메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 63, Issue 4, 2001, Pages 637-661

The ambivalence of political courage

(1)  Scorza, Jason A a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 2642554561     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500032113     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (7)

References (63)
  • 1
    • 0004127377 scopus 로고
    • For instance, Montesquieu rebukes the laws of Sparta, writing, "Lycurgus, whose institutions were harsh, did not have civility as an object when he formed the manners; he had in view the bellicose spirit he wanted to give his people" (The Spirit of the Laws [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989], p. 319). Albert O. Hirschman usefully illuminates the development of the distinction between calm and violent passions in the liberal tradition. See (Princeton: Princeton University Press) , esp
    • For instance, Montesquieu rebukes the laws of Sparta, writing, "Lycurgus, whose institutions were harsh, did not have civility as an object when he formed the manners; he had in view the bellicose spirit he wanted to give his people" (The Spirit of the Laws [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989], p. 319). Albert O. Hirschman usefully illuminates the development of the distinction between calm and violent passions in the liberal tradition. See Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977), esp. pp. 63-66.
    • (1977) The Passions and the Interests , pp. 63-66
    • Hirschman1
  • 2
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance, see (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • For instance, see Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996);
    • (1996) Democracy and Disagreement
    • Gutmann, A.1    Thompson, D.2
  • 5
    • 84972625995 scopus 로고
    • Constrained discourse and public life
    • J. Donald Moon, "Constrained Discourse and Public Life," Political Theory 19 (1991): 202-29;
    • (1991) Political Theory , vol.19 , pp. 202-29
    • Donald Moon, J.1
  • 6
    • 84974220501 scopus 로고
    • Pluralism and reasonable disagreement
    • and
    • and Charles Larmore, "Pluralism and Reasonable Disagreement," Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (1994): 61-79.
    • (1994) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.11 , pp. 61-79
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 7
    • 0003532171 scopus 로고
    • For feminist critiques of manliness and aggressiveness in politics, see (New York: Basic Books, Inc.)
    • For feminist critiques of manliness and aggressiveness in politics, see Jean Bethke Elshtain, Women and War (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1987);
    • (1987) Women and War
    • Bethke Elshtain, J.1
  • 8
    • 84900714354 scopus 로고
    • Citizenship and armed civic virtue: Some critical questions on the commitment to public life
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Elshtain, "Citizenship and Armed Civic Virtue: Some Critical Questions on the Commitment to Public Life," in Community in America (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988), pp. 47-55;
    • (1988) Community in America , pp. 47-55
    • Elshtain1
  • 10
    • 0004152399 scopus 로고
    • See (Chicago: University of Chicago Press) . Arendt's view of courage is sometimes improperly conflated with a Nietzschean will to power
    • See Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), pp. 35-36. Arendt's view of courage is sometimes improperly conflated with a Nietzschean will to power.
    • (1958) The Human Condition , pp. 35-36
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 11
    • 0011545083 scopus 로고
    • What Is Freedom?
    • New York: The Viking Press, esp.
    • For a clarification of this misunderstanding see Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" in Between Past and Future (New York: The Viking Press, 1968), esp. p. 156.
    • (1968) Between Past and Future , pp. 156
    • Arendt1
  • 12
    • 0007346893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Liberalism of Fear
    • See, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • See Judith Shklar, "The Liberalism of Fear," in Political Thought and Political Thinkers (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Political Thought and Political Thinkers
    • Shklar, J.1
  • 13
    • 84856243454 scopus 로고
    • See, London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Browne, Green, and Longman
    • See Jeremy Bentham, Deontology (London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Browne, Green, and Longman, 1834), p. 251.
    • (1834) Deontology , pp. 251
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 15
    • 77956252716 scopus 로고
    • The Artist's Reward
    • Strictly speaking, this is Hemingway's definition of "guts". Attributed to Hemingway by, (30 November)
    • Strictly speaking, this is Hemingway's definition of "guts". Attributed to Hemingway by Dorothy Parker, "The Artist's Reward," The New Yorker (30 November 1929).
    • (1929) The New Yorker
    • Parker, D.1
  • 16
    • 0004089787 scopus 로고
    • For discussion of operational definitions of courage employed by clinical and experimental psychologists, see, 2nd ed. New York: W. H. Freeman and Company
    • For discussion of operational definitions of courage employed by clinical and experimental psychologists, see Stanley Rachman, Fear and Courage, 2nd ed. (New York: W. H. Freeman and Company, 1990).
    • (1990) Fear and Courage
    • Rachman, S.1
  • 17
    • 0004196970 scopus 로고
    • For an analysis of the philosophical meaning of courage, see (Berkeley: University of California Press)
    • For an analysis of the philosophical meaning of courage, see Douglas N. Walton, Courage; A Philosophical Investigation (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986);
    • (1986) Courage; A Philosophical Investigation
    • Douglas, N.1    Walton2
  • 19
    • 0003868532 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Peter Geach, The Virtues (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977);
    • (1977) The Virtues
    • Geach, P.1
  • 20
    • 0004290120 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press, esp. chap. 3;
    • James D. Wallace, Virtues and Vice (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1978), esp. chap. 3;
    • (1978) Virtues and Vice
    • James, D.1    Wallace2
  • 22
    • 77954079534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Socrates displayed courage as a soldier (by saving the life of Alcibiades during the battle of Delium); as an officeholder (by opposing the unconstitutional trial of thestrategoi while taking his turn presiding over the Athenian council); and as an ordinary citizen (first, by refusing to participate in the assassination of Leon of Salamis and, later, by refusing to abandon or renounce his philosophical explorations)
    • Socrates displayed courage as a soldier (by saving the life of Alcibiades during the battle of Delium); as an officeholder (by opposing the unconstitutional trial of thestrategoi while taking his turn presiding over the Athenian council); and as an ordinary citizen (first, by refusing to participate in the assassination of Leon of Salamis and, later, by refusing to abandon or renounce his philosophical explorations).
  • 23
    • 77954054846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Plato's accounts of the courage of Socrates see Laches 187e-188; The Apology 28e-29a
    • For Plato's accounts of the courage of Socrates see Laches 187e-188; The Apology 28e-29a;
  • 24
    • 84972168208 scopus 로고
    • Courage and Comedy in Plato's Laches
    • and Symposium 219a-221b. For discussion of Plato's own view of courage, see
    • and Symposium 219a-221b. For discussion of Plato's own view of courage, seeAristide Tessitore, "Courage and Comedy in Plato's Laches," journal of Politics 56 (1994): 115-133
    • (1994) Journal of Politics , vol.56 , pp. 115-133
    • Tessitore, A.1
  • 25
    • 77954076408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The word courage is derived from the French word cceur ("heart"), and was, perhaps, originally associated with chivalry. Other names for courage have different derivations and connotations. For instance, "bravery" comes from the Italian word bravo (a thug or hired assassin). Some philosophers still make something of these distinctions. Walton, for instance, suggests that courage stripped of its lofty purpose and normative content is mere bravery. See Walton, Courage, p. 98. However, in ordinary usage, the differences between the various names for courage have become indistinct, even as our thinking about the nature of courage has become muddied. The question of what, exactly, courage is, and whether courage can be said to have strong normative content, has been reopened. This question cannot be closed merely by reference to etymology
    • The word courage is derived from the French word cceur ("heart"), and was, perhaps, originally associated with chivalry. Other names for courage have different derivations and connotations. For instance, "bravery" comes from the Italian word bravo (a thug or hired assassin). Some philosophers still make something of these distinctions. Walton, for instance, suggests that courage stripped of its lofty purpose and normative content is mere bravery. See Walton, Courage, p. 98. However, in ordinary usage, the differences between the various names for courage have become indistinct, even as our thinking about the nature of courage has become muddied. The question of what, exactly, courage is, and whether courage can be said to have strong normative content, has been reopened. This question cannot be closed merely by reference to etymology.
  • 26
    • 0346711477 scopus 로고
    • This problem was identified by Thomas Hobbes, who explained, in a protoliberal moment, how the passion of courage-defined as sudden anger -along with the kindred passions of honor and glory, could be used by political leaders to overcome the rational self-interest of citizens to avoid civil discord. See (New York: Viking Penguin, Inc.), 157
    • This problem was identified by Thomas Hobbes, who explained, in a protoliberal moment, how the passion of courage-defined as "sudden anger"-along with the kindred passions of honor and glory, could be used by political leaders to overcome the rational self-interest of citizens to avoid civil discord. See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan [1651] (New York: Viking Penguin, Inc., 1968), pp. 123,157.
    • (1968) Leviathan [1651] , pp. 123
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 27
    • 77954067197 scopus 로고
    • The two faces of courage
    • As Amelie Rorty explains, "Psychologically, the magnetizing dispositions of courage typically diminish the force of other highly desirable categorical dispositions" [Boston: Beacon Press]
    • As Amelie Rorty explains, "Psychologically, the magnetizing dispositions of courage typically diminish the force of other highly desirable categorical dispositions" (Rorty, "The Two Faces of Courage," inMind in Action [Boston: Beacon Press, 1988], p. 301).
    • (1988) Mind in Action , pp. 301
    • Rorty1
  • 28
    • 77954048511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Montesquieu writes: L'heroisme que la Morale avoue ne touche que peu de gens. C'est l'heroisme qui derruit la Morale qui nous frappe et cause notre admiration", Oeuvres Completes, ed. Roger Caillois [Paris: Bibliotheque de la Pleiade 1949] . ["The heroism that morality favors does not affect that many people. It is the heroism that destroys morality that affects us and causes our admiration."]
    • Montesquieu writes: "L'heroisme que la Morale avoue ne touche que peu de gens. C'est l'heroisme qui derruit la Morale qui nous frappe et cause notre admiration"(Montesquieu, "Mes Pensees," Oeuvres Completes, ed. Roger Caillois [Paris: Bibliotheque de la Pleiade, 1949], 1:1305). ["The heroism that morality favors does not affect that many people. It is the heroism that destroys morality that affects us and causes our admiration."]
    • Mes Pensees , vol.1 , pp. 1305
    • Montesquieu1
  • 29
    • 0003750156 scopus 로고
    • See, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 217-222
    • (1991) Liberal Purposes , pp. 217-222
    • Galston, W.1
  • 31
    • 0347432544 scopus 로고
    • The priority of democracy to philosophy
    • ed. Merrill Peterson and Robert Vaughan (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press)
    • Richard Rorty, "The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy," in The Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom, ed. Merrill Peterson and Robert Vaughan (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1988), 269.
    • (1988) The Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom , vol.269
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 32
    • 84937260800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The land of the fearful and the free
    • Shklar's account of fear has been criticized for being limited and onesided. For instance, it has been suggested that she focuses on the fear of state oppression to the exclusion of the equally common fear of being stateless. See
    • Shklar's account of fear has been criticized for being limited and onesided. For instance, it has been suggested that she focuses on the fear of state oppression to the exclusion of the equally common fear of being stateless. See Yael Tamir, "The Land of the Fearful and the Free," Constellations 3 (1997): 296-314.
    • (1997) Constellations , vol.3 , pp. 296-314
    • Tamir, Y.1
  • 33
    • 0004027519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Shklar, Ordinary Vices (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984), p. 8.
    • (1984) Ordinary Vices , pp. 8
    • Shklar1
  • 34
    • 77954052750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition to obvious violations of human rights by totalitarian regimes (e.g., the political use of torture and murder), we can understand this to include cruelties performed by ostensibly liberal regimes {e.g., systematic discrimination against, and intimidation of, members of minority groups)
    • In addition to obvious violations of human rights by totalitarian regimes (e.g., the political use of torture and murder), we can understand this to include cruelties performed by ostensibly liberal regimes {e.g., systematic discrimination against, and intimidation of, members of minority groups).
  • 35
    • 77954073314 scopus 로고
    • See. Previously published in Nancy Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See Judith Shklar, "The Liberalism of Fear," p. 11. Previously published in Nancy Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989).
    • (1989) The Liberalism of Fear , pp. 11
    • Shklar, J.1
  • 40
    • 84945962607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 242
    • Ordinary Vices , Ibid., pp. 5, 242.
    • Ordinary Vices , pp. 5
  • 41
    • 77954055335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 23-24
    • Ibid., pp. 23-24.
  • 42
    • 77954058872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shklar's admiration for Montaigne is due, in no small part, to his identification of cruelty and torture as the foremost human evils. Like Shklar, Montaigne associates cruelty with cowardice, although he is much harsher in his declamation of cowardice than is Shklar. See, trans. M. A. Screech (New York: Penguin Classics)
    • Shklar's admiration for Montaigne is due, in no small part, to his identification of cruelty and torture as the foremost human evils. Like Shklar, Montaigne associates cruelty with cowardice, although he is much harsher in his declamation of cowardice than is Shklar. See Michel De Montaigne, The Complete Essays, trans. M. A. Screech (New York: Penguin Classics), II: 27.
    • The Complete Essays , vol.2 , pp. 27
    • De Montaigne, M.1
  • 45
    • 77954074089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other liberal theorists either have been less attentive to this problem or have found a way around it. For instance, Galston does not share Shklar's nervousness when theorizing about virtue from a liberal point of view, although he does acknowledge that the virtues needed by liberalism may "come into conflict with other powerful tendencies in liberal life" (Galston, Liberal Purposes, pp. 217-22.)
    • Other liberal theorists either have been less attentive to this problem or have found a way around it. For instance, Galston does not share Shklar's nervousness when theorizing about virtue from a liberal point of view, although he does acknowledge that the virtues needed by liberalism may "come into conflict with other powerful tendencies in liberal life" (Galston, Liberal Purposes, pp. 217-22.)
  • 46
    • 77954072818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Herodotus, Herodotus, trans. A.D. Godley (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957), V. 78.
    • See Herodotus, Herodotus, trans. A.D. Godley (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957), V. 78.
  • 47
    • 77954059569 scopus 로고
    • Song of Harmodius
    • See (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press) trans. J. M. Edmonds
    • See Callistratus, "Song of Harmodius," inLyra Graeca, trans. J. M. Edmonds (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1927), III.
    • (1927) Lyra Graeca
    • Callistratus1
  • 49
    • 0003987202 scopus 로고
    • trans. C.E Smith (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, trans. C.E Smith (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), II.43.1.
    • (1991) History of the Peloponnesian War , pp. 431
    • Thucydides1
  • 50
    • 0004312936 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press bk. 1.23
    • Cicero, De Officiis (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), bk. 1.23.
    • (1990) De Officiis
    • Cicero1
  • 52
    • 77954045819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. I. 9
    • Ibid., I. 9.
  • 53
    • 77954081803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance, public opinion surveys reveal that American citizens still perceive courage to be an important quality of political leadership. One recent national survey found that 82.7 percent of Americans believe that courage is an extremely important or very important characteristic of leaders, while only 3.4 percent believe courage to be either not very important or not important at all. Courage ranked higher than charisma, forcefulness, and religiousness, but slightly below good judgement, honesty, and fairness. See Institute for Research in Social Science, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA Today Study Number 3023 (May 1987)
    • For instance, public opinion surveys reveal that American citizens still perceive courage to be an important quality of political leadership. One recent national survey found that 82.7 percent of Americans believe that courage is an extremely important or very important characteristic of leaders, while only 3.4 percent believe courage to be either not very important or not important at all. Courage ranked higher than charisma, forcefulness, and religiousness, but slightly below good judgement, honesty, and fairness. See Institute for Research in Social Science, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA Today Study Number 3023 (May 1987).
  • 55
    • 77954079789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Kennedy sometimes refers to the responsible and unselfish officeholder as conscientious. I prefer to reserve this term to describe persons who follow their personal moral principles rather than official duties which can, themselves, be inconsistent with these principles
    • Although Kennedy sometimes refers to the responsible and unselfish officeholder as "conscientious," I prefer to reserve this term to describe persons who follow their personal moral principles rather than official duties which can, themselves, be inconsistent with these principles.
  • 56
    • 77954042250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider Arendt's account of the centrality of courage to political life. Arendt writes "The connotation of courage, which we now feel to be an indispensable quality of the hero, is in fact already present in a willingness to act and speak at all, to insert one's self into the world and begin a story of one's own" (Human Condition, p. 186)
    • Consider Arendt's account of the centrality of courage to political life. Arendt writes, "The connotation of courage, which we now feel to be an indispensable quality of the hero, is in fact already present in a willingness to act and speak at all, to insert one's self into the world and begin a story of one's own" (Human Condition, p. 186).
  • 58
    • 0003531148 scopus 로고
    • This transformation resembles the disillusionment experienced by many ex-communists during the 1930s and 1940s, as the extent of Stalin's betrayal of their idealistic vision of the revolutionary workers' state became clear. See New York: Harper and Row, Publishers
    • This transformation resembles the disillusionment experienced by many ex-communists during the 1930s and 1940s, as the extent of Stalin's betrayal of their idealistic vision of the revolutionary workers' state became clear. See Andre Gide, Richard Wright, Ignazio Silone et al., The God That Failed (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1950).
    • (1950) The God That Failed
    • Gide, A.1    Wright, R.2    Silone, I.3
  • 59
    • 77954060509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recall the confrontations between police and veterans groups during the 1972 Republican National Convention in Miami, Florida
    • Recall the confrontations between police and veterans groups during the 1972 Republican National Convention in Miami, Florida.
  • 60
    • 77954081244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that some of the most ardent anti-communists had once been communists themselves. See James Burnham's preface to the 1960 re-print of The Managerial Revolution (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1960)
    • It is worth noting that some of the most ardent anti-communists had once been communists themselves. See James Burnham's preface to the 1960 re-print of The Managerial Revolution (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1960).
  • 61
    • 77954063014 scopus 로고
    • "The Fugitive Slave Law, Address to Citizens of Concord, 3 May 1851"; And "the Fugitive Slave Law, Lecture in New York City, 7 March 1854,"
    • Emerson made at least two public speeches condemning what he called "Mr. Webster's treachery". See (Boston: Houghton Mifflin)
    • Emerson made at least two public speeches condemning what he called "Mr. Webster's treachery". See Emerson, "The Fugitive Slave Law, Address to Citizens of Concord, 3 May 1851"; and "The Fugitive Slave Law, Lecture in New York City, 7 March 1854," in Complete Works (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1903-1904), 11:181.
    • (1903) Complete Works , vol.11 , pp. 181
    • Emerson1
  • 62
    • 77954078755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Brown: Salem Speech, January 6,1860
    • ibid.
    • Emerson, "John Brown: Salem Speech, January 6,1860," ibid., p. 280.
    • Complete Works , pp. 280
    • Emerson1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.