메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 3, 2005, Pages 397-425

Locke on language in (civil) society

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 25844433874     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (18)

References (193)
  • 1
    • 25844439583 scopus 로고
    • The main thesis of Locke's semantic theory
    • Some notable examples are: Norman Kretzmann, 'The Main Thesis of Locke's Semantic Theory', The Philosophical Review, 77 (1968), pp. 175-96;
    • (1968) The Philosophical Review , vol.77 , pp. 175-196
    • Kretzmann, N.1
  • 2
    • 79956393099 scopus 로고
    • Leibniz on Locke on language
    • Minneapolis
    • Hans Aarsleff, 'Leibniz on Locke on Language', in From Locke to Saussure (Minneapolis, 1982), pp. 42-83;
    • (1982) From Locke to Saussure , pp. 42-83
    • Aarsleff, H.1
  • 4
    • 25844522747 scopus 로고
    • Locke's theory of meaning
    • ed. Richard Ashcraft London and New York
    • Charles Landesman, 'Locke's Theory of Meaning', in John Locke: Critical Assessments, ed. Richard Ashcraft (London and New York, 1991), Vol. IV, pp. 218-34;
    • (1991) John Locke: Critical Assessments , vol.4 , pp. 218-234
    • Landesman, C.1
  • 5
    • 25844439353 scopus 로고
    • Locke on meaning and signification
    • ed. G.A.J. Rogers Oxford
    • Michael Losonsky, 'Locke on Meaning and Signification', in Locke's Philosophy: Content and Context, ed. G.A.J. Rogers (Oxford, 1994), pp. 123-41;
    • (1994) Locke's Philosophy: Content and Context , pp. 123-141
    • Losonsky, M.1
  • 10
    • 25844502512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Measuring locke's shadow
    • John Locke, ed. Ian Shapiro Yale
    • See John Dunn, 'Measuring Locke's Shadow', in John Locke, Two Treatises of Government and a Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. Ian Shapiro (Yale, 2003), pp. 257-85, for a critique of the quest for a unified Locke.
    • (2003) Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration , pp. 257-285
    • Dunn, J.1
  • 11
    • 25844509304 scopus 로고
    • The social language of John Locke: A study in the history of ideas
    • ed. Richard Ashcraft 4 vols., London
    • There has been some work done on the relationship between language and society in Locke, notably: Rosalie L. Colie, 'The Social Language of John Locke: A Study in the History of Ideas', in John Locke: Critical Assessments, ed. Richard Ashcraft (4 vols., London, 1991), Vol. IV, pp. 259-80;
    • (1991) John Locke: Critical Assessments , vol.4 , pp. 259-280
    • Colie, R.L.1
  • 12
    • 0041768901 scopus 로고
    • Prince Maurice's rational parrot: Civil discourse in Locke's essay
    • Peter Walmsley, 'Prince Maurice's Rational Parrot: Civil Discourse in Locke's Essay', Eighteenth Century Studies, 28 (4) (1995), pp. 413-25.
    • (1995) Eighteenth Century Studies , vol.28 , Issue.4 , pp. 413-425
    • Walmsley, P.1
  • 13
    • 25844508387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • While Locke has many interesting things to say about names of simple sensations and of natural substances, and some of them very much at odds with what he says about names of non-natural things, for the most part these lie outside the social scope of this paper - except in two regards: first, they can provide an illuminating contrast to the non-natural names; second, some substance terms, particularly 'man', are involved in social discourse (on this difficult issue see note 95 below).
  • 14
    • 25844443748 scopus 로고
    • ed. Peter H. Nidditch Oxford, III.v.16
    • He admits as much in John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford, 1975), p. 437 (III.v.16); Cf. III.v which is entitled 'Of the Names of mixed Modes and Relations', but talks only about mixed modes, revealing Locke's inclusion of relations in this category.
    • (1975) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , pp. 437
    • Locke, J.1
  • 15
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.iv.6
    • Given that for Locke, as for his contemporaries, words signify thoughts or ideas, 'ideas' and 'meanings' come to the same thing. For example, Locke, Essay, p. 422 (III.iv.6): 'the meaning of words, being only the ideas they are made to stand for by him that uses them'.
    • Essay , pp. 422
    • Locke1
  • 16
    • 3643135991 scopus 로고
    • ed. R.C. Alston Menston, [1702]
    • Cf. John Kersey, A New English Dictionary, ed. R.C. Alston (Menston, 1969 [1702]), wherein 'to mean' is explicated as 'to purpose, to understand, or to signify';
    • (1969) A New English Dictionary
    • Kersey, J.1
  • 17
    • 0039430994 scopus 로고
    • London
    • John Sergeant, The Method to Science (London, 1696), p. 3: 'The words Notion, Simple Apprehension, Conception, and Meaning, are all synonymous terms'.
    • (1696) The Method to Science , pp. 3
    • Sergeant, J.1
  • 18
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.ii.2
    • Locke, Essay, p. 405 (II.ii.2).
    • Essay , pp. 405
    • Locke1
  • 19
    • 25844477564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.1
    • Ibid., p. 405 (III.ii.1).
    • Essay , pp. 405
  • 20
    • 25844523829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.i.5
    • Ibid., p. 403 (III.i.5).
    • Essay , pp. 403
  • 21
    • 4344664269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.7
    • Ibid., p. 408 (III.ii.7).
    • Essay , pp. 408
  • 22
    • 25844490453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.7
    • Ibid., pp. 407-8 (III.ii.7).
    • Essay , pp. 407-408
  • 23
    • 25844456949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.21
    • Ibid., p. 488 (III.ix.21).
    • Essay , pp. 488
  • 24
    • 71449111965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chs. 6 and 9
    • For a fuller analysis of Locke's concerns about the dominance of language and the context to which they were a response see Dawson, Locke, Language and Early-Modern Philosophy, Chs. 6 and 9.
    • Locke, Language and Early-modern Philosophy
    • Dawson1
  • 25
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IV.iii.6
    • Locke, Essay, pp. 541-2 (IV.iii.6).
    • Essay , pp. 541-542
    • Locke1
  • 26
    • 25844498860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.21
    • Ibid., p. 502 (III.x.21).
    • Essay , pp. 502
  • 27
    • 25844498856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.14
    • Ibid., p. 497 (III.x.14).
    • Essay , pp. 497
  • 28
    • 25844490014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.5
    • Ibid., p. 407 (III.ii.5).
    • Essay , pp. 407
  • 30
    • 25844471613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Locke and his contemporaries may not have been clear on this terminological distinction (and while his contemporaries did describe language as a 'contract'), I use the term 'compact' to distinguish it from a 'contract'. Whereas a 'contract' is a technical legal term, enforceable by positive law, a 'compact' is just a synonym for an agreement. In the case of language, it signifies an informal, tacit agreement enforceable only by reciprocal expectation (and natural law) that entails reciprocal obligation and benefits. I am very grateful to James Murphy for helping me to clarify contemporary use of 'contract', 'compact' and 'trust'.
  • 32
    • 0039429512 scopus 로고
    • Trust and political agency
    • Cambridge
    • Cf. Dunn, 'Trust and Political Agency', in Interpreting Political Responsibility: Essays 1981-1989 (Cambridge, 1990), pp. 26-44, p. 34 on betrayal being ineluctably the other side of the coin.
    • (1990) Interpreting Political Responsibility: Essays 1981-1989 , pp. 26-44
  • 34
    • 0242641738 scopus 로고
    • Some theories of a natural language from the renaissance to the seventeenth century
    • Wiesbaden
    • Marie-Luce Demonet establishes that there was a broad consensus in the sixteenth century that the relationship between language and meaning was arbitrary. A sweeping look at seventeenth-century texts indicates that the consensus held. By contrast, many commentators have emphasized beliefs in a natural link between sign and signified, in particular with reference to Adamicism, Plato's Cratylus, Hermeticism and the Cabbala. Notable among these commentators are: Allison Coudert, 'Some Theories of a Natural Language from the Renaissance to the Seventeenth Century', in Magi Naturalis und die Entstehung der modernen Natur Wissenschaften (Wiesbaden, 1978), pp. 56-114;
    • (1978) Magi Naturalis und Die Entstehung der Modernen Natur Wissenschaften , pp. 56-114
    • Coudert, A.1
  • 35
    • 25844507107 scopus 로고
    • Forgotten ways of knowing: The Kabbalah, language and science in the seventeenth century
    • ed. Donald R. Kelley and Richard H. Popkin Dordrecht
    • Allison Coudert, 'Forgotten Ways of Knowing: The Kabbalah, Language and Science in the Seventeenth Century', in Shapes of Knowledge from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment, ed. Donald R. Kelley and Richard H. Popkin (Dordrecht, 1991), pp. 83-99;
    • (1991) Shapes of Knowledge from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment , pp. 83-99
    • Coudert, A.1
  • 37
    • 0040272160 scopus 로고
    • The language of Adam in seventeenth-century England
    • ed. Hugh Lloyd-Jones, Valerie Pearl and Blair Worden London
    • David S. Katz, 'The Language of Adam in Seventeenth-Century England', in History and Imagination: Essays in Honour of H.R. Trevor-Roper, ed. Hugh Lloyd-Jones, Valerie Pearl and Blair Worden (London, 1981), pp. 132-45;
    • (1981) History and Imagination: Essays in Honour of H.R. Trevor-Roper , pp. 132-145
    • Katz, D.S.1
  • 39
    • 0003934483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in Francis Bacon: the Oxford Authors, ed. B. Vickers Oxford
    • Francis Bacon, The Advancement of Learning, in Francis Bacon: The Oxford Authors, ed. B. Vickers (Oxford, 1996), pp. 120-299, p. 231.
    • (1996) The Advancement of Learning , pp. 120-299
    • Bacon, F.1
  • 40
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.1
    • Locke, Essay, p. 405 (III.ii.1).
    • Essay , pp. 405
    • Locke1
  • 41
    • 25844513603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.vii.51
    • Ibid., pp. 470-1 (III.vii.51);
    • Essay , pp. 470-471
  • 42
    • 4344664269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.8
    • Essay, p. 408 (III.ii.8).
    • Essay , pp. 408
  • 43
    • 4344664269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.8
    • Ibid., p. 408 (III.ii.8). In Part IV we shall see that, while personal and public use ought to converge, Locke was concerned that in fact people still individually determine what ideas words stand for, with the effect that common use often turns out to be little more than a collection of disparate individual uses. The very existence of the semantic compact is therefore called into question. For the moment, however, I am dealing with the law of propriety in the existent way that Locke frequently presents it - as a fixed and accessible standard that arbitrarily links certain words to certain ideas (of any kind, sensible as well as insensible, simple as well as complex) to which people are bound to conform.
    • Essay , pp. 408
  • 44
    • 25844443471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.vi.45
    • Ibid., p. 467 (III.vi.45);
    • Essay , pp. 467
  • 45
    • 25844488152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.8
    • Essay, p. 479 (III.ix.8).
    • Essay , pp. 479
  • 48
    • 25844527368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. R. Tuck Cambridge
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. R. Tuck (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 28-9.
    • (1996) Leviathan , pp. 28-29
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 50
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.xi.11
    • Locke, Essay, p. 514 (III.xi.11).
    • Essay , pp. 514
    • Locke1
  • 51
    • 25844456652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.31
    • Ibid., p. 506(III.x.31).
    • Essay , pp. 506
  • 52
    • 6344266495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • I am grateful to Janet Coleman for pointing out the many continuities between Augustine and Locke. On Augustine's view that conventional language is grounded in trust and on his more general characterization of humans as 'creatures of trust' see Janet Coleman, A History of Political Thought From Ancient Greece to Early Christianity (Oxford, 2000), pp. 317-18.
    • (2000) A History of Political Thought from Ancient Greece to Early Christianity , pp. 317-318
    • Coleman, J.1
  • 54
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.19
    • Locke, Essay, p. 501 (III.x.19)
    • Essay , pp. 501
    • Locke1
  • 55
    • 25844509903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.3
    • explains that 'the word Gold (which by standing for a more or less perfect collection of simple ideas, serves to design that sort of body well enough in civil discourse)'. On the distinction between the 'civil' and 'philosophical' uses of words see ibid., p. 476 (III.ix.3);
    • Essay , pp. 476
  • 56
    • 25844438381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.15
    • Essay, p. 484 (III.ix.15).
    • Essay , pp. 484
  • 57
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Classical Roman rhetoric had five parts: invention, disposition (following the Ramist reforms, both of these were appropriated by logic), elocution (the figures and the tropes), memory (this increasingly became an art of its own, as well as suffering a demise with the advent of printing), pronunciation (this too became less of a concern in the context of printing, although spoken oratory, for example in the pulpit, remained hugely important). On the specialization of rhetoric see Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 55-65.
    • (1996) Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes , pp. 55-65
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 58
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.34
    • Locke, Essay, p. 508 (III.x.34). Strictly speaking, only tropes (e.g. metaphors) involve a change in word meaning. Figures are 'shapes' of speech (e.g. antithesis). However, 'figurative' increasingly became not only an umbrella term but also a term to denote the tropes, to the extent that 'tropical' has now fallen out of use almost completely and been replaced by 'figurative'.
    • Essay , pp. 508
    • Locke1
  • 62
    • 0008598251 scopus 로고
    • trans. M.A. Screech Harmondsworth
    • Michel de Montaigne, The Complete Essays, trans. M.A. Screech (Harmondsworth, 1991), p. 341.
    • (1991) The Complete Essays , pp. 341
    • De Montaigne, M.1
  • 63
    • 25844481574 scopus 로고
    • ed. Jackson I. Cope and Harold Whitmore Jones London
    • Thomas Sprat, History of the Royal Society, ed. Jackson I. Cope and Harold Whitmore Jones (London, 1959), p. 112.
    • (1959) History of the Royal Society , pp. 112
    • Sprat, T.1
  • 64
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.34
    • Locke, Essay, p. 508 (III.x.34).
    • Essay , pp. 508
    • Locke1
  • 65
    • 25844520793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.34
    • Ibid., p. 508 (III.x.34).
    • Essay , pp. 508
  • 66
    • 25844496991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.5
    • Ibid., p. 492 (III.x.5).
    • Essay , pp. 492
  • 67
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.5
    • Locke is specifically talking about the names of complex ideas, which, as we shall see in Part IV, are, being voluntarily composed, liable to inadvertent semantic alteration, so that the very idea of common use fades as a possibility. Here, however, Locke is making a different point. While the pliability of complex ideas doubtless plays its part, Locke is concerned about a situation where the speaker wilfully makes a word stand sometimes for the complex idea that common use dictates and sometimes for ideas that ought to be represented by different words. The abuse recalls the fallacies or sophisms of logic, whereby a false point is proved by putting an ambiguous word as the middle term, making it stand for one thing in the first proposition and another in the second, such as 'dog' which is both an animal and a star. That Locke has this kind of thing in mind is confirmed when he complains that 'in arguings, and learned contests, the same sort of proceeding passes commonly for wit and learning' (Locke, Essay, p. 493 (III.x.5)).
    • Essay , pp. 493
    • Locke1
  • 68
    • 25844471043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.5
    • Ibid., pp. 492-3 (III.x.5).
    • Essay , pp. 492-493
  • 76
    • 0003691257 scopus 로고
    • ed. Peter Laslett Cambridge
    • Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge, 1988), p. 412.
    • (1988) Two Treatises of Government , pp. 412
    • Locke1
  • 80
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxxii.15
    • Locke, Essay, p. 389 (II.xxxii.15).
    • Essay , pp. 389
    • Locke1
  • 81
    • 25844465829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I.iii.6
    • Ibid., p. 69 (I.iii.6).
    • Essay , pp. 69
  • 82
    • 84880148006 scopus 로고
    • ed. James H. Tully Indianapolis
    • Locke, A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. James H. Tully (Indianapolis, 1983), p. 25.
    • (1983) A Letter Concerning Toleration , pp. 25
    • Locke1
  • 85
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxii.9
    • Locke, Essay, p. 292 (II.xxii.9).
    • Essay , pp. 292
    • Locke1
  • 86
    • 25844453549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IV.iii.20
    • Ibid., p. 552 (IV.iii.20).
    • Essay , pp. 552
  • 87
    • 25844480839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay, 552, Ibid.
    • Essay , pp. 552
  • 88
    • 60949310559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxvii.22
    • However, my interpretation of Locke's analysis of linguistic self-delusion that nevertheless does not exculpate the believer does not square easily with what Locke says about personal identity and responsibility: a person is only responsible on the day of judgment for that of which he is conscious (Essay, pp. 343-4 (II.xxvii.22)).
    • Essay , pp. 343-344
  • 91
    • 0004324399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 325, 332, 337, 406, 350.
    • Two Treatises , pp. 325
  • 95
  • 99
  • 101
    • 25844441036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. G.R.F. Ferrari, trans. Tom Griffith Cambridge, 351c-d
    • Plato, The Republic, ed. G.R.F. Ferrari, trans. Tom Griffith (Cambridge, 2000), p. 32 (351c-d).
    • (2000) The Republic , pp. 32
    • Plato1
  • 102
    • 0040909304 scopus 로고
    • trans. intro. John O'Meara Harmondsworth
    • Locke could also have in mind Augustine's characterization of criminal gangs as 'bound by a compact' (Concerning The City of God Against the Pagans, trans. Henry Bettenson, intro. John O'Meara (Harmondsworth, 1984), p. 139).
    • (1984) Concerning the City of God Against the Pagans , pp. 139
    • Bettenson, H.1
  • 103
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I.iii.2
    • Locke, Essay, p. 66 (I.iii.2).
    • Essay , pp. 66
    • Locke1
  • 105
    • 84904936829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 49.
    • A Letter , pp. 49
  • 106
    • 25844482595 scopus 로고
    • ed. E.S. de Beer 8 vols., Oxford
    • Locke, The Correspondence, ed. E.S. de Beer (8 vols., Oxford, 1976-1989), Vol. I, p. 123.
    • (1976) The Correspondence , vol.1 , pp. 123
    • Locke1
  • 110
    • 0006001001 scopus 로고
    • trans. Harold P. Cooke Cambridge, MA
    • Aristotle, On Interpretation, trans. Harold P. Cooke (Cambridge, MA, 1938), p. 115.
    • (1938) On Interpretation , pp. 115
    • Aristotle1
  • 114
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.1
    • Locke, Essay, p. 405 (III.ii.1).
    • Essay , pp. 405
    • Locke1
  • 115
    • 25844464174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.3
    • Ibid., p. 406 (III.ii.3).
    • Essay , pp. 406
  • 116
    • 25844452841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay, 406, Ibid.
    • Essay , pp. 406
  • 117
    • 25844481573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay, 406, Ibid.
    • Essay , pp. 406
  • 122
    • 25844523262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.15
    • Locke is, nonetheless, worried about the divergence of the meanings of substance terms in the context of 'philosophical enquiries and debates' (ibid., p. 484 (III.ix.15);
    • A History of Political Thought , pp. 484
  • 128
    • 25844523262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxii.5
    • It ought to be noted that mixed modes are not arbitrary in the sense that, in the interest of convenience, it is in the nature of man to make mixed modes (ibid., p. 290 (II.xxii.5)).
    • A History of Political Thought , pp. 290
  • 129
    • 25844523262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.iii.2-4
    • It is in what men decide they consist that is perfectly arbitrary. It should also be noted that mixed modes are, for the most part, species of 'abstract' or universal ideas, and that it is again in the God-given nature of man to make these kind of general ideas (for the purposes of expedience, knowledge and communication (ibid., pp. 409-10 (III.iii.2-4)).
    • A History of Political Thought , pp. 409-410
  • 130
    • 25844523262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.iii.3-8
    • However, when Locke deals with abstraction, he often implies that men abstract identically (which is precisely why abstract ideas, being universal, enable men to communicate). So, for example, he explains how a child notices a resemblance between his ideas of particular persons and abstracts from them a universal idea of 'man' (ibid., pp. 409-11 (III.iii.3-8)).
    • A History of Political Thought , pp. 409-411
  • 131
    • 25844523262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.vi.26-27
    • But when Locke deals with ideational complexity, he often insists that men make complex ideas differently from each other, and one of his favourite illustrations of this phenomena is the very same idea of 'man' (e.g. ibid., pp. 453-5 (III.vi.26-27)). While the relationship between complexity and abstraction is difficult to pin down, and is perhaps another permutation of the tension that this final part of the article is concerned to reveal, it does not detract from Locke's anti-scholastic, nominalist polemic about the voluntary nature of complex ideas, and his associated claims about their divergence. In this article I do not deal with the distinction between abstract and particular ideas because all the words I am concerned with are general. Particular names, such as Charles II, are unproblematic and not in danger of duplicity or proliferation.
    • A History of Political Thought , pp. 453-455
  • 132
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IV.iii.18
    • While Locke struggles throughout his life with the demonstrability of natural law, he lays the groundwork. Briefly, we have intuitive knowledge of our own existence, from which we achieve demonstrative knowledge of God and his will - by which we are bound, according to the right a maker has in his work or labour. The fundamental dictate of the law of nature, that mankind is to be preserved, can be deduced from God's giving us life and the means to preserve it (Locke, Essay, p. 549 (IV.iii.18);
    • Essay , pp. 549
    • Locke1
  • 134
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.xi.16
    • Locke declares that morality can be a demonstrable science because the ideas involved are mixed modes and so 'not of nature's, but man's making'; being therefore 'perfectly known', they can be the objects of demonstration (Locke, Essay, p. 516 (III.xi.16)).
    • Essay , pp. 516
    • Locke1
  • 136
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.8
    • Locke, Essay, p. 408 (III.ii.8).
    • Essay , pp. 408
    • Locke1
  • 137
    • 25844494412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxxii.12
    • Ibid., pp. 387-8 (II.xxxii.12).
    • Essay , pp. 387-388
  • 138
    • 25844466617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke on private language
    • For an investigation of Locke and his commentators on the subject of private language see Dawson, 'Locke on Private Language', British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 11 (4) (2003), pp. 609-38.
    • (2003) British Journal for the History of Philosophy , vol.11 , Issue.4 , pp. 609-638
    • Dawson1
  • 139
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.5
    • Locke, Essay, p. 477 (III.ix.5).
    • Essay , pp. 477
    • Locke1
  • 140
    • 25844433714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.8
    • Ibid., p. 479 (III.ix.8).
    • Essay , pp. 479
  • 141
    • 25844521141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay, 479, Ibid.
    • Essay , pp. 479
  • 142
    • 4344664269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ii.8
    • Ibid., p. 408 (III.ii.8).
    • Essay , pp. 408
  • 143
    • 25844513602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.8
    • Ibid., p. 479 (III.ix.8).
    • Essay , pp. 479
  • 144
    • 25844448682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xx.1
    • Ibid., p. 229 (II.xx.1);
    • Essay , pp. 229
  • 145
    • 25844483772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xx.3
    • Essay, p. 229 (II.xx.3).
    • Essay , pp. 229
  • 146
    • 25844505098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xx.2
    • Ibid., p. 229 (II.xx.2);
    • Essay , pp. 229
  • 148
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IV.xix.1
    • Locke, Essay, p. 698 (IV.xix.1);
    • Essay , pp. 698
    • Locke1
  • 155
    • 25844523827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corinthians, ch. 13
    • Cf. The King James Bible, 1 Corinthians, ch. 13.
    • The King James Bible , vol.1
  • 156
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxvii.16
    • Locke, Essay, p. 340 (II.xxvii.16): 'whatever has the consciousness of present and past actions, is the same person to whom they belong'.
    • Essay , pp. 340
    • Locke1
  • 157
    • 25844466616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.x.4
    • Ibid., p. 151 (II.x.4).
    • Essay , pp. 151
  • 158
    • 25844471610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.x.5
    • Ibid., pp. 151-2(II.x.5).
    • Essay , pp. 151-152
  • 159
    • 25844489068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.6
    • Ibid., p. 478 (III.ix.6).
    • Essay , pp. 478
  • 161
    • 0004153207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke owned both the 1669 French edition of the Essais and Florio's 1603 translation (Harrison and Laslett, Library, p. 191).
    • Library , pp. 191
    • Harrison1    Laslett2
  • 162
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.9
    • Locke, Essay, p. 480 (III.ix.9).
    • Essay , pp. 480
    • Locke1
  • 163
    • 25844432920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.6
    • Ibid., p. 478 (III.ix.6).
    • Essay , pp. 478
  • 164
    • 25844490455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.i.1
    • Ibid., p. 402 (III.i.1).
    • Essay , pp. 402
  • 166
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.22
    • Locke, Essay, p. 489 (III.ix.22).
    • Essay , pp. 489
    • Locke1
  • 169
    • 0004324399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke often elides the difference between the two compacts (e.g. ibid., pp. 347, 353). However, it is important for Locke that the generation of the government is a two-stage process, whereby there is one, powerful body of the people that is prior to the government and to which the government is answerable. Here Locke is implicitly attacking the Hobbesian one-stage compact whereby there is no body of the people independent of the sovereign.
    • Two Treatises , pp. 347
  • 172
    • 77955254064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke's stress on express consent, particularly at the original compact, has perplexed some commentators. However, as John Dunn has suggested, the proposal becomes more credible if one considers the 'occasions in any man's life in which he uses verbal formulae which imply a recognition of his membership in the national society to which he belongs' (Dunn, Political Thought, p. 141).
    • Political Thought , pp. 141
    • Dunn1
  • 173
    • 84959717669 scopus 로고
    • Consent in the political theory of John Locke
    • Even if one admits of the necessarily behavioural and hypothetical nature of much of the rights-transfer, the process remains reliant on linguistically constituted moral concepts and therefore dangerously threatened by semantic promiscuity. For further thoughts on this issue see Dunn, 'Consent in the Political Theory of John Locke', Historical Journal, X (2) (1967), pp. 153-82;
    • (1967) Historical Journal , vol.10 , Issue.2 , pp. 153-182
    • Dunn1
  • 175
    • 25844435694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lockean express consent: An argument against irrevocability
    • Michael W. Brough, 'Lockean Express Consent: An Argument Against Irrevocability', Locke Studies, 3 (2003), pp. 113-31.
    • (2003) Locke Studies , vol.3 , pp. 113-131
    • Brough, M.W.1
  • 176
    • 25844502512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Measuring Locke's shadow
    • Locke, ed. Shapiro
    • See John Dunn, 'Measuring Locke's Shadow', in Locke, Two Treatises of Government and a Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. Shapiro, pp. 257-85, pp. 277-8 on the centrality of judgment at the precarious and creative centre of Locke's vision of the human political predicament.
    • Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration , pp. 257-285
    • Dunn, J.1
  • 177
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.v.8
    • Locke, Essay, pp. 432-3 (III.v.8).
    • Essay , pp. 432-433
    • Locke1
  • 178
    • 25844464172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxviii.2
    • Essay, pp. 349-50 (II.xxviii.2).
    • Essay , pp. 349-350
  • 179
    • 25844501521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxviii.2
    • Ibid., p. 349 (II.xxviii.2).
    • Essay , pp. 349
  • 180
    • 25844493646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.v.10
    • Ibid., p. 434 (III.v.10).
    • Essay , pp. 434
  • 181
    • 25844507466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay, 434, Ibid.
    • Essay , pp. 434
  • 182
    • 25844530158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay, 434, ibid.
    • Essay , pp. 434
  • 183
    • 25844456649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.v.8
    • Ibid., pp. 432-3 (III.v.8).
    • Essay , pp. 432-433
  • 184
    • 84883950945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of ethick in general
    • Cambridge
    • Locke contradicts himself on this point in the (1686-8?) manuscript entitled Of Ethick in General, in Political Essays, ed. Mark Goldie (Cambridge, 1997), pp. 297-304.
    • (1997) Political Essays , pp. 297-304
    • Goldie, M.1
  • 185
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxviii.12
    • Locke, Essay, p. 357 (II.xxviii.12).
    • Essay , pp. 357
    • Locke1
  • 188
    • 84870885263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II.xxviii.12
    • Locke, Essay, p. 357 (II.xxviii.12).
    • Essay , pp. 357
    • Locke1
  • 189
    • 25844477117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.13
    • Ibid., p. 497 (III.x.13).
    • Essay , pp. 497
  • 190
    • 25844477118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.ix.9
    • Ibid., p. 480 (III.ix.9).
    • Essay , pp. 480
  • 191
    • 25844461352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III.x.13
    • Ibid., p. 497 (III.x.13).
    • Essay , pp. 497
  • 192
    • 0346943306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tully, 'Governing Conduct' is the piece that illuminates Locke's 'mercantilist', reformist agenda.
    • Governing Conduct
    • Tully1
  • 193
    • 0011655726 scopus 로고
    • The making of homo faber: John Locke between ideology and history
    • Cf. E.J. Hundert, "The Making of Homo Faber: John Locke Between Ideology and History', Journal of the History of Ideas, XXXV (1) (1972), pp. 3-22.
    • (1972) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.35 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-22
    • Hundert, E.J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.