-
1
-
-
0010427147
-
-
Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, present author's translation
-
'We human beings do not possess freedom; ... freedom possesses [besitzt] us.' M. Heidegger, Wegmarken (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1967), p. 85 (present author's translation). Heidegger's discussion of 'the nature of freedom' formed part of a lecture (on the nature of truth) first given in 1930 and included in this volume in a revised version first published in 1943.
-
(1967)
Wegmarken
, pp. 85
-
-
Heidegger, M.1
-
2
-
-
25444489333
-
International Law and the Idea of History
-
On the nature and social function of history, see Philip Allott, 'International Law and the Idea of History', Journal of the History of International Law (1999), pp. 1-21.
-
(1999)
Journal of the History of International Law
, pp. 1-21
-
-
Allott, P.1
-
3
-
-
0004082105
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For an exposition of this conception of international society, see Philip Allott, Eunomia - New Order for a New World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990). Since the Reformation of the sixteenth century no single reified unifying conception of the social aspect of human existence has established itself, leaving the speculative field open to competing ideas: a universal society of human beings or of states or nations, an international society of states, the international community, an anarchical society of states, the international system, world order, and so on. Greek and Roman thought, and pre-Reformation Christian thought, had produced many such ideas: homonoia, kosmopolis, humanitas, civitas maxima, concordia, the earthly kingdom, the City of Man, Christendom.
-
(1990)
Eunomia - New Order for a New World
-
-
Allott, P.1
-
4
-
-
4243480904
-
-
trans. F. M. Cornford
-
'One party is trying to drag everything down to earth out of heaven and the unseen ... and strenuously affirm that real existence belongs only to that which can be handled and offers resistance to the touch. They define reality as the same thing as body, and as soon as one of the opposite party asserts that anything without a body is real, they are utterly contemptuous and will not listen to another word ... and accordingly their adversaries are very wary in defending their position somewhere in the heights of the unseen, maintaining with all their force that true reality consists in certain intelligible and bodiless forms ... and what those others allege to be true reality they call, not real being but a sort of moving process of becoming. On this issue an interminable battle is always going on between the two camps.' Plato, Sophist (trans. F. M. Cornford), 246b-c,
-
Sophist
-
-
Plato1
-
6
-
-
0003860837
-
-
London: Kegan Paul
-
The negating of idealism has been called, at different times: sophism, pyrrhonism, scepticism, empiricism, nominalism, materialism, relativism, nihilism, positivism, naturalism, realism, pragmatism, logical positivism, phenomenology, neopragmatism, postmodernism. For contemporary examples of characteristically American fundamentalist anti-idealism, see: J. B. Watson, Behaviorism, 2nd edn. (London: Kegan Paul, 1931);
-
(1931)
Behaviorism, 2nd Edn.
-
-
Watson, J.B.1
-
10
-
-
0003859002
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
E. O. Wilson, Sociobiology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975);
-
(1975)
Sociobiology
-
-
Wilson, E.O.1
-
13
-
-
0842278175
-
-
trans. F. M. Cornford
-
'And so, since what acts upon me is for me and for no one else, I, and no one else, am actually perceiving it ... Then my perception is true for me, for its object at any moment is my reality, and I am, as Protagoras says, a judge of what is for me, and of what is not, that it is not.' Plato, Theaetetus (trans. F. M. Cornford), 160c,
-
Theaetetus
-
-
Plato1
-
14
-
-
0004248187
-
-
Collected Dialogues, p. 866. Plato's Socrates is here speaking about a subjectivist conception of the reality of reality (that is, of universal reality, not merely of what we are here calling human reality). G.W. Leibniz (1646-1716) conceived of the universe as being formed from ultimate indivisible 'monads' each of which contains the whole order of the universe organized around its unique 'point of view' [point de vue], so that each 'simple substance' is 'a perpetual living mirror of the universe'.
-
Collected Dialogues
, pp. 866
-
-
-
17
-
-
0003851654
-
-
1781-87, 2nd edn., trans. N. Kemp-Smith London: Macmillan
-
Kant compared his own work to the Copernican revolution, resituating the human observer in relation to universal reality by making the human mind an integral part of the constructing of the reality of the universe. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (1781-87), 2nd edn., trans. N. Kemp-Smith (London: Macmillan, 1929), pp. 22, 25.
-
(1929)
Critique of Pure Reason
, pp. 22
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
18
-
-
0003672965
-
-
trans. P. Winch, ed. G. H.von Wright Oxford: Blackwell
-
'What a Copernicus or a Darwin really achieved was not the discovery of a true theory but of a fertile new point of view [eines fruchtbaren neuen Aspekts].' L. Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (trans. P. Winch, ed. G. H.von Wright) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), p.18e.
-
(1980)
Culture and Value
-
-
Wittgenstein, L.1
|