-
1
-
-
85081832188
-
-
I would like to thank, and the referees of, for their helpful contributions.
-
I would like to thank Brian McLaughlin, Harold Rubinstein, and the referees of Criminal Justice Ethics for their helpful contributions.
-
Criminal Justice Ethics
-
-
McLaughlin, B.1
Rubinstein, H.2
-
2
-
-
0011369311
-
-
2d ed., I offer no hypothesis about why Hall's thesis is so widely accepted among criminal theorists.
-
J. Hall, General Principles Of Criminal Law 88 (2d ed. 1960). I offer no hypothesis about why Hall's thesis is so widely accepted among criminal theorists.
-
(1960)
General Principles Of Criminal Law
, vol.88
-
-
Hall, J.1
-
3
-
-
84979115983
-
Partial Excuses in the Criminal Law
-
“The basis for… assuming a clear distinction between excusing conditions, which operate to relieve a criminal defendant from liability entirely, and mitigating excuses, which are taken into account by way of sentencing discretion… is rarely articulated, and when it is, seems unconvincing.
-
“The basis for… assuming a clear distinction between excusing conditions, which operate to relieve a criminal defendant from liability entirely, and mitigating excuses, which are taken into account by way of sentencing discretion… is rarely articulated, and when it is, seems unconvincing.” Wasik, Partial Excuses in the Criminal Law, 45 Mod. L. Rev. 516 (1982).
-
(1982)
Mod. L. Rev
, vol.45
, pp. 516
-
-
Wasik1
-
4
-
-
84928446155
-
The Cultural Defense in the Criminal Law
-
See Note
-
See Note, The Cultural Defense in the Criminal Law, 99 Harv. L. Rev. 1293 (1986).
-
(1986)
Harv. L. Rev
, vol.99
, pp. 1293
-
-
-
5
-
-
34250647846
-
Criminal Law: The Missing Element in Sentencing Reform
-
See
-
See Tonry, Criminal Law: The Missing Element in Sentencing Reform, 35 Vand. L. Rev. 607 (1982).
-
(1982)
Vand. L. Rev
, vol.35
, pp. 607
-
-
Tonry1
-
7
-
-
85081832902
-
-
See Hall's ground for rejecting Salmond's definition: “[T]he criticism of Salmond's usage is based upon… countless decisions holding that motive is not a material element of a crime., note 1
-
See Hall's ground for rejecting Salmond's definition: “[T]he criticism of Salmond's usage is based upon… countless decisions holding that motive is not a material element of a crime.” Supra note 1, at 85, n. 67.
-
Supra
, Issue.67
, pp. 85
-
-
-
8
-
-
85081834334
-
-
Gross attributes this example to “a philosopher,” but neglects to identify him.
-
H. Gross, A Theory Of Criminal Justice 111 (1979). Gross attributes this example to “a philosopher,” but neglects to identify him.
-
(1979)
A Theory Of Criminal Justice
, vol.111
-
-
Gross, H.1
-
9
-
-
84928460235
-
Agent Motives and the Criminal Law
-
See
-
See Sistare, Agent Motives and the Criminal Law, 13 Soc. Theory & Prac. 303 (1987).
-
(1987)
Soc. Theory & Prac
, vol.13
, pp. 303
-
-
Sistare1
-
11
-
-
4244019275
-
-
See also, 7th ed.
-
See also J. Salmond, Jurisprudence 397 (7th ed. 1924).
-
(1924)
Jurisprudence
, pp. 397
-
-
Salmond, J.1
-
14
-
-
84922979869
-
Motive as an Essential Element of Crime
-
See, -1931
-
See Hitchler, Motive as an Essential Element of Crime, 35 Dick L. Rev. 105 (1930-1931).
-
(1930)
Dick L. Rev
, vol.35
, pp. 105
-
-
Hitchler1
-
15
-
-
85081827633
-
-
note 10
-
Supra note 10, at 49.
-
Supra
, pp. 49
-
-
-
17
-
-
85081823309
-
Philosophy Of Criminal Law
-
See, for a discussion of how, causation, and harm requirements have been “defended” by being interpreted as tautologies.
-
See D. Husak, Philosophy Of Criminal Law (1987), for a discussion of how theactus reus, mens rea, causation, and harm requirements have been “defended” by being interpreted as tautologies.
-
(1987)
theactus reus, mens rea
-
-
Husak, D.1
-
18
-
-
85081832950
-
-
note 8
-
Supra note 8, at 111.
-
Supra
, pp. 111
-
-
-
19
-
-
77957760303
-
Desert and Previous Convictions in Sentencing
-
See
-
See Von Hirsch, Desert and Previous Convictions in Sentencing, 65 U. Minn. L. Rev. 591 (1981).
-
(1981)
U. Minn. L. Rev
, vol.65
, pp. 591
-
-
Von Hirsch1
-
20
-
-
85081834080
-
-
410 A2d 1000
-
410 A2d 1000 (1979).
-
(1979)
-
-
-
21
-
-
85081832513
-
-
See, note 9, The chief difficulty with this view is to identify those “action-initiators” that are not motives.
-
See Sistare, supra note 9, at 306. The chief difficulty with this view is to identify those “action-initiators” that are not motives.
-
supra
, pp. 306
-
-
Sistare1
-
23
-
-
85081832980
-
-
In light of these offenses, Sistare remarks, “If there is a real ground for dispute here, it seems to be a question of how many exceptions remake the rule., note 9
-
In light of these offenses, Sistare remarks, “If there is a real ground for dispute here, it seems to be a question of how many exceptions remake the rule.” Supra note 9, at 316.
-
Supra
, pp. 316
-
-
-
24
-
-
85081823596
-
-
See, F.2d
-
See Jones v. U.S., 308 F.2d 307 (1962).
-
(1962)
Jones v. U.S
, vol.308
, pp. 307
-
-
-
25
-
-
85081830011
-
Doctors as Murderers
-
See
-
See Beynon, Doctors as Murderers, Crim. L. Rev. (1982).
-
(1982)
Crim. L. Rev
-
-
Beynon1
-
27
-
-
4344595936
-
Prolonging Life: Some Legal Considerations
-
See the analysis in
-
See the analysis in Fletcher, Prolonging Life: Some Legal Considerations, 42 Wash. L. Rev. 999 (1967).
-
(1967)
Wash. L. Rev
, vol.42
, pp. 999
-
-
Fletcher1
-
28
-
-
84055208984
-
Barber v. Superior Court of Los Angeles County
-
The influence of this analysis in case law is illustrated by
-
The influence of this analysis in case law is illustrated by Barber v. Superior Court of Los Angeles County, 195 Cal. Rptr. 484 (1983).
-
(1983)
Cal. Rptr
, vol.195
, pp. 484
-
-
-
29
-
-
84963153818
-
-
It is unclear whether a defendant whose conduct is justified actually commits a criminal offense. See, note 17
-
It is unclear whether a defendant whose conduct is justified actually commits a criminal offense. See D. Husak, supra note 17, at 190-92.
-
supra
, pp. 190-192
-
-
Husak, D.1
-
31
-
-
0042376648
-
A Theory of Justification: Societal Harm as a Prerequisite for Criminal Liability
-
But see
-
But see Robinson, A Theory of Justification: Societal Harm as a Prerequisite for Criminal Liability, 23 UCLA L. Rev. 261 (1975).
-
(1975)
UCLA L. Rev
, vol.23
, pp. 261
-
-
Robinson1
-
32
-
-
38849109450
-
-
Thus my hypothetical does not involve overdetermination. In my original hypothetical, were Smith aware of Jones's plan, he probably would have two sufficient motives for assault. Presumably, if either of the defendant's motives for assault falls under a justification, the defense should be available. But some requirements for the use of justifications are more stringent. A few commentators refer to the defendant's “dominant motivation.” See, note 16
-
Thus my hypothetical does not involve overdetermination. In my original hypothetical, were Smith aware of Jones's plan, he probably would have two sufficient motives for assault. Presumably, if either of the defendant's motives for assault falls under a justification, the defense should be available. But some requirements for the use of justifications are more stringent. A few commentators refer to the defendant's “dominant motivation.” See W. Lafave & F. Scott, supra note 16, at 207.
-
supra
, pp. 207
-
-
Lafave, W.1
Scott, F.2
-
33
-
-
0347936732
-
-
California requires that some such defenses be available only if the defendant acts “under the influence of such fears alone.” See, Sec. 198
-
California requires that some such defenses be available only if the defendant acts “under the influence of such fears alone.” See Cal. Penal Code, Sec. 198 (1970).
-
(1970)
Cal. Penal Code
-
-
-
34
-
-
85081829973
-
-
LaFave and Scott endorse the puzzling view that the availability of a justification is dependent upon “objective facts,” but immediately contradict this conclusion by adding: “This does not mean, of course, that the defense can be manufactured after the event by resort to facts not known to the actor when he engaged in the conduct., note 16
-
LaFave and Scott endorse the puzzling view that the availability of a justification is dependent upon “objective facts,” but immediately contradict this conclusion by adding: “This does not mean, of course, that the defense can be manufactured after the event by resort to facts not known to the actor when he engaged in the conduct.” Supra note 16, at 206-07.
-
Supra
, pp. 206-207
-
-
-
35
-
-
85081826024
-
-
describes, not as motive but “purpose.”
-
Robinson describes “justificatory intent” not as motive but “purpose.”
-
justificatory intent
-
-
Robinson1
-
37
-
-
85081828795
-
-
There is a great deal of debate among commentators about how many excusing conditions involve nonvoluntary behavior. Robinson contends thata condition does not excuse unless “the act constituting the offense is not the product of a meaningful choice.
-
There is a great deal of debate among commentators about how many excusing conditions involve nonvoluntary behavior. Robinson contends thata condition does not excuse unless “the act constituting the offense is not the product of a meaningful choice.” Id., at 223, n. 1.
-
Id
, Issue.1
, pp. 223
-
-
-
38
-
-
0004260399
-
-
See the insightful discussion of voluntariness as a “variable concept” in
-
See the insightful discussion of voluntariness as a “variable concept” in J. Feinberg, Harm to Self 117-24 (1986).
-
(1986)
Harm to Self
, pp. 117-124
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
39
-
-
34547574288
-
Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law
-
Some commentators tentatively suggest that excusing conditions not be publicized, so that resolve to comply with the law is not weakened. See
-
Some commentators tentatively suggest that excusing conditions not be publicized, so that resolve to comply with the law is not weakened. See Dan-Cohen, Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, 97 Harv. L. Rev. 625 (1984).
-
(1984)
Harv. L. Rev
, vol.97
, pp. 625
-
-
Dan-Cohen1
-
40
-
-
84928224205
-
Paradoxes in Legal Thought
-
See
-
See Fletcher, Paradoxes in Legal Thought, 85 Col. L. Rev. 1263, 1283 (1985).
-
(1985)
Col. L. Rev
, vol.85
, pp. 1263-1283
-
-
Fletcher1
|