courts see Baker, above n 34 at 204-17.
    • (2002) An Introduction to English Legal History , pp. 204-217
    • Baker, J.H.1
  • 46
    • 0003084474 scopus 로고
    • 'The Forms and Limits of Adjudication'
    • The classic exposition is
    • The classic exposition is L.L. Fuller 'The Forms and Limits of Adjudication' 92 Harvard L Rev 393 (1978).
    • (1978) Harvard L Rev. , vol.92 , pp. 393
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 47
    • 10844234533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Hart Publishing) note
    • P. Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2002), 165-67. Premise-driven voting is more likely than conclusion-driven voting to produce coherence and consistency over time. This explains the importance of the principle of stare decisis and the concept of the ratio decidendi, the effect of which is to apply the principle of majority-voting to premises: Even the reasoning of judges who dissent from the majority's conclusion may contribute to the majority premises - the ratio decidendi. Voting in legislative assemblies is also conclusion driven. Whereas the particular dispute before the court provides the focus for judicial voting, the canonical words of the statute provide the focus for legislative voting. This explains why court orders and decisions are canonically formulated whereas the reasons for those decisions are not, any more than are the reasons for the enactment of statutes.
    • (2002) Responsibility in Law and Morality , pp. 165-167
    • Cane, P.1
  • 48
    • 27744544406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Conduct is either legal or illegal: Legality is not a matter of degree.
  • 49
    • 27744561768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The lack of discipline in the statement of the reasons and reasoning supporting legislation provides one of the strongest arguments against interpreting legislation by reference to parliamentary debates and other travaux preparatoires.
  • 50
    • 27744500937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not to say that there cannot be too much collegiality. The modus operandi of the U.S. Supreme Court puts a premium on building coalitions in favour of particular outcomes; and this may be inimical to consistent and coherent development of the law. It may be easier for individual judges than for groups of judges to tell a consistent and coherent story to support their voting decisions in individual cases over time. The fact that the nine-member US court invariably sits en banc may aggravate the problem. The seven-member Australian High Court increasingly sits en banc, but the strongly individualistic ethos of its members and its non-collegial mode of operation tend to produce the problems outlined in the text. The UK House of Lords sits in shifting panels of roughly half its total membership. This may make it easier for its judges to find a safe passage between the Scylla of excessive individualism and the Charybdis of excessive collegiality (I am very grateful to Adrienne Stone for stimulating this fruitful line of thought).
  • 51
    • 84934562843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note. at (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1988), esp. 14-26, 149-53. From my perspective, Eisenberg does not take disagreement seriously enough
    • This point must not be taken too far. Law in general and the common law in particular is always more-or-less uncertain. Contrary to what judges sometimes say, (moderate) uncertainty in the law does not make planning impossible any more than does (moderate) uncertainty in life generally: Eisenberg, above n 17 at 157-58.
    • The Nature of the Common Law , pp. 157-158
    • Eisenberg, M.A.1
  • 52
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an account of 'deliberative democracy' that takes disagreement seriously see (Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press)
    • For an account of 'deliberative democracy' that takes disagreement seriously see A. Gutmann and D. Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Democracy and Disagreement
    • Gutmann, A.1    Thompson, D.2
  • 53
    • 85189999209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'What is Parliament For?'
    • N. Bamforth and P. Leyland (eds), (Oxford: Hart Publishing) Jeremy Waldron, who is searching for the 'dignity of legislation' in the activities of legislative assemblies - especially majority voting (Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Part I; The Dignity of Legislation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)), seems to me to be looking in the wrong place, at least so far as Westminster systems are concerned
    • A. Tomkins, 'What is Parliament For?' in N. Bamforth and P. Leyland (eds), Public Law in a Multi-Layered Constitution (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2003). Jeremy Waldron, who is searching for the 'dignity of legislation' in the activities of legislative assemblies - especially majority voting (Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Part I; The Dignity of Legislation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)), seems to me to be looking in the wrong place, at least so far as Westminster systems are concerned.
    • (2003) Public Law in a Multi-Layered Constitution
    • Tomkins, A.1
  • 54
    • 27744487642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • who is searching for the 'dignity of legislation' in the activities of legislative assemblies - especially majority voting (Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)), seems to me to be looking in the wrong place, at least so far as Westminster systems are concerned
    • Jeremy Waldron, who is searching for the 'dignity of legislation' in the activities of legislative assemblies - especially majority voting (Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), Part I; The Dignity of Legislation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)), seems to me to be looking in the wrong place, at least so far as Westminster systems are concerned.
    • (1999) The Dignity of Legislation , Issue.PART I
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 55
    • 27744514328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Witness the debate in US administrative law about the choice that regulatory agencies have between adjudicative and legislative law-making: (Durham, NC: Durham Academic States (Durham, NC: Durham Academic Press, 2nd edn)
    • But see n 36 above.
    • (2002) Administrative Justice in the United States , pp. 258-262
    • Strauss, P.L.1
  • 56
    • 27744519634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is why acts of attainder are thought problematic
    • This is why acts of attainder are thought problematic.
  • 57
    • 27744480398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that this argument is primarily directed to the norm-legalization element of adjudication. By contrast, one aspect of the constitutional desideratum of judicial independence is that judges should be held accountable for the way they resolve individual disputes by being required to respond publicly and in a reasoned way to the arguments and proofs presented by the parties, and not by being answerable to some person or body outside the adjudicative triad. But because the demands of consistency forge a strong link between resolution of individual disputes and legalization of norms, the argument tends to be applied to judicial activity generally and not just to norm-legalization. At all events, the concept of representativeness is deeply ambiguous. To say that courts are not representative might signify that judges are not popularly elected, or that judges as a group are not a 'representative cross-section' of society. Nevertheless, we might consider judges to be representatives in the sense that they are appointed to perform particular tasks on society's behalf. Each of these different senses of representativeness has different implications for issues such as judicial appointments and accountability.
  • 58
    • 27744449836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that I am using 'consistency' in two different, but related, senses. The consistency that underpins adjudicative legalization of norms is the consistency of treating like cases alike ('formal justice' as it is sometimes called). The consistency in issue here is consistency within the body of common law norms.
  • 59
    • 27744583217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Courts may and do attempt to remove incoherence and inconsistency from the statute book by interpretative methods.
  • 60
    • 27744455542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For instance, people may disagree about when it is appropriate for existing common law norms to be rejected (by 'overruling') or side-lined (by 'distinguishing').
  • 61
    • 27744569988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Judges vary in the degree of respect they accord to 'precedent'. The priority norm leaves much room for individual judicial choice. This minimizes the risk of insoluble conflict between the priority norm and the coherence norm.
  • 62
    • 27744526858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To the extent that they do not affect the decision, they are resolved by the principles according to which the ratio decidendi is identified, which provide a surrogate for majority voting.
  • 63
    • 48249110626 scopus 로고
    • 'Is the Common Law Law?'
    • The increasing willingness of appeal courts to revisit earlier decisions is perhaps the main target of Heydon
    • F. Schauer 'Is the Common Law Law?', 77 California L Rev 455 (1989). The increasing willingness of appeal courts to revisit earlier decisions is perhaps the main target of Heydon, above n 13.
    • (1989) California L Rev , vol.77 , pp. 455
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 64
    • 27744440575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'What Are Appeal Courts For?
    • For a different perspective see See also Lord of Earlsferry
    • For a different perspective see Lord Rodger of Earlsferry, above n 34 at 529-36.
    • (2004) Otago LR , vol.10 , pp. 529-536
    • Rodger1
  • 65
    • 0037933924 scopus 로고
    • 'Introduction'
    • The non-documentary nature of 'morality' may be one reason why there is much disagreement amongst philosophers about 'the nature of morality'. For a helpful survey see G. Wallace and A.D.M. Walker (eds), (London: Methuen)
    • The non-documentary nature of 'morality' may be one reason why there is much disagreement amongst philosophers about 'the nature of morality'. For a helpful survey see G. Wallace and A.D.M. Walker, 'Introduction' in G. Wallace and A.D.M. Walker (eds), The Definition of Morality (London: Methuen, 1970).
    • (1970) The Definition of Morality
    • Wallace, G.1    Walker, A.D.M.2
  • 66
    • 27744594444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Rightness of Acts and the Goodness of Lives'
    • For recent discussion see R.J. Wallace et al. (eds), (Oxford, Clarendon Press)
    • For recent discussion see R.J. Wallace, 'The Rightness of Acts and the Goodness of Lives' in R.J. Wallace et al. (eds), Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2004).
    • (2004) Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz
    • Wallace, R.J.1
  • 67
    • 0002033666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press) the common law, like the Code, must 'have an answer for everything'
    • Particular courts may, of course, have limited jurisdiction. The statement in the text refers to the court system as a whole; and recall that I am using the term 'the courts' very broadly to refer to legal machinery for resolving disputes by adjudication. In this sense, the job of 'the courts' is to resolve disputes put before them, full stop, without limitation to disputes of any particular type or content. This partly explains why the common law is conceived as the background against which legislation operates, whereas in a 'Code system' the Code provides the background against which adjudication operates (D. Kennedy, A Critique of Adjudication (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1997), 241): The common law, like the Code, must 'have an answer for everything'.
    • (1997) A Critique of Adjudication , pp. 241
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 68
    • 27744474190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Often called 'moral' or 'ethical' norms
    • Often called 'moral' or 'ethical' norms.
  • 69
    • 27744577869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Taking Law Seriously: Starting Points of the Hart-Devlin Debate'
    • note (forthcoming)
    • These principles are related to the functions and resources of law and the legal system. This issue was addressed in one of the most famous jurisprudential debates of the 20th century between Partrick Devlin and Herbert Hart under the heading 'the legal enforcement of morals': P. Cane 'Taking Law Seriously: Starting Points of the Hart-Devlin Debate' (2006) 10 Journal of Ethics (forthcoming).
    • (2006) Journal of Ethics , vol.10
    • Cane, P.1
  • 70
    • 27744484846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Such considerations are sometimes referred to as matters of 'policy'; but this word is used in a bewildering number of other ways as well. Perhaps the two most frequently rehearsed policy arguments in tort law are the 'floodgates' and 'overkill' arguments.
  • 71
    • 0003883951 scopus 로고
    • note. See generally (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • For this reason, all laws, whether or not the product of political processes, should be revisable. People are more likely to accept laws they disagree with if they know that their existence will not stop debate about the terms of social cooperation. This is why effectively unamendable constitutional provisions are undesirable. See also Postema, above n 21 at 461-64.
    • (1986) Bentham and the Common Law Tradition , pp. 461-464
    • Postema, G.J.1
  • 72
    • 0004273196 scopus 로고
    • (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2nd edn)
    • L.L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2nd edn, 1969).
    • (1969) The Morality of Law
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 73
    • 27744446154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I suspect that at least one cause of judicial hostility to legislative 'interference' with tort law is dissatisfaction with the way the political process operates in practice - for instance, by according 'too much weight' to the views of pro-defendant lobby groups. Another explanation may be judicial 'rent-seeking'.
  • 74
    • 27744548970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harriton v Stephens
    • 694 at
    • Harriton v Stephens (2004) 59 NSWLR 694 at [24].
    • (2004) NSWLR , vol.59 , pp. 24
  • 75
    • 27744531688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'On the Division of Law-Making Labour'
    • A third argument might be that tort law is concerned with interpersonal 'corrective justice', not social 'distributive justice'. For discussion of this argument see 31
    • A third argument might be that tort law is concerned with interpersonal 'corrective justice', not social 'distributive justice'. For discussion of this argument see P. Cane, 'On the Division of Law-Making Labour' (2004) 7 The Judicial Review 31, 47-49
    • (2004) The Judicial Review , vol.7 , pp. 47-49
    • Cane, P.1
  • 77
    • 27744489248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Tort Law and Distributive Justice'
    • 'Tort Law and Distributive Justice' [2001] New Zealand LR 401.
    • (2001) New Zealand LR , pp. 401
  • 79
    • 27744585235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ironically, in the area of negligence law, at least, judicial vacillation in the past 25 years or so has arguably created much more instability than legislative intervention.
  • 80
    • 0041054120 scopus 로고
    • note see (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press)
    • Note that the objection is to legislative change of existing common law rules rather than to legislative extension and development of the common law by the legalization of norms consistent with existing common law rules or designed efficiently to clean up a mess in the common law. Note, conversely, that the inflexibility of the common law affects its ability to change direction and to clean up its own mess more than its ability to move forward. Indeed, a commonly-touted advantage of adjudicative over legislative legalization is its capacity to deal sensitively and coherently with new areas of law that regulate activities which may develop in unforeseeable ways. This is one reason why legislation may be drafted effectively to delegate significant law-making power to courts. Another oft-cited motivation is a desire to 'depoliticise' contentious issues. Concerning the converse problem of statutory obsolescence and the role of courts in dealing with it see G. Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1982).
    • (1982) A Common Law for the Age of Statutes
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 81
    • 27744493039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Liability for Personal Injuries Arising from Recreational Services: The Interaction of Contract, Tort, State Legislation and the Trade Practices Act and the Resultant Mess'
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g. J. Dietrich, 'Liability for Personal Injuries Arising from Recreational Services: The Interaction of Contract, Tort, State Legislation and the Trade Practices Act and the Resultant Mess' (2003) 11 Torts LJ 244.
    • (2003) Torts LJ , vol.11 , pp. 244
    • Dietrich, J.1
  • 82
    • 27744514666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cattanach v Melchior
    • at 1 at See also [82]-[83]
    • See n 7 above.
    • (2003) CLR , vol.215 , pp. 74
  • 83
    • 84983945935 scopus 로고
    • 'The Traditionality of Statutes'
    • M. Krygier, 'The Traditionality of Statutes' (1988) 1 Ratio Juris 20.
    • (1988) Ratio Juris , vol.1 , pp. 20
    • Krygier, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.