메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 59, Issue 2, 1997, Pages 233-258

John Locke and the argument against strict separation

(1)  McCabe, David a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 26444614364     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500026620     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (16)

References (56)
  • 2
    • 77954116979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most contemporary liberals endorse strict separation and see it as following from state neutrality towards conceptions of the good. For example... or the values of perfection (as in perfectionism), than it can act to advanee Catholicism or Protestantism, or any other religion. None of these views of the meaning, value and purpose of human life, as specified by the corresponding comprehensive religious or philosophical conceptions of the good, are affirmed by citizens generally, and so the pursuit of any one of them through basic institutions gives the state a sectarian character"
    • Most contemporary liberals endorse strict separation and see it as following from state neutrality towards conceptions of the good. For example, John Rawls declares, "the state can no more act to maximize the fulfillment of citizens' rational preferences,... or the values of perfection (as in perfectionism), than it can act to advanee Catholicism or Protestantism, or any other religion. None of these views of the meaning, value and purpose of human life, as specified by the corresponding comprehensive religious or philosophical conceptions of the good, are affirmed by citizens generally, and so the pursuit of any one of them through basic institutions gives the state a sectarian character"
    • The State Can No More Act to Maximize the Fulfillment of Citizens' Rational Preferences
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 3
    • 84935597626 scopus 로고
    • The priority of right and ideas of the good
    • (John Rawls, "The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good," Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 [1988]: 256).
    • (1988) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.17 , pp. 256
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 4
    • 0001991872 scopus 로고
    • Social unity and primary goods
    • Throughout his work Rawls has made it clear that he regards modern liberalism as the logical extension of religious toleration, and he explicitly cites Locke as someone who believed "that there are many conflicting and incommensurable conceptions of the good" ed. Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press]
    • Throughout his work Rawls has made it clear that he regards modern liberalism as the logical extension of religious toleration, and he explicitly cites Locke as someone who believed "that there are many conflicting and incommensurable conceptions of the good" (John Rawls, "Social Unity and Primary Goods," in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982], p 160).
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and beyond , pp. 160
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 5
    • 77954128653 scopus 로고
    • David Richards also adverts to Locke in his argument for strict separation, though he gives more attention than does Rawls to Locke's argument for the interconnections among religion, public morality, and individual harm (New York: Oxford University Press
    • David Richards also adverts to Locke in his argument for strict separation, though he gives more attention than does Rawls to Locke's argument for the interconnections among religion, public morality, and individual harm. See his Toleration and the Constitution (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 251-252
    • (1986) His Toleration and the Constitution , pp. 251-252
  • 6
    • 77954103157 scopus 로고
    • Though Richards claims that a belief in such interconnections cannot be sustained today, I do not think, for reasons I outline in this essay, that Locke's argument on this point can be so easily dismissed. One of the clearest statements of strict separation from the United States Supreme Court is found in Hugo Black's majority opinion in Everson v. Board of Education: "Neither a state nor the Federal Government can set up a church. Neither can pass laws which aid one religion, aid all religions, or prefer one religion over another" (quoted in ) Phoenix: The Oryx Press
    • Though Richards claims that a belief in such interconnections cannot be sustained today, I do not think, for reasons I outline in this essay, that Locke's argument on this point can be so easily dismissed. One of the clearest statements of strict separation from the United States Supreme Court is found in Hugo Black's majority opinion in Everson v. Board of Education: "Neither a state nor the Federal Government can set up a church. Neither can pass laws which aid one religion, aid all religions, or prefer one religion over another" (quoted in Darien A. McWhirter, The Separation of Church and State [Phoenix: The Oryx Press, 1994], p. 46).
    • (1994) The Separation of Church and State , pp. 46
    • McWhirter, D.A.1
  • 7
    • 0009419970 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and public morality
    • For attempts to illuminate the broader debate over state neutrality through readings of Locke's Letter ed. Alfonso Damico (Tottowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield)
    • For attempts to illuminate the broader debate over state neutrality through readings of Locke's Letter, see William Galston, "Liberalism and Public Morality," in Liberals on Liberalism, ed. Alfonso Damico (Tottowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1986);
    • (1986) Liberals on Liberalism
    • Galston, W.1
  • 10
    • 77954136251 scopus 로고
    • Any account of liberal neutrality ought to accommodate the Letter or else have a very good story about why not
    • The view is increasingly popular that, as Don Herzog puts it [Chicago: Chicago University Press]
    • The view is increasingly popular that, as Don Herzog puts it, "any account of liberal neutrality ought to accommodate the Letter or else have a very good story about why not" {Happy Slaves: A Critique of Consent Theory [Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1989], p. 148
    • (1989) Happy Slaves: A Critique of Consent Theory , pp. 148
  • 11
    • 0004236347 scopus 로고
    • ed. James Tully (Indianapolis: Hackett)
    • John Locke, A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. James Tully (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), p. 24.
    • (1983) A Letter Concerning Toleration , pp. 24
    • Locke, J.1
  • 13
    • 0037760047 scopus 로고
    • Toleration and the rationality of persecution
    • ed. John Horton and Susan Mendus (London: Routledge)
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution," in John Locke:A. Letter Concerning Toleration In Focus, ed. John Horton and Susan Mendus (London: Routledge, 1991), p. 99.
    • (1991) John Locke:A. Letter Concerning Toleration in Focus , pp. 99
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 14
    • 77954100186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interesting and evidently acceptable line of argument
    • Mendus's account in Toleration and the Limits of Liberalism and that of Waldron, who declares argument (4) the only (Waldron, "Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution,")
    • Cf. Mendus's account in Toleration and the Limits of Liberalism and that of Waldron, who declares argument (4) the only "interesting and evidently acceptable line of argument" in the Letter (Waldron, "Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution," p. 101).
    • The Letter , pp. 101
  • 15
    • 77954095551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waldron's presentation of the structure of this argument, as well as his exposition of the problems it faces, is clear and penetrating. But he is wrong to dismiss the importance in the Letter of another argument, centered around the circumstances of the original founding of the commonwealth and the extent of the consent granted to the magistrate. Given that this discussion of the origins of political authority constitutes one of Locke's most significant contributions to liberal theory and that such a consent-oriented argument lies at the heart of his most influential political tract, the Second Treatise, it is surprising to find that Waldron classifies as "careless readers" those who consider this argument crucial to the Letter
    • Waldron's presentation of the structure of this argument, as well as his exposition of the problems it faces, is clear and penetrating. But he is wrong to dismiss the importance in the Letter of another argument, centered around the circumstances of the original founding of the commonwealth and the extent of the consent granted to the magistrate. Given that this discussion of the origins of political authority constitutes one of Locke's most significant contributions to liberal theory and that such a consent-oriented argument lies at the heart of his most influential political tract, the Second Treatise, it is surprising to find that Waldron classifies as "careless readers" those who consider this argument crucial to the Letter.
  • 17
    • 77954067695 scopus 로고
    • John locke: From absolutism to toleration
    • for the argument that the Letter expresses Locke's distinctively liberal emphasis on "the differentiation of realms"
    • for the argument that the Letter expresses Locke's distinctively liberal emphasis on "the differentiation of realms" and Robert Kraynak, "John Locke: From Absolutism to Toleration," American Political Science Review 74 (1980): 53-69
    • (1980) American Political Science Review , vol.74 , pp. 53-69
    • Kraynak, R.1
  • 18
    • 77954099416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • on the importance in the Letter of
    • on the importance in the Letter of "the separation of spheres;
    • The Separation of Spheres
  • 19
    • 0004227351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. C. B. Macpherson (Indianapolis:Hackett) § 171
    • John Locke, Second Treatise of Government, ed. C. B. Macpherson (Indianapolis:Hackett, 1980), § 171.
    • (1980) Second Treatise of Government
    • Locke, J.1
  • 21
    • 77954141530 scopus 로고
    • Ibid., § 134. Locke's 1667 Essay Concerning Toleration sounds the same theme: "What was the end of erecting of government ought alone to be the measure of its proceeding" (quoted ) [New York:Harper and Bros. Publishers]
    • Ibid., § 134. Locke's 1667 Essay Concerning Toleration sounds the same theme:"What was the end of erecting of government ought alone to be the measure of its proceeding" (quoted in H. R. Fox Bourne, The Life of John Locke, vol. 1 [New York:Harper and Bros. Publishers, 1876], p. 174).
    • (1876) The Life of John Locke , vol.1 , pp. 174
    • Fox Bourne, H.R.1
  • 22
    • 0004284007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The centrality of justificatory neutrality to contemporary liberalism comes across clearly
    • The centrality of justificatory neutrality to contemporary liberalism comes across clearly in Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity;
    • Patterns of Moral Complexity
    • Larmore1
  • 24
    • 0002000041 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism
    • ed. Stuart Hampshire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Liberalism," in Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978);
    • (1978) Public and Private Morality
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 25
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Columbia University Press)
    • and John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 26
    • 77954114304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contemporary liberals have tended to endorse justificatory neutrality over neutrality of effect for two reasons. First, neutrality of effect is most likely impossible to achieve. Second, the state's refusal to evaluate citizens' conceptions of the good is seen as the only policy consistent with the idea of treating all citizens with equal respect. Since it is always possible that the state may have to outlaw practices that some individuals declare central to their conceptions of the good, the commitment to justificatory neutrality allows states to do so without impugning the intrinsic worth of such conceptions
    • Contemporary liberals have tended to endorse justificatory neutrality over neutrality of effect for two reasons. First, neutrality of effect is most likely impossible to achieve. Second, the state's refusal to evaluate citizens' conceptions of the good is seen as the only policy consistent with the idea of treating all citizens with equal respect. Since it is always possible that the state may have to outlaw practices that some individuals declare central to their conceptions of the good, the commitment to justificatory neutrality allows states to do so without impugning the intrinsic worth of such conceptions.
  • 27
    • 0344429342 scopus 로고
    • Legislation and moral neutrality
    • note
    • The comments of an anonymous referee have led me to conclude that there is another way of understanding the principle of justificatory neutrality. According to this alternative interpretation, the state may not act with the intention of affecting some religions for good or ill for any reason whatsoever (including reasons unrelated to assessments of intrinsic value); it is thus a more restrictive principle of justificatory neutrality than one that excludes reasons relating only to intrinsic value. While something like this alternative interpretation may be what some contemporary neutralists have in mind when they argue for strict separation, the principle thus interpreted is problematic. After all, if the neutral state may outlaw certain religious practices on the grounds of harm to civil interests, then for the same reasons it might be warranted in promoting, say, religious attitudes if a necessary relation were established between such attitudes and the protection of civil interests. It is hard to see why liberal states may take steps to punish those who violate civil interests but may not take reasonable steps to help deter such violations. Defenders of the more restrictive interpretation might then try to defend it by arguing for the special importance of religious conceptions of the good as opposed to nonreligious conceptions, but if one makes this distinction one privileges religious conceptions and thus violates neutrality among conceptions of the good. In any case, this alternative interpretation is certainly not the one endorsed by Locke, who understands justificatory neutrality in terms of reasons relating to intrinsic value. Jeremy Waldron's "Legislation and Moral Neutrality," in Liberal Neutrality, ed. Bruce Goodin and Andrew Reeve (New York: Routledge, 1989), does an excellent job of spelling out different ways of interpreting the principle of neutrality.
    • (1989) Liberal Neutrality
    • Waldron'S, J.1
  • 28
    • 77954096743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The argument I shall consider against strict separation also has ramifications, which I shall not develop here, for conceptions of the good other than religious ones. For example, if it turns out that certain conceptions of the good foster moral values fundamentally at odds with the public morality required for liberal society, then the argument I shall consider suggests that liberal states may be warranted in taking steps to hinder the pursuit of such conceptions
    • The argument I shall consider against strict separation also has ramifications, which I shall not develop here, for conceptions of the good other than religious ones. For example, if it turns out that certain conceptions of the good foster moral values fundamentally at odds with the public morality required for liberal society, then the argument I shall consider suggests that liberal states may be warranted in taking steps to hinder the pursuit of such conceptions.
  • 29
    • 0010801096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • explores Locke's understanding of the importance of public moral rules
    • Galston, "Liberalism and Public Morality," explores Locke's understanding of the importance of public moral rules.
    • Liberalism and Public Morality
    • Galston1
  • 30
    • 77954113061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke's understanding of the need for consensus on certain issues of public morality is also addressed
    • Locke's understanding of the need for consensus on certain issues of public morality is also addressed in Thomas A. Spragens, Jr., "Reconstructing Liberal Theory:Reason and Culture
    • Reconstructing Liberal Theory:Reason and Culture
    • Spragens Jr., T.A.1
  • 31
    • 84876830942 scopus 로고
    • The fruits of success and the crisis of liberalism
    • ed. Alfonso J. D'Amico (New Jersey:Rowman & Littlefield)
    • and Ronald J. Terchek, "The Fruits of Success and the Crisis of Liberalism," both in Liberals on Liberalism, ed. Alfonso J. D'Amico (New Jersey:Rowman & Littlefield, 1986).
    • (1986) Both in Liberals on Liberalism
    • Terchek, R.J.1
  • 32
    • 77954125180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the Letter Locke's grounding of the magistrate's authority to enforce moral codes rests entirely on their instrumental value in aiding public order and tranquility. He appears to have held the same view in his 1667 Essay:"Give me leave to say, however strange it may seem, that the law-maker hath nothing to do with moral virtues and vice, nor ought to enjoin the duties of the second table any otherwise than barely as they are subservient to the good and preservation of mankind under government"
    • In the Letter Locke's grounding of the magistrate's authority to enforce moral codes rests entirely on their instrumental value in aiding public order and tranquility. He appears to have held the same view in his 1667 Essay:"Give me leave to say, however strange it may seem, that the law-maker hath nothing to do with moral virtues and vice, nor ought to enjoin the duties of the second table any otherwise than barely as they are subservient to the good and preservation of mankind under government" (Fox Bourne, 77ie Life of John Locke, p. 181).
    • 77ie Life of John Locke , pp. 181
    • Bourne, F.1
  • 34
    • 24944486253 scopus 로고
    • John Locke and the case for toleration
    • ed. Susan Mendus and D. Edwards (New York: Oxford University Press) testify to Locke's desire for an established Church of England, as do his private letters, some of which I discuss below
    • and Maurice Cranston, "John Locke and the Case for Toleration," in On Toleration, ed. Susan Mendus and D. Edwards (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), testify to Locke's desire for an established Church of England, as do his private letters, some of which I discuss below.
    • (1987) On Toleration
    • Cranston, M.1
  • 35
    • 77954100446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against the second of these alternatives, it should be remembered that Locke took great pains to hide his authorship of the Letter and that it appears to have been published without his knowledge. Both of these facts suggest that he did not want to be publicly identified with the views expressed in the Letter
    • Against the second of these alternatives, it should be remembered that Locke took great pains to hide his authorship of the Letter and that it appears to have been published without his knowledge. Both of these facts suggest that he did not want to be publicly identified with the views expressed in the Letter.
  • 37
    • 77954110243 scopus 로고
    • John locke: Authority, conscience and religious roleration
    • ed. John Horton and Susan Mendus [London: Routledge]
    • ("John Locke: Authority, Conscience and Religious Toleration," in John Locke: A Letter Concerning Toleration In Focus, ed. John Horton and Susan Mendus [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 132).
    • (1991) John Locke: A Letter Concerning Toleration in Focus , pp. 132
  • 38
    • 77954125712 scopus 로고
    • ed. E. S. De Beer (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • The Correspondence of John Locke, vol.3, ed. E. S. De Beer (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978), p. 588.
    • (1978) The Correspondence of John Locke , vol.3 , pp. 588
  • 42
    • 77954108951 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • James Tully puts the point thus: "For Locke, as for almost all his contemporaries, only belief in a God who punishes the wicked and rewards the virtuous in an afterlife provides most individuals with motive-self-interest- sufficient to cause them to act morally and legally" Dunn claims that belief in God is, for Locke, "the foundation of all morality" (John Locke [Oxford: Oxford University Press, P. 58]
    • James Tully puts the point thus:"For Locke, as for almost all his contemporaries, only belief in a God who punishes the wicked and rewards the virtuous in an afterlife provides most individuals with motive-self-interest- sufficient to cause them to act morally and legally" (" Introduction" to A Letter Concerning Toleration, p. 8). Dunn claims that belief in God is, for Locke, "the foundation of all morality" (John Locke [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984], p. 58.
    • (1984) A Letter Concerning Toleration , pp. 8
  • 46
    • 84971791632 scopus 로고
    • John Locke:From Absolutism to Toleration," and George Windstrup "freedom and Authority: The Ancient Faith of Locke's Letter on Toleration
    • In this respect, the position I am advancing continues the lines of argument put forth by
    • In this respect, the position I am advancing continues the lines of argument put forth by Kraynak, "John Locke:From Absolutism to Toleration," and George Windstrup, "Freedom and Authority: The Ancient Faith of Locke's Letter on Toleration," Review of Politics 44 (1982): 242-265
    • (1982) Review of Politics , vol.44 , pp. 242-265
    • Kraynak1
  • 47
    • 77954127611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • both of whom see Locke's position in the Letter as largely motivated by his mature understanding of what was required, given the fact of religious pluralism, to achieve peaceful coexistence among citizens. (Windstrup's article contains a particularly lucid discussion of the special compatibility between Christianity and Locke's liberalism.) Though each goes further than I in the degree to which they see Locke's argument for toleration as strategically motivated (Kraynak does not discuss sufficiently the possibility that Locke came to see toleration as the strategy most conducive to spreading the true faith, while Windstrup somewhat overstates his case in implying that Locke regarded natural rights largely as convenient fictions), both essays do an excellent job of demonstrating that for Locke the question of how the state ought to act with respect to religion cannot be resolved solely through an a priori analysis but must be determined partly on the basis of empirical facts about the citizens of the state and their attitudes towards religion.
  • 48
    • 77954114805 scopus 로고
    • Cross-purposes: The liberal-communitarian debate
    • ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • "Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate," in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), p. 171.
    • (1989) Liberalism and the Moral Life , pp. 171
  • 49
    • 77954129137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As I write, the government of the United States is shut down, stalled in a battle over which segments of its society should be asked to shoulder the burden of balancing the budget. One could hardly imagine a more dramatic demonstration of the way in which liberal democracies depend on citizens' willingness to sacrifice personal interests for the good of the whole, though to be precise one should speak here of the perception on the part of certain lawmakers that citizens are unwilling to make such sacrifices
    • As I write, the government of the United States is shut down, stalled in a battle over which segments of its society should be asked to shoulder the burden of balancing the budget. One could hardly imagine a more dramatic demonstration of the way in which liberal democracies depend on citizens' willingness to sacrifice personal interests for the good of the whole, though to be precise one should speak here of the perception on the part of certain lawmakers that citizens are unwilling to make such sacrifices.
  • 50
    • 77954136530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That religion is vital to the sustaining of public morality has, of course, been endorsed by many leading figures in the history of the United States. Consider the following passage from George Washington's farewell address: "And let us with caution indulge the supposition, that morality can be maintained without religion. Whatever may be conceded to the influence of refined education on minds of peculiar structure, reason and experience both forbid us to expect that national morality can prevail in exclusion of religious principle; (I thank Walter Nicgorski for alerting me to the relevance of this passage.)
    • That religion is vital to the sustaining of public morality has, of course, been endorsed by many leading figures in the history of the United States. Consider the following passage from George Washington's farewell address: "And let us with caution indulge the supposition, that morality can be maintained without religion. Whatever may be conceded to the influence of refined education on minds of peculiar structure, reason and experience both forbid us to expect that national morality can prevail in exclusion of religious principle; (I thank Walter Nicgorski for alerting me to the relevance of this passage.)
  • 51
    • 77954111975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The study of Muncie, Indiana, that discusses in(Commentary) is an example of what I have in mind. This study claims to show that higher levels of religious belief correlated with higher degrees of tolerance, clearly a moral virtue of great importance in preserving civil harmony. Of course, correlation is not causation, and gathering and interpreting such information is a highly precarious process.
    • The study of Muncie, Indiana, that R. J. Neuhaus discusses in "What the Fundamentalists Want" (Commentary 79, no. 5: 41-46) is an example of what I have in mind. This study claims to show that higher levels of religious belief correlated with higher degrees of tolerance, clearly a moral virtue of great importance in preserving civil harmony. Of course, correlation is not causation, and gathering and interpreting such information is a highly precarious process.
    • What the Fundamentalists Want , vol.79 , Issue.5 , pp. 41-46
    • Neuhaus, R.J.1
  • 52
    • 0010801096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (The reference to Neuhaus and the study is taken from More recently, Don Browning has argued that the revival of the moral virtues in parishioners of a church in south Chicago was made possible largely by the fact that these virtues were presented within an explicitly religious framework
    • (The reference to Neuhaus and the study is taken from Galston, "Liberalism and Public Morality;) More recently, Don Browning has argued that the revival of the moral virtues in parishioners of a church in south Chicago was made possible largely by the fact that these virtues were presented within an explicitly religious framework.
    • Liberalism and Public Morality
    • Galston1
  • 53
    • 84990343655 scopus 로고
    • Altruism, civic virtue, and religion
    • ed. Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn (Lanham, MD: Madison Books)
    • See Don Browning, "Altruism, Civic Virtue, and Religion," in Seedbeds of Virtue, ed. Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn (Lanham, MD: Madison Books, 1995).
    • (1995) Seedbeds of Virtue
    • Browning, D.1
  • 54
    • 77954092834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intuitively it seems plausible that for many individuals a close connection exists between their moral and religious beliefs-so close that it perhaps should not be called a connection at all. If we accept, as seems reasonable, Michael Perry's claims that all religions "comprise norms governing one's relation to others" and that "every religious vision also comprises beliefs-moral beliefs- about how to live compatibly with the basic religious beliefs" (Love and Power [New York: Oxford University Press, 1991] 77), then it would seem likely that for some people a decline in religious sentiment may lead to significant alterations in their moral character
    • Intuitively it seems plausible that for many individuals a close connection exists between their moral and religious beliefs-so close that it perhaps should not be called a connection at all. If we accept, as seems reasonable, Michael Perry's claims that all religions "comprise norms governing one's relation to others" and that "every religious vision also comprises beliefs-moral beliefs- about how to live compatibly with the basic religious beliefs" (Love and Power [New York: Oxford University Press, 1991], p. 77), then it would seem likely that for some people a decline in religious sentiment may lead to significant alterations in their moral character.
  • 55
    • 0004292366 scopus 로고
    • "The dogmas of the civil religion ought to be simple, few in number, precisely worded, without explanations or commentaries. The existence of a powerful, intelligent, beneficent divinity that foresees and provides; the life to come; the happiness of the just; the punishment of the wicked; the sanctity of the social contract and of the laws. These are the positive dogmas" trans. Donald Cress [Indianapolis: Hackett]
    • "The dogmas of the civil religion ought to be simple, few in number, precisely worded, without explanations or commentaries. The existence of a powerful, intelligent, beneficent divinity that foresees and provides; the life to come; the happiness of the just; the punishment of the wicked; the sanctity of the social contract and of the laws. These are the positive dogmas" (The Social Contract, trans. Donald Cress [Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987], p. 102).
    • (1987) The Social Contract , pp. 102
  • 56
    • 77954111050 scopus 로고
    • London: George Allen & Unwin, remains one of the clearest treatments of civil religion in Rousseau's thought
    • Alfred Cobban's Rousseau and the Modern State (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1934), pp. 76-88, remains one of the clearest treatments of civil religion in Rousseau's thought.
    • (1934) Alfred Cobban's Rousseau and the Modern State , pp. 76-88


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.