메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 33, Issue 5, 2005, Pages 602-628

Kantian personal autonomy

Author keywords

Autonomy; Kant; Prudence; Rawls; Virtue

Indexed keywords


EID: 26444579304     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591705278397     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (41)

References (147)
  • 1
    • 0004253887 scopus 로고
    • ed. John Gray (New York: Oxford University Press)
    • John Stuart Mill, On Liberty and Other Essays, ed. John Gray (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), 63.
    • (1991) On Liberty and Other Essays , pp. 63
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 2
    • 84927113467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral autonomy and personal autonomy
    • eds. John Christman and Joel Anderson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Moral Autonomy and Personal Autonomy," in Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism, eds. John Christman and Joel Anderson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 308-14.
    • (2005) Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism , pp. 308-314
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 3
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 370n.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom
    • Raz, J.1
  • 4
    • 1642495088 scopus 로고
    • Autonomy
    • ed. John Christman (New York: Oxford University Press)
    • Cf. Joel Feinberg, "Autonomy," in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, ed. John Christman (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), 35-6, 44.
    • (1989) The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy , pp. 35-36
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 6
    • 5744229285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Kantian conception of autonomy
    • Cf. Thomas Hill, "The Kantian Conception of Autonomy," in The Inner Citadel, 92-5.
    • The Inner Citadel , pp. 92-95
    • Hill, T.1
  • 8
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: The Clarendon Press
    • On the concept/conception distinction, see H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1961), 155-9
    • (1961) The Concept of Law , pp. 155-159
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 9
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), [Revised Edition]
    • and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999 [Revised Edition]), 5, 8-9.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 5
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 10
    • 26444602670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a similar spirit, Waldron says that "what is called for is some sort of moderate or intermediate position. This chapter has not sought to identify that third way, but I hope it has helped illuminate some of the perils as well as some of the advantages of a distinction between personal and moral autonomy." Waldron, "Moral Autonomy and Personal Autonomy," 325.
    • Moral Autonomy and Personal Autonomy , pp. 325
    • Waldron1
  • 13
    • 59349119571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kantian constructivism in moral theory
    • ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • John Rawls, "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," in Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 308, 319.
    • (1999) Collected Papers , pp. 308
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 18
    • 0346275693 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of the will and the concept of the person
    • Harry Frankfurt, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cf. Harry Frankfurt, "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of the Person," in Harry Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 15, 19.
    • (1988) The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays , pp. 15
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 19
    • 26444444344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Autonomy and hierarchy
    • Also see Michael Bratman, "Autonomy and Hierarchy," Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (2003): 156-76.
    • (2003) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.20 , pp. 156-176
    • Bratman, M.1
  • 21
    • 84948661972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Autonomy in moral and political philosophy
    • ed. Edward N. Zalta
    • John Christman, "Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy," in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/autonomy-moral/.
    • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition)
    • Christman, J.1
  • 22
    • 84917173671 scopus 로고
    • Constructing the inner citadel: Recent work on the concept of autonomy
    • Also see John Christman, "Constructing the Inner Citadel: Recent Work on the Concept of Autonomy," Ethics 99 (1988): 109-24.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 109-124
    • Christman, J.1
  • 29
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. and ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), [GMM 4:399], [GMM 4:414]
    • Immanuel Kant, Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 54 [GMM 4:399], 69n [GMM 4:414]. N.B.: Throughout the endnotes I will supplement the page references to this edition of Kant with (i) abbreviations for the works from which they were drawn plus (ii) the relevant volume and page references to the standard German edition of Kant's works, Kant's Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences (Berlin: Georg Reimer, 1900). Here is a complete list of the abbreviations I use: GMM=Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals; MM=Metaphysics of Morals; CPrR= Critique of Practical Reason; T&P="On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice"; Rel=Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason.
    • (1996) Practical Philosophy , pp. 54
    • Kant, I.1
  • 31
    • 26444447210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • eds. Allen Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), [Rel 6:58]
    • Immanuel Kant, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, eds. Allen Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 78 [Rel 6:58].
    • (1998) Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason , pp. 78
    • Kant, I.1
  • 34
    • 0004281448 scopus 로고
    • trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books), [589a-c]
    • Cf. Plato, Republic, trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1991), 272 [589a-c].
    • (1991) Republic , pp. 272
    • Plato1
  • 35
    • 26444515202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human nature is not a machine to be built after a model, and set to do exactly the work prescribed for it, but a tree, which requires to grow and develop itself on all sides, according to the tendency of the inward forces which make it a living thing
    • See Mill, On Liberty and Other Essays, 66: "Human nature is not a machine to be built after a model, and set to do exactly the work prescribed for it, but a tree, which requires to grow and develop itself on all sides, according to the tendency of the inward forces which make it a living thing."
    • On Liberty and Other Essays , pp. 66
    • Mill1
  • 38
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:216]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, cf. ibid., 371 [MM 6:216].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 371
  • 41
    • 0003584929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Also see Christine Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 111-2.
    • (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends , pp. 111-112
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 44
    • 84872966445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In [Rel 6:27]
    • Cf. Kant, Religion, 5 In [Rel 6:27].
    • Religion , pp. 5
    • Kant1
  • 46
    • 0004123369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cf. Henry Allison, Kant's Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 164-5.
    • (1990) Kant's Theory of Freedom , pp. 164-165
    • Allison, H.1
  • 48
    • 84872966445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [Rel 6:27], [Rel 6:58]
    • Kant, Religion, 50-1 [Rel 6:27], 78 [Rel 6:58].
    • Religion , pp. 50-51
    • Kant1
  • 50
    • 84901834664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), [Second Discourse, Rousseau's Note 15]
    • for a different perspective. These predispositions are to mechanical self-love (animality) and comparative self-love (humanity), which are roughly equivalent to Rousseau's concepts of amour de soi-même and amour propre, respectively. See Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings, ed. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 218 [Second Discourse, Rousseau's Note 15].
    • (1997) The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings , pp. 218
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 55
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:429], [MM 6:392]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, 80 [GMM 4:429], 522 [MM 6:392].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 80
    • Kant1
  • 56
    • 26444515203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preserving and respecting rational nature means preserving and respecting it in all its functions, not merely in its moral function of giving and obeying moral laws. Furthering rational nature requires furthering all the (morally permissible) ends it sets, not merely the ends it sets in response to duty
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cf. Allen Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 120: "Preserving and respecting rational nature means preserving and respecting it in all its functions, not merely in its moral function of giving and obeying moral laws. Furthering rational nature requires furthering all the (morally permissible) ends it sets, not merely the ends it sets in response to duty."
    • (1999) Kant's Ethical Thought , pp. 120
    • Wood, A.1
  • 59
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:399], [GMM 4:419]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 54 [GMM 4:399], 71 [GMM 4:419].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 54
    • Kant1
  • 60
    • 26444462717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant and stoic ethics
    • eds. Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • J. B. Schneewind, "Kant and Stoic Ethics," in Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, eds. Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 290.
    • (1996) Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty , pp. 290
    • Schneewind, J.B.1
  • 62
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [T&P 8:284] (emphasis added)
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 285n [T&P 8:284] (emphasis added).
    • Practical Philosophy
    • Kant1
  • 63
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [CPrR 5:118], [CPrR 5:161]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 235 [CPrR 5:118], 268 [CPrR 5:161].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 235
    • Kant1
  • 64
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:428]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Cf. ibid., 79 [GMM 4:428].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 79
  • 66
    • 26444605117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Barbara Herman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • Rawls nonetheless defends Kant against this charge, arguing that his moral psychology is less Manichaean than Augustinian. See John Rawls, Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, ed. Barbara Herman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), 303-6.
    • (2000) Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy , pp. 303-306
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 67
    • 84872966445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [Rel 6:35]
    • Kant, Religion, 57-8 [Rel 6:35].
    • Religion , pp. 57-58
    • Kant1
  • 68
    • 84872966445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [Rel 6:27]
    • Kant, Religion, Ibid., 51 [Rel 6:27]. Also see endnote on Rousseau above.
    • Religion , pp. 51
    • Kant1
  • 70
    • 26444454132 scopus 로고
    • Hedonism, heteronomy and Kant's principle of happiness
    • If Kant's belief in the natural and/or social genesis of all inclinations appears implausible, see Andrew Reath's interpretation of Kant on the nature of heteronomy and the genealogy of desire in "Hedonism, Heteronomy and Kant's Principle of Happiness," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989): 42-72, especially 48, 60.
    • (1989) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.70 , pp. 42-72
    • Reath's, A.1
  • 72
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:394] (emphasis added)
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 50 [GMM 4:394] (emphasis added).
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 50
    • Kant1
  • 73
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many if not most theorists of personal autonomy recognize the conditionality of its goodness. See, for example, Raz, The Morality of Freedom, 380-1 ;
    • The Morality of Freedom , pp. 380-381
    • Raz1
  • 79
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:240], [MM 6:398]
    • Based on diagrams in Kant, Practical Philosophy, 395 [MM 6:240], 527 [MM 6:398].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 395
    • Kant1
  • 81
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:391]
    • One can also discharge one's duties of right virtuously (i.e., meritoriously) if one makes "the right of humanity, or also the right of human beings, one's end." Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 521-2 [MM 6:391].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 521-522
  • 82
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:333-6], [MM 6:462-8]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 474-6 [MM 6:333-6], 579-83 [MM 6:462-8].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 474-476
    • Kant1
  • 83
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:390-2]
    • On the distinction between perfect and imperfect duties in general, see Kant, Practical Philosophy, ibid., 521-2 [MM 6:390-2].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 521-522
    • Kant1
  • 85
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:424], [GMM 4:431], [MM 6:453]
    • Though the duty of beneficence requires no particular actions, a complete absence of beneficent actions would be a violation of the duty. See Kant, Practical Philosophy, ibid., 75 [GMM 4:424], 81 [GMM 4:431], 572 [MM 6:453].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 75
  • 86
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:390-1]
    • Also, all duties of right are perfect duties: one cannot impose an end by use of coercion, though one can use coercion to guarantee the performance or omission of an action. See Kant, Practical Philosophy, ibid., 521 [MM 6:390-1].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 521
  • 87
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:423], [MM 6:387], [MM 6:392], [MM 6:445-66]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 74-5 [GMM 4:423], 518 [MM 6:387], 522-3 [MM 6:392], 565-6 [MM 6:445-66].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 74-75
    • Kant1
  • 88
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:386]
    • Kant explicitly rules out the perfection of others as a duty: he says that perfection is "something that only the other himself can do," for unless the other himself sets it as an end, the cultivation of his talents will fail to be meritorious. Again, one can force actions but not ends, and only the free adoption of virtuous ends can earn merit. Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 517-8 [MM 6:386].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 517-518
  • 89
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:429], [MM 6:392]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 80 [GMM 4:429], 522-3 [MM 6:392].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 80
    • Kant1
  • 90
    • 0004231396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a different approach to justifying natural perfection as a duty, see O'Neill, Constructions of Reason, 98-101.
    • Constructions of Reason , pp. 98-101
    • O'Neill1
  • 91
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:392], [MM 6:446]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, 523 [MM 6:392], 566 [MM 6:446].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 523
    • Kant1
  • 92
    • 26444445310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-realization and the priority of fair equality of opportunity
    • On the precise nature of the relationship between natural perfection and occupation, see Robert S. Taylor, "Self-Realization and the Priority of Fair Equality of Opportunity," Journal of Moral Philosophy 1 (2004): 333-47, here 342-3.
    • (2004) Journal of Moral Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 333-347
    • Taylor, R.S.1
  • 93
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [CPrR 5:122-4], [MM 6:387], [MM 6:393], [MM 6:447]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, 238-9 [CPrR 5:122-4], 518-9 [MM 6:387], 523 [MM 6:393], 566-7 [MM 6:447].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 238-239
    • Kant1
  • 94
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:393], [6:447]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 523 [MM 6:393], 567 [6:447].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 523
    • Kant1
  • 95
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:402], [MM 6:450]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 530 [MM 6:402], 569 [MM 6:450].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 530
    • Kant1
  • 96
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:386]
    • Kant rejects the idea of a duty of practical love toward oneself, the promotion of one's own happiness is at most an indirect duty and only insofar as its promotion is necessary to ward off poverty, pain, and so on, as "great temptations to violate one's duty." That is, the promotion of one's own happiness is, from a moral point of view, only useful as a means to promote (adherence to) morality. Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 517-8 [MM 6:386].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 517-518
  • 97
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:388], [MM 6:394], [MM 6:453-5]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, Ibid., 519 [MM 6:388], 524 [MM 6:394], 571-3 [MM 6:453-5].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 519
    • Kant1
  • 99
    • 0004051088 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), Chapter 3
    • Also see Barbara Herman, The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), Chapter 3
    • (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgment
    • Herman, B.1
  • 105
    • 84971943374 scopus 로고
    • Self-realization in work and politics: The marxist conception of the good life
    • On consumption as a self-actualizing (but not self-realizing) activity, see Jon Elster, "Self-Realization in Work and Politics: The Marxist Conception of the Good Life," Social Philosophy & Policy 3 (1986): 103, 106.
    • (1986) Social Philosophy & Policy , vol.3 , pp. 103
    • Elster, J.1
  • 106
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [MM 6:394], [MM 6:432-3], [MM 6:453]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, 524 [MM 6:394], 555-6 [MM 6:432-3], 572 [MM 6:453].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 524
    • Kant1
  • 108
    • 0009993153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the larger issue of setting ends in a virtuous life, see Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought, 325.
    • Kant's Ethical Thought , pp. 325
    • Wood1
  • 109
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:394] (emphasis added)
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, 50 [GMM 4:394] (emphasis added).
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 50
    • Kant1
  • 111
    • 0004341367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [GMM 4:423-4], [GMM 4:446-7]
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, 74-5 [GMM 4:423-4], 94-5 [GMM 4:446-7].
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 74-75
    • Kant1
  • 114
    • 26444516734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Washington, DC: Regnery Publishing
    • Cf. Luke 14:23 ("Go out into the highways and hedges, and compel them to come in, that my house may be filled.") and St. Augustine's use of it to defend the persecution of heretics in St. Augustine, The Political Writings, ed. Henry Paolucci (Washington, DC: Regnery Publishing, 1996), 193.
    • (1996) The Political Writings , pp. 193
    • Paolucci, H.1
  • 115
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 497. Rawls summarizes the myriad strands of the congruence argument in §86 ("The Good of the Sense of Justice").
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 497
    • Rawls1
  • 116
    • 84937285463 scopus 로고
    • John Rawls and the search for stability
    • Brian Barry says of the congruence argument that "the only thing to do with it is to follow the course followed virtually unanimously by commentators on A Theory of Justice and forget about it." See Brian Barry, "John Rawls and the Search for Stability," Ethics 105 (1995): 915n. Rawls's doubts are expressed in Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), xv-xvii, though the focus here is on the larger argument in Part III of A Theory of Justice about the stability of a well-ordered society rather than on the congruence argument proper, which is merely one component (albeit a central one) of the larger argument. Concerns about the stability of justice as fairness were the primary motivation for Rawls's so-called "political turn," as we shall soon see.
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105
    • Barry, B.1
  • 117
    • 26444488766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Congruence and the good of justice
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Freeman attempts to reconstruct Rawls's congruence argument in "Congruence and the Good of Justice," in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 277-315. On the argument's critics and limitations, see especially 277-8, 292, and 303-8.
    • (2003) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls , pp. 277-315
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 118
    • 84893751755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [Rel 6:112]
    • For example, Kant provides "the supreme principle of all scriptural exegesis" in Religion, which requires us to interpret scriptural passages so that they are consistent with our obligations of justice and virtue (Religion, 119-20 [Rel 6:112]). Consequently, Kant would reject any religious doctrine that interpreted scripture (e.g., Luke 14:23) in such a way as to endorse the persecution of heretics or unbelievers, as such persecution is inconsistent with our prior political duty of religious toleration.
    • Religion , pp. 119-120
  • 124
    • 26444613496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I may be overstating the residual indeterminacy here, as principles of deliberative rationality may interact with objective ends in such a way as to constrain the choice set further. For example, one principle of deliberative rationality is surely "inventorying," that is, systematically examining our various capacities, preferences, and so on, before we make (important) decisions. If we do this before engaging in self-perfection, we may be able to rule out certain plans of self-development due to the lack of relevant capacities-singing lessons, for instance, are probably not the best path to self-improvement for the congenitally tone deaf. (Special thanks to Brad Inwood for pointing this out.)
  • 126
    • 0003499065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • For a brief discussion of the key differences between A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism, see John Rawls, The Law of Peoples with "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited" (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 179-80;
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples with "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited" , pp. 179-180
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 129
    • 0010147706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Barry, for example, has been a persistent critic of Rawls's "political turn." To quote Barry on this topic: "I believe that, as time goes on, A Theory of Justice will stand out with increasing clarity as by far the most significant contribution to political philosophy produced in this century. Only one thing threatens to obscure that achievement: the publication of Political Liberalism." Barry, "John Rawls and the Search for Stability," 915.
    • John Rawls and the Search for Stability , pp. 915
    • Barry1
  • 131
    • 26444480895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls's defense of the priority of liberty: A Kantian reconstruction
    • Robert S. Taylor, "Rawls's Defense of the Priority of Liberty: A Kantian Reconstruction," Philosophy & Public Affairs 31 (2003): 246-71.
    • (2003) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.31 , pp. 246-271
    • Taylor, R.S.1
  • 132
    • 3042695948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of an overlapping consensus
    • Rawls, "The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus," in Collected Papers, 433-4. Rawls later changes his mind about this exclusion (Political Liberalism, 170), though the reason for this change appears to be his conflation of constitutional and overlapping consensus;
    • Collected Papers , pp. 433-434
    • Rawls1
  • 137
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See §18-9 in general
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Ibid., 94, 98-101. See §18-9 in general.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 94
    • Rawls1
  • 146
    • 0034345845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What enlightenment project?
    • James Schmidt, "What Enlightenment Project?" Political Theory 28 (2000): 735.
    • (2000) Political Theory , vol.28 , pp. 735
    • Schmidt, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.