메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 3, 2004, Pages 320-346

From the act to the decision: Hannah Arendt and the question of decisionism

Author keywords

Act; Arendt; Decision; Freedom; Schmitt; Will

Indexed keywords


EID: 2542517825     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591704263032     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (32)

References (159)
  • 1
    • 0002404574 scopus 로고
    • Force of law: The 'mystical foundations of authority'
    • ed. by Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (New York: Routledge)
    • Jacques Derrida, "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundations of Authority'," Deconstraction and the Possibility of Justice, ed. by Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (New York: Routledge, 1992), 26.
    • (1992) Deconstraction and the Possibility of Justice , pp. 26
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 2
    • 0003542452 scopus 로고
    • Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld
    • George Kateb, Hannah Arendt. Politics, Conscience, and Evil (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984), 28-33, 36, 39, 55, 88; Martin Jay, "The Political Existentialism of Hannah Arendt," Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985), 237-256; Jerome John, "Thinking/Acting," Social Research 57, no. 1 (1990): 105; Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger (New York: Columbia University, 1990), 35-40, 191; and Luc Ferry and Alain Renault, Heidegger and Modernity, trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 95-96, 98, 104-108.
    • (1984) Hannath Arendt. Politics, Conscience, and Evil , pp. 28-33
    • Kateb, G.1    Arendt, H.2
  • 3
    • 2542629999 scopus 로고
    • The political existentialism of Hannah Arendt
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • George Kateb, Hannah Arendt. Politics, Conscience, and Evil (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984), 28-33, 36, 39, 55, 88; Martin Jay, "The Political Existentialism of Hannah Arendt," Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985), 237-256; Jerome John, "Thinking/Acting," Social Research 57, no. 1 (1990): 105; Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger (New York: Columbia University, 1990), 35-40, 191; and Luc Ferry and Alain Renault, Heidegger and Modernity, trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 95-96, 98, 104-108.
    • (1985) Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America , pp. 237-256
    • Jay, M.1
  • 4
    • 84930561328 scopus 로고
    • Thinking/acting
    • George Kateb, Hannah Arendt. Politics, Conscience, and Evil (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984), 28-33, 36, 39, 55, 88; Martin Jay, "The Political Existentialism of Hannah Arendt," Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985), 237-256; Jerome John, "Thinking/Acting," Social Research 57, no. 1 (1990): 105; Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger (New York: Columbia University, 1990), 35-40, 191; and Luc Ferry and Alain Renault, Heidegger and Modernity, trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 95-96, 98, 104-108.
    • (1990) Social Research , vol.57 , Issue.1 , pp. 105
    • John, J.1
  • 5
    • 0003979296 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University
    • George Kateb, Hannah Arendt. Politics, Conscience, and Evil (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984), 28-33, 36, 39, 55, 88; Martin Jay, "The Political Existentialism of Hannah Arendt," Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985), 237-256; Jerome John, "Thinking/Acting," Social Research 57, no. 1 (1990): 105; Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger (New York: Columbia University, 1990), 35-40, 191; and Luc Ferry and Alain Renault, Heidegger and Modernity, trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 95-96, 98, 104-108.
    • (1990) The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger , pp. 35-40
    • Wolin, R.1
  • 6
    • 0012621604 scopus 로고
    • trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • George Kateb, Hannah Arendt. Politics, Conscience, and Evil (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984), 28-33, 36, 39, 55, 88; Martin Jay, "The Political Existentialism of Hannah Arendt," Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985), 237-256; Jerome John, "Thinking/Acting," Social Research 57, no. 1 (1990): 105; Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger (New York: Columbia University, 1990), 35-40, 191; and Luc Ferry and Alain Renault, Heidegger and Modernity, trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 95-96, 98, 104-108.
    • (1990) Heidegger and Modernity , pp. 95-96
    • Ferry, L.1    Renault, A.2
  • 7
    • 55449105234 scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt: On the concept of power
    • trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Hannah Arendt: On the Concept of Power," Philosophical-Political Profiles, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 173-190; Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 156-164, 169-200; Dana R. Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 116; and Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks: Sage, 1996), 166.
    • (1990) Philosophical-political Profiles , pp. 173-190
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 8
    • 0003549388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Hannah Arendt: On the Concept of Power," Philosophical-Political Profiles, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 173-190; Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 156-164, 169-200; Dana R. Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 116; and Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks: Sage, 1996), 166.
    • (1992) A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought , pp. 156-164
    • Canovan, M.1    Arendt, H.2
  • 9
    • 0004130019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Hannah Arendt: On the Concept of Power," Philosophical-Political Profiles, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 173-190; Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 156-164, 169-200; Dana R. Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 116; and Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks: Sage, 1996), 166.
    • (1996) Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political , pp. 116
    • Villa, D.R.1
  • 10
    • 33749417407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thousand Oaks: Sage
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Hannah Arendt: On the Concept of Power," Philosophical-Political Profiles, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 173-190; Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 156-164, 169-200; Dana R. Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 116; and Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks: Sage, 1996), 166.
    • (1996) The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt , pp. 166
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 11
    • 2542633020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Revolutions and constitutions: Hannah Arendt's challenge to Carl Schmitt
    • David Dyzenhaus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press)
    • For this point, see William E. Scheuerman, "Revolutions and Constitutions: Hannah Arendt's Challenge to Carl Schmitt," Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism, ed. by David Dyzenhaus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1998), 252-280; and Andrew Arato, Civil Society, Constitution, and Legitimacy (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000), 129-138, 145-147, 167-183, 229-256.
    • (1998) Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism , pp. 252-280
    • Scheuerman, W.E.1
  • 12
    • 0009456819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Rowman & Littlefield
    • For this point, see William E. Scheuerman, "Revolutions and Constitutions: Hannah Arendt's Challenge to Carl Schmitt," Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism, ed. by David Dyzenhaus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1998), 252-280; and Andrew Arato, Civil Society, Constitution, and Legitimacy (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000), 129-138, 145-147, 167-183, 229-256.
    • (2000) Civil Society, Constitution, and Legitimacy , pp. 129-138
    • Arato, A.1
  • 13
    • 84971730955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vita Activa and vita contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's political thought in the life of the mind
    • July
    • For a recognition of this abrupt shift, see Peter Stern and Jean Yarbrough, "Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's Political Thought in The Life of the Mind," The Review of Politics 43, no. 3 (July 1981): 323-354; Ronald Beiner, "Hannah Arendt on Judging," Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982), 89-156; Kateb, Hannah Arendt, 195-196; Suzanne Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):53-54; and Hauke Brukhorst, "Equality and Elitism in Arendt," The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 178-198. By contrast, Bonnie Honig has argued that there is no significant shift between Arendt's earlier and later work regarding the will. Although Honig acknowledges that in Arendt's last writings the character of the will is dual and not monistic as in the earlier versions, she does not take this modification to represent a substantial change of orientation. Honig's argument seems to me to be unconvincing for the following reasons: (1) She overlooks Arendt's clear identification of the will and freedom in The Life of the Mind (hereafter, LOM). (2) Although Honig begins her exposition by claiming that Arendt's concept of the will does not undergo significant changes, she mainly confirms that her notion of action does not change. But is this the point? There is no doubt that action remains more or less consistent in Arendt. Her concept of the will, however, does not. Whereas Arendt's definition of action as spontaneous new beginnings is constant, her definition of the will as the faculty of novelty, alterity, and natality represents an important departure from previous versions. (3) Honig does not discuss the implications of Arendt's equation of the will with the organ of the future that evokes the concept of "the memory of the will." (4) Finally, Honig's argument is internally divided between showing that Arendt's concept of the will is "internally coherent and importantly consistent with her earlier accounts of action and identity" and acknowledging that "the will in LOM is not consistent with her earlier account" and that "one important change has been made." Bonnie Honing, "Arendt, Identity, and Difference," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):77-98.
    • (1981) The Review of Politics , vol.43 , Issue.3 , pp. 323-354
    • Stern, P.1    Yarbrough, J.2
  • 14
    • 84971730955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt on judging
    • ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press)
    • For a recognition of this abrupt shift, see Peter Stern and Jean Yarbrough, "Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's Political Thought in The Life of the Mind," The Review of Politics 43, no. 3 (July 1981): 323-354; Ronald Beiner, "Hannah Arendt on Judging," Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982), 89-156; Kateb, Hannah Arendt, 195-196; Suzanne Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):53-54; and Hauke Brukhorst, "Equality and Elitism in Arendt," The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 178-198. By contrast, Bonnie Honig has argued that there is no significant shift between Arendt's earlier and later work regarding the will. Although Honig acknowledges that in Arendt's last writings the character of the will is dual and not monistic as in the earlier versions, she does not take this modification to represent a substantial change of orientation. Honig's argument seems to me to be unconvincing for the following reasons: (1) She overlooks Arendt's clear identification of the will and freedom in The Life of the Mind (hereafter, LOM). (2) Although Honig begins her exposition by claiming that Arendt's concept of the will does not undergo significant changes, she mainly confirms that her notion of action does not change. But is this the point? There is no doubt that action remains more or less consistent in Arendt. Her concept of the will, however, does not. Whereas Arendt's definition of action as spontaneous new beginnings is constant, her definition of the will as the faculty of novelty, alterity, and natality represents an important departure from previous versions. (3) Honig does not discuss the implications of Arendt's equation of the will with the organ of the future that evokes the concept of "the memory of the will." (4) Finally, Honig's argument is internally divided between showing that Arendt's concept of the will is "internally coherent and importantly consistent with her earlier accounts of action and identity" and acknowledging that "the will in LOM is not consistent with her earlier account" and that "one important change has been made." Bonnie Honing, "Arendt, Identity, and Difference," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):77-98.
    • (1982) Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy , pp. 89-156
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 15
    • 84971730955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recognition of this abrupt shift, see Peter Stern and Jean Yarbrough, "Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's Political Thought in The Life of the Mind," The Review of Politics 43, no. 3 (July 1981): 323-354; Ronald Beiner, "Hannah Arendt on Judging," Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982), 89-156; Kateb, Hannah Arendt, 195-196; Suzanne Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):53-54; and Hauke Brukhorst, "Equality and Elitism in Arendt," The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 178-198. By contrast, Bonnie Honig has argued that there is no significant shift between Arendt's earlier and later work regarding the will. Although Honig acknowledges that in Arendt's last writings the character of the will is dual and not monistic as in the earlier versions, she does not take this modification to represent a substantial change of orientation. Honig's argument seems to me to be unconvincing for the following reasons: (1) She overlooks Arendt's clear identification of the will and freedom in The Life of the Mind (hereafter, LOM). (2) Although Honig begins her exposition by claiming that Arendt's concept of the will does not undergo significant changes, she mainly confirms that her notion of action does not change. But is this the point? There is no doubt that action remains more or less consistent in Arendt. Her concept of the will, however, does not. Whereas Arendt's definition of action as spontaneous new beginnings is constant, her definition of the will as the faculty of novelty, alterity, and natality represents an important departure from previous versions. (3) Honig does not discuss the implications of Arendt's equation of the will with the organ of the future that evokes the concept of "the memory of the will." (4) Finally, Honig's argument is internally divided between showing that Arendt's concept of the will is "internally coherent and importantly consistent with her earlier accounts of action and identity" and acknowledging that "the will in LOM is not consistent with her earlier account" and that "one important change has been made." Bonnie Honing, "Arendt, Identity, and Difference," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):77-98.
    • Hannah Arendt , pp. 195-196
    • Kateb1
  • 16
    • 84973220809 scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt and the will
    • For a recognition of this abrupt shift, see Peter Stern and Jean Yarbrough, "Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's Political Thought in The Life of the Mind," The Review of Politics 43, no. 3 (July 1981): 323-354; Ronald Beiner, "Hannah Arendt on Judging," Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982), 89-156; Kateb, Hannah Arendt, 195-196; Suzanne Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):53-54; and Hauke Brukhorst, "Equality and Elitism in Arendt," The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 178-198. By contrast, Bonnie Honig has argued that there is no significant shift between Arendt's earlier and later work regarding the will. Although Honig acknowledges that in Arendt's last writings the character of the will is dual and not monistic as in the earlier versions, she does not take this modification to represent a substantial change of orientation. Honig's argument seems to me to be unconvincing for the following reasons: (1) She overlooks Arendt's clear identification of the will and freedom in The Life of the Mind (hereafter, LOM). (2) Although Honig begins her exposition by claiming that Arendt's concept of the will does not undergo significant changes, she mainly confirms that her notion of action does not change. But is this the point? There is no doubt that action remains more or less consistent in Arendt. Her concept of the will, however, does not. Whereas Arendt's definition of action as spontaneous new beginnings is constant, her definition of the will as the faculty of novelty, alterity, and natality represents an important departure from previous versions. (3) Honig does not discuss the implications of Arendt's equation of the will with the organ of the future that evokes the concept of "the memory of the will." (4) Finally, Honig's argument is internally divided between showing that Arendt's concept of the will is "internally coherent and importantly consistent with her earlier accounts of action and identity" and acknowledging that "the will in LOM is not consistent with her earlier account" and that "one important change has been made." Bonnie Honing, "Arendt, Identity, and Difference," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):77-98.
    • (1988) Political Theory , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 53-54
    • Jacobitti, S.1
  • 17
    • 84971730955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equality and elitism in Arendt
    • ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • For a recognition of this abrupt shift, see Peter Stern and Jean Yarbrough, "Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's Political Thought in The Life of the Mind," The Review of Politics 43, no. 3 (July 1981): 323-354; Ronald Beiner, "Hannah Arendt on Judging," Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982), 89-156; Kateb, Hannah Arendt, 195-196; Suzanne Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):53-54; and Hauke Brukhorst, "Equality and Elitism in Arendt," The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 178-198. By contrast, Bonnie Honig has argued that there is no significant shift between Arendt's earlier and later work regarding the will. Although Honig acknowledges that in Arendt's last writings the character of the will is dual and not monistic as in the earlier versions, she does not take this modification to represent a substantial change of orientation. Honig's argument seems to me to be unconvincing for the following reasons: (1) She overlooks Arendt's clear identification of the will and freedom in The Life of the Mind (hereafter, LOM). (2) Although Honig begins her exposition by claiming that Arendt's concept of the will does not undergo significant changes, she mainly confirms that her notion of action does not change. But is this the point? There is no doubt that action remains more or less consistent in Arendt. Her concept of the will, however, does not. Whereas Arendt's definition of action as spontaneous new beginnings is constant, her definition of the will as the faculty of novelty, alterity, and natality represents an important departure from previous versions. (3) Honig does not discuss the implications of Arendt's equation of the will with the organ of the future that evokes the concept of "the memory of the will." (4) Finally, Honig's argument is internally divided between showing that Arendt's concept of the will is "internally coherent and importantly consistent with her earlier accounts of action and identity" and acknowledging that "the will in LOM is not consistent with her earlier account" and that "one important change has been made." Bonnie Honing, "Arendt, Identity, and Difference," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):77-98.
    • (2000) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt , pp. 178-198
    • Brukhorst, H.1
  • 18
    • 84928507859 scopus 로고
    • Arendt, identity, and difference
    • For a recognition of this abrupt shift, see Peter Stern and Jean Yarbrough, "Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt's Political Thought in The Life of the Mind," The Review of Politics 43, no. 3 (July 1981): 323-354; Ronald Beiner, "Hannah Arendt on Judging," Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982), 89-156; Kateb, Hannah Arendt, 195-196; Suzanne Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):53-54; and Hauke Brukhorst, "Equality and Elitism in Arendt," The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. by Dana Villa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 178-198. By contrast, Bonnie Honig has argued that there is no significant shift between Arendt's earlier and later work regarding the will. Although Honig acknowledges that in Arendt's last writings the character of the will is dual and not monistic as in the earlier versions, she does not take this modification to represent a substantial change of orientation. Honig's argument seems to me to be unconvincing for the following reasons: (1) She overlooks Arendt's clear identification of the will and freedom in The Life of the Mind (hereafter, LOM). (2) Although Honig begins her exposition by claiming that Arendt's concept of the will does not undergo significant changes, she mainly confirms that her notion of action does not change. But is this the point? There is no doubt that action remains more or less consistent in Arendt. Her concept of the will, however, does not. Whereas Arendt's definition of action as spontaneous new beginnings is constant, her definition of the will as the faculty of novelty, alterity, and natality represents an important departure from previous versions. (3) Honig does not discuss the implications of Arendt's equation of the will with the organ of the future that evokes the concept of "the memory of the will." (4) Finally, Honig's argument is internally divided between showing that Arendt's concept of the will is "internally coherent and importantly consistent with her earlier accounts of action and identity" and acknowledging that "the will in LOM is not consistent with her earlier account" and that "one important change has been made." Bonnie Honing, "Arendt, Identity, and Difference," Political Theory 16, no. 1 (1988):77-98.
    • (1988) Political Theory , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 77-98
    • Honing, B.1
  • 19
    • 0001981225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, see Villa, Arendt and Heidegger, 76, 62. Similarly, Michael Denneny has contended that for Arendt the will cannot but lead to totalitarianism. Michael Denneny, "The Privilege of Ourselves: Hannah Arendt on Judgment," Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, ed. by Melvyn A. Hill (New York: St. Martin's, 1979), 259. Hannah Arendt, "Willing," LOM (New York: A Harvest Book, 1978), 32.
    • Arendt and Heidegger , pp. 76
    • Villa1
  • 20
    • 2542572059 scopus 로고
    • The privilege of ourselves: Hannah Arendt on judgment
    • ed. by Melvyn A. Hill (New York: St. Martin's)
    • For example, see Villa, Arendt and Heidegger, 76, 62. Similarly, Michael Denneny has contended that for Arendt the will cannot but lead to totalitarianism. Michael Denneny, "The Privilege of Ourselves: Hannah Arendt on Judgment," Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, ed. by Melvyn A. Hill (New York: St. Martin's, 1979), 259. Hannah Arendt, "Willing," LOM (New York: A Harvest Book, 1978), 32.
    • (1979) Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World , pp. 259
    • Denneny, M.1
  • 21
    • 2542643447 scopus 로고
    • Willing
    • New York: A Harvest Book
    • For example, see Villa, Arendt and Heidegger, 76, 62. Similarly, Michael Denneny has contended that for Arendt the will cannot but lead to totalitarianism. Michael Denneny, "The Privilege of Ourselves: Hannah Arendt on Judgment," Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, ed. by Melvyn A. Hill (New York: St. Martin's, 1979), 259. Hannah Arendt, "Willing," LOM (New York: A Harvest Book, 1978), 32.
    • (1978) LOM , pp. 32
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 22
    • 0007422951 scopus 로고
    • Berlin: Duncker und Humblot
    • Carl Schmitt, Über die drei Arten des rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1993), 21, 23-24 (emphasis added). For a discussion of Schmitt's theory of the constituent decision, see my "Carl Schmitt and the Three Moments of Democracy," Cardozo Law Review 21 (2000):5-6.
    • (1993) Über die drei Arten des Rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens , pp. 21
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 23
    • 23544470441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt and the three moments of democracy
    • Carl Schmitt, Über die drei Arten des rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1993), 21, 23-24 (emphasis added). For a discussion of Schmitt's theory of the constituent decision, see my "Carl Schmitt and the Three Moments of Democracy," Cardozo Law Review 21 (2000):5-6.
    • (2000) Cardozo Law Review , vol.21 , pp. 5-6
  • 24
    • 0003491750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berlin: Duncker und Humblot
    • Carl Schmitt, Die Dictatur (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1994), 23; and Carl Schmitt, Political Theology. Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans. George Schwab (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988), 32, 66.
    • (1994) Die Dictatur , pp. 23
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 26
    • 0004260663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berlin: Duncker und Humblot
    • Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1989), 75-76.
    • (1989) Verfassungslehre , pp. 75-76
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 27
    • 0004260663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, 224, 36, 90, 94-95; and Schmitt, Die Dictatur, 134.
    • Verfassungslehre , pp. 224
    • Schmitt1
  • 28
    • 0003491750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, 224, 36, 90, 94-95; and Schmitt, Die Dictatur, 134.
    • Die Dictatur , pp. 134
    • Schmitt1
  • 31
    • 84862357675 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence
    • For a helpful historical presentation, conceptual analysis, and comparative discussion of the concept of the constituent power, see Georges Burdeau, Traité de science politique: le statut du pouvoir dans l'état, vol. 4 (Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence, 1983); Ernst Wolfgang Böckenforde, "Die verfassungsggebende Gewalt des Volkes-Ein Grenzbegriff des Verfassungsrechts, " Staat, Verfassung, Democratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht (Frankfurt-am-Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1991), 90-114; Olivier Beaud, La puissance de l'état (Paris: PUF, 1995); Claude Klein, Théorie et Pratique du pouvoir constituant (Paris: PUF, 1996); and Antonio Negri, Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State, trans. Maurizia Boscagli (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999).
    • (1983) Traité de Science Politique: Le Statut du Pouvoir dans l'état , vol.4
    • Burdeau, G.1
  • 32
    • 84920192198 scopus 로고
    • Die verfassungsggebende Gewalt des Volkes-Ein Grenzbegriff des Verfassungsrechts
    • Frankfurt-am-Main, Germany: Suhrkamp
    • For a helpful historical presentation, conceptual analysis, and comparative discussion of the concept of the constituent power, see Georges Burdeau, Traité de science politique: le statut du pouvoir dans l'état, vol. 4 (Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence, 1983); Ernst Wolfgang Böckenforde, "Die verfassungsggebende Gewalt des Volkes-Ein Grenzbegriff des Verfassungsrechts, " Staat, Verfassung, Democratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht (Frankfurt-am-Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1991), 90-114; Olivier Beaud, La puissance de l'état (Paris: PUF, 1995); Claude Klein, Théorie et Pratique du pouvoir constituant (Paris: PUF, 1996); and Antonio Negri, Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State, trans. Maurizia Boscagli (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999).
    • (1991) Staat, Verfassung, Democratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht , pp. 90-114
    • Böckenforde, E.W.1
  • 33
    • 33749119430 scopus 로고
    • Paris: PUF
    • For a helpful historical presentation, conceptual analysis, and comparative discussion of the concept of the constituent power, see Georges Burdeau, Traité de science politique: le statut du pouvoir dans l'état, vol. 4 (Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence, 1983); Ernst Wolfgang Böckenforde, "Die verfassungsggebende Gewalt des Volkes-Ein Grenzbegriff des Verfassungsrechts, " Staat, Verfassung, Democratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht (Frankfurt-am-Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1991), 90-114; Olivier Beaud, La puissance de l'état (Paris: PUF, 1995); Claude Klein, Théorie et Pratique du pouvoir constituant (Paris: PUF, 1996); and Antonio Negri, Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State, trans. Maurizia Boscagli (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999).
    • (1995) La Puissance de l'état
    • Beaud, O.1
  • 34
    • 0007463015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris: PUF
    • For a helpful historical presentation, conceptual analysis, and comparative discussion of the concept of the constituent power, see Georges Burdeau, Traité de science politique: le statut du pouvoir dans l'état, vol. 4 (Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence, 1983); Ernst Wolfgang Böckenforde, "Die verfassungsggebende Gewalt des Volkes-Ein Grenzbegriff des Verfassungsrechts, " Staat, Verfassung, Democratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht (Frankfurt-am-Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1991), 90-114; Olivier Beaud, La puissance de l'état (Paris: PUF, 1995); Claude Klein, Théorie et Pratique du pouvoir constituant (Paris: PUF, 1996); and Antonio Negri, Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State, trans. Maurizia Boscagli (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999).
    • (1996) Théorie et Pratique du Pouvoir Constituant
    • Klein, C.1
  • 35
    • 0942305932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Maurizia Boscagli (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press)
    • For a helpful historical presentation, conceptual analysis, and comparative discussion of the concept of the constituent power, see Georges Burdeau, Traité de science politique: le statut du pouvoir dans l'état, vol. 4 (Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence, 1983); Ernst Wolfgang Böckenforde, "Die verfassungsggebende Gewalt des Volkes-Ein Grenzbegriff des Verfassungsrechts, " Staat, Verfassung, Democratie. Studien zur Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht (Frankfurt-am-Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1991), 90-114; Olivier Beaud, La puissance de l'état (Paris: PUF, 1995); Claude Klein, Théorie et Pratique du pouvoir constituant (Paris: PUF, 1996); and Antonio Negri, Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State, trans. Maurizia Boscagli (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999).
    • (1999) Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State
    • Negri, A.1
  • 36
    • 0004114487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added, and 17 emphasis added
    • Schmitt, Political Theology, 10, 30 (emphasis added), and 17 (emphasis added).
    • Political Theology , pp. 10
    • Schmitt1
  • 38
    • 0002949221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deconstruction, pragmatism, hegemony
    • ed. by Chantal Mouffe (London: Verso)
    • Ernesto Laclau, "Deconstruction, Pragmatism, Hegemony," Deconstruction and Pragmatism, ed. by Chantal Mouffe (London: Verso, 1996), 54-55.
    • (1996) Deconstruction and Pragmatism , pp. 54-55
    • Laclau, E.1
  • 39
    • 0037602283 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Éditions du Seuil
    • For the most systematic treatment of the event, see Alain Badiou, L'étre et l'événement (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1988).
    • (1988) L'étre et L'événement
    • Badiou, A.1
  • 40
    • 0004114487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schmitt, Political Theology, 36-38; and Carl Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum Europaeum, trans. Gary Ulmen (New York: Telos Press, 2003), 82.
    • Political Theology , pp. 36-38
    • Schmitt1
  • 44
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 205, 206; and Hannah Arendt, "The Concept of History," Between Past and Future (hereafter, BPF) (New York: Penguin Books, 1961), 43.
    • HC , pp. 205
    • Arendt1
  • 45
    • 0012220806 scopus 로고
    • The concept of history
    • New York: Penguin Books
    • Arendt, HC, 205, 206; and Hannah Arendt, "The Concept of History," Between Past and Future (hereafter, BPF) (New York: Penguin Books, 1961), 43.
    • (1961) Between Past and Future (Hereafter, BPF) , pp. 43
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 46
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 190; Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (hereafter, OR (New York: Penguin Books, 1963), 205, 27, 172-173; and Hannah Arendt, "On Violence," Crisis of the Republic (hereafter, CR) (New York: A Harvest/HBJ Book, 1972), 109, 27.
    • HC , pp. 190
    • Arendt1
  • 47
    • 2542628465 scopus 로고
    • New York: Penguin Books
    • Arendt, HC, 190; Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (hereafter, OR (New York: Penguin Books, 1963), 205, 27, 172-173; and Hannah Arendt, "On Violence," Crisis of the Republic (hereafter, CR) (New York: A Harvest/HBJ Book, 1972), 109, 27.
    • (1963) On Revolution (Hereafter, OR) , pp. 205
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 48
    • 2542605617 scopus 로고
    • On violence
    • New York: A Harvest/HBJ Book
    • Arendt, HC, 190; Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (hereafter, OR (New York: Penguin Books, 1963), 205, 27, 172-173; and Hannah Arendt, "On Violence," Crisis of the Republic (hereafter, CR) (New York: A Harvest/HBJ Book, 1972), 109, 27.
    • (1972) Crisis of the Republic (Hereafter, CR) , pp. 109
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 49
    • 0011545083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is freedom?
    • Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" BPF, 169,170-171; and Arendt, "Preface," BPF, 5. Margaret Canovan has proposed a different reading of miracles in Arendt by disassociating them from new foundings. Her interpretation focuses on the Christian and theological origins of the concept of miracle, while placing political foundations and forms of constitutional making in the Roman political legacy. Notwithstanding its merits, this interpretation eludes the miraculous dimension of revolutions and new collective beginnings. In Canovan's reading, miracles are performed only by individuals. According to my reading, Arendt thought that revolutionary foundings were also miracles because they defied the preordered structure of normal politics. See Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought, 146-147.
    • BPF , pp. 169
    • Arendt1
  • 50
    • 79957759032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preface
    • Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" BPF, 169,170-171; and Arendt, "Preface," BPF, 5. Margaret Canovan has proposed a different reading of miracles in Arendt by disassociating them from new foundings. Her interpretation focuses on the Christian and theological origins of the concept of miracle, while placing political foundations and forms of constitutional making in the Roman political legacy. Notwithstanding its merits, this interpretation eludes the miraculous dimension of revolutions and new collective beginnings. In Canovan's reading, miracles are performed only by individuals. According to my reading, Arendt thought that revolutionary foundings were also miracles because they defied the preordered structure of normal politics. See Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought, 146-147.
    • BPF , pp. 5
    • Arendt1
  • 51
    • 0003549388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" BPF, 169,170-171; and Arendt, "Preface," BPF, 5. Margaret Canovan has proposed a different reading of miracles in Arendt by disassociating them from new foundings. Her interpretation focuses on the Christian and theological origins of the concept of miracle, while placing political foundations and forms of constitutional making in the Roman political legacy. Notwithstanding its merits, this interpretation eludes the miraculous dimension of revolutions and new collective beginnings. In Canovan's reading, miracles are performed only by individuals. According to my reading, Arendt thought that revolutionary foundings were also miracles because they defied the preordered structure of normal politics. See Margaret Canovan, Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought, 146-147.
    • Hannah Arendt. A Reinterpretation of Her Political Thought , pp. 146-147
    • Canovan, M.1
  • 52
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 190-191; "Willing," 195-217; Arendt "The Concept of History," 63; Arendt OR, 212.
    • HC , pp. 190-191
    • Arendt1
  • 53
    • 2542567560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 190-191; "Willing," 195-217; Arendt "The Concept of History," 63; Arendt OR, 212.
    • Willing , pp. 195-217
  • 54
  • 55
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 190-191; "Willing," 195-217; Arendt "The Concept of History," 63; Arendt OR, 212.
    • OR , pp. 212
    • Arendt1
  • 56
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 198-199, 202, 204; Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 152.
    • OR , pp. 198-199
    • Arendt1
  • 59
  • 60
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 145-147, 151-152; Arendt, OR, 76, 225.
    • OR , pp. 76
    • Arendt1
  • 62
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 234-236.
    • HC , pp. 234-236
    • Arendt1
  • 64
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 24, 153, 156-158, 163, 185.On the concept of the People-as-One that builds on Arendt's writings, see Claude Lefort, The Political Forms of Modern Society, Bureaucracy, Democracy, Totalitarianism, ed. by John B. Thompson (Cambridge: Polity, 1986), 297-304.
    • OR , pp. 24
    • Arendt1
  • 66
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 208, 63, 66; and Arendt, OR, 188-190, 194, 206.
    • OR , pp. 165
    • Arendt1
  • 67
    • 0004254117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 165, 194; and Arendt, "On Violence," 138.
    • On Violence , pp. 138
    • Arendt1
  • 68
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 208, 63, 66; and Arendt, OR, 188-190, 194, 206.
    • Willing , pp. 208
    • Arendt1
  • 69
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 208, 63, 66; and Arendt, OR, 188-190, 194, 206.
    • OR , pp. 188-190
    • Arendt1
  • 70
    • 2542593496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Postscriptum to thinking
    • Arendt, "Willing," 69, 207-208; Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 161. Interesting enough, Arendt comes extremely close to Hans Kelsen's discussion of the will. Like Arendt, Reisen attributed this demiurgic power of the will in the Judeo-Christian theological tradition. And like Arendt, he condemned this formulation in a polemic that is highly reminiscent of her own critique of the will. See Hans Reisen, "Foundations of Democracy," Ethics, 66, no. 1 (1955): 19-20.
    • LOM , pp. 215
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 71
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt, "Postscriptum to Thinking," LOM, 215; Arendt, "Willing," 68.
    • Willing , pp. 68
    • Arendt1
  • 72
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 69, 207-208; Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 161. Interesting enough, Arendt comes extremely close to Hans Kelsen's discussion of the will. Like Arendt, Reisen attributed this demiurgic power of the will in the Judeo-Christian theological tradition. And like Arendt, he condemned this formulation in a polemic that is highly reminiscent of her own critique of the will. See Hans Reisen, "Foundations of Democracy," Ethics, 66, no. 1 (1955): 19-20.
    • Willing , pp. 69
    • Arendt1
  • 73
    • 0038524901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 69, 207-208; Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 161. Interesting enough, Arendt comes extremely close to Hans Kelsen's discussion of the will. Like Arendt, Reisen attributed this demiurgic power of the will in the Judeo-Christian theological tradition. And like Arendt, he condemned this formulation in a polemic that is highly reminiscent of her own critique of the will. See Hans Reisen, "Foundations of Democracy," Ethics, 66, no. 1 (1955): 19-20.
    • What is Freedom? , pp. 161
    • Arendt1
  • 74
    • 2542584176 scopus 로고
    • Foundations of democracy
    • Arendt, "Willing," 69, 207-208; Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 161. Interesting enough, Arendt comes extremely close to Hans Kelsen's discussion of the will. Like Arendt, Reisen attributed this demiurgic power of the will in the Judeo-Christian theological tradition. And like Arendt, he condemned this formulation in a polemic that is highly reminiscent of her own critique of the will. See Hans Reisen, "Foundations of Democracy," Ethics, 66, no. 1 (1955): 19-20.
    • (1955) Ethics , vol.66 , Issue.1 , pp. 19-20
    • Reisen, H.1
  • 75
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 94.
    • OR , pp. 94
    • Arendt1
  • 78
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 78; Arendt, OR, 155.
    • Willing , pp. 78
    • Arendt1
  • 79
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 78; Arendt, OR, 155.
    • OR , pp. 155
    • Arendt1
  • 80
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 17.
    • HC , pp. 17
    • Arendt1
  • 82
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 206.
    • OR , pp. 206
    • Arendt1
  • 83
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 208; Arendt, OR, 186.
    • Willing , pp. 208
    • Arendt1
  • 84
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 208; Arendt, OR, 186.
    • OR , pp. 186
    • Arendt1
  • 85
    • 2542563066 scopus 로고
    • ed. by Allen W. Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. by Allen W. Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 38-39.
    • (1991) Elements of the Philosophy of Right , pp. 38-39
    • Hegel1
  • 87
    • 0004276213 scopus 로고
    • trans. R. H. M. Elwes (New York: Dover Publications)
    • Benedict de Spinoza, A Theologico-Political Treatise, trans. R. H. M. Elwes (New York: Dover Publications, 1951), 211.
    • (1951) A Theologico-political Treatise , pp. 211
    • De Spinoza, B.1
  • 90
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pt. II, chap. 26, 184
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pt. II, chap. 26, 184.
    • (1992) Leviathan
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 91
  • 92
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 77, 163.
    • OR , pp. 77
    • Arendt1
  • 93
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 125.
    • OR , pp. 125
    • Arendt1
  • 94
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 83; Arendt, OR, 93, 144, 159, 125.
    • Willing , pp. 83
    • Arendt1
  • 95
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 83; Arendt, OR, 93, 144, 159, 125.
    • OR , pp. 93
    • Arendt1
  • 96
    • 0038524901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fn. 21
    • Arendt, "What Is Freedom?" 296, fn. 21. Arendt fails to see the significant differences between Rousseau's and Schmitt's notions of sovereignty, particularly the instituting dimension of the latter. Schmitt's version fuses the legislator and the people instead of keeping them separate as Rousseau did.
    • What is Freedom? , pp. 296
    • Arendt1
  • 97
    • 0003776036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. George Schwab, foreword by Tracy B. Strong (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, trans. George Schwab, foreword by Tracy B. Strong (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 39. Jeremy Waldron misses this aspect of Arendt's theory, gratuitously claiming that she relied on a Schmittian understanding of enmity. Jeremy Waldron, "Arendt's Constitutional Politics," Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, 206. By contrast, for an illuminating discussion of Arendt's rejection of the friend/enemy distinction, see Dana R. Villa, Politics, Philosophy, Terror. Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999), 81, 109, 123.
    • (1996) The Concept of the Political , pp. 39
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 98
    • 0242431319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt's constitutional politics
    • Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, trans. George Schwab, foreword by Tracy B. Strong (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 39. Jeremy Waldron misses this aspect of Arendt's theory, gratuitously claiming that she relied on a Schmittian understanding of enmity. Jeremy Waldron, "Arendt's Constitutional Politics," Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, 206. By contrast, for an illuminating discussion of Arendt's rejection of the friend/enemy distinction, see Dana R. Villa, Politics, Philosophy, Terror. Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999), 81, 109, 123.
    • Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt , pp. 206
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 99
    • 0037510970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, trans. George Schwab, foreword by Tracy B. Strong (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 39. Jeremy Waldron misses this aspect of Arendt's theory, gratuitously claiming that she relied on a Schmittian understanding of enmity. Jeremy Waldron, "Arendt's Constitutional Politics," Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, 206. By contrast, for an illuminating discussion of Arendt's rejection of the friend/enemy distinction, see Dana R. Villa, Politics, Philosophy, Terror. Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999), 81, 109, 123.
    • (1999) Politics, Philosophy, Terror. Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt , pp. 81
    • Villa, D.R.1
  • 100
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 200; Arendt, OR, 164.
    • HC , pp. 200
    • Arendt1
  • 101
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 200; Arendt, OR, 164.
    • OR , pp. 164
    • Arendt1
  • 102
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 91.
    • OR , pp. 91
    • Arendt1
  • 103
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 77.
    • OR , pp. 77
    • Arendt1
  • 104
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 78.
    • OR , pp. 78
    • Arendt1
  • 105
    • 84998158305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • Arendt, TOT, 468 (emphasis added).
    • TOT , pp. 468
    • Arendt1
  • 106
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • Arendt, HC, 186 (emphasis added).
    • HC , pp. 186
    • Arendt1
  • 107
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (emphasis added), 245, 186-187
    • Arendt, HC, 246 (emphasis added), 245, 186-187.
    • HC , pp. 246
    • Arendt1
  • 108
    • 0242514722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil disobedience
    • emphasis added
    • Hannah Arendt, "Civil Disobedience," CR, 98 (emphasis added).
    • CR , pp. 98
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 109
    • 0004254117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • Arendt, "On Violence," 118 (emphasis added).
    • On Violence , pp. 118
    • Arendt1
  • 110
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 243.
    • HC , pp. 243
    • Arendt1
  • 111
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 245.
    • HC , pp. 245
    • Arendt1
  • 112
    • 84893616583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, HC, 245. For an enlightening discussion of Arendt's shifting views on sovereignty, see Hanna Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob. Hannah Arendt's Concept of the Social (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 199-200.
    • HC , pp. 245
    • Arendt1
  • 113
    • 84909395949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Arendt, HC, 245. For an enlightening discussion of Arendt's shifting views on sovereignty, see Hanna Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob. Hannah Arendt's Concept of the Social (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 199-200.
    • (1998) The Attack of the Blob. Hannah Arendt's Concept of the Social , pp. 199-200
    • Pitkin, H.1
  • 114
  • 115
  • 116
    • 0002967558 scopus 로고
    • Understanding and politics
    • ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace)
    • In a seminal 1953 essay, Arendt transposes the power to make new beginnings solely to political freedom. Hannah Arendt, "Understanding and Politics," Essays in Understanding: 1930-1954, ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1994), 320-321.
    • (1994) Essays in Understanding: 1930-1954 , pp. 320-321
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 118
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 6-7, 109-110, 130-131.
    • Willing , pp. 6-7
    • Arendt1
  • 120
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 214. For Arendt's silence, see Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," 54.
    • Willing , pp. 214
    • Arendt1
  • 123
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 5, 89. For a discussion of the relationship between freedom and will in Arendt, see J. Glenn Gray, "The Abyss of Freedom-and Hannah Arendt," Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, 227-228. It should be noted, however, that Gray remains unaware of the shift in Arendt's thought discussed here. By contrast, Pitkin has argued that Arendt's notion of political freedom cannot be completely separated from the idea of free will. Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob, 245.
    • Willing , pp. 5
    • Arendt1
  • 124
    • 84925210765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The abyss of freedom-and Hannah Arendt
    • Arendt, "Willing," 5, 89. For a discussion of the relationship between freedom and will in Arendt, see J. Glenn Gray, "The Abyss of Freedom-and Hannah Arendt," Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, 227-228. It should be noted, however, that Gray remains unaware of the shift in Arendt's thought discussed here. By contrast, Pitkin has argued that Arendt's notion of political freedom cannot be completely separated from the idea of free will. Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob, 245.
    • Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World , pp. 227-228
    • Gray, J.G.1
  • 125
    • 2542566059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 5, 89. For a discussion of the relationship between freedom and will in Arendt, see J. Glenn Gray, "The Abyss of Freedom-and Hannah Arendt," Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, 227-228. It should be noted, however, that Gray remains unaware of the shift in Arendt's thought discussed here. By contrast, Pitkin has argued that Arendt's notion of political freedom cannot be completely separated from the idea of free will. Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob, 245.
    • The Attack of the Blob , pp. 245
    • Pitkin1
  • 126
    • 2542587297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, see Jacobitti's incisive discussion in "Hannah Arendt and the Will," 59, 62-70.
    • Hannah Arendt and the Will , pp. 59
  • 127
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 13, 14, 155, 196.
    • Willing , pp. 13
    • Arendt1
  • 128
    • 0004040659 scopus 로고
    • New York: Viking Press
    • In her book on the trial of Adolf Eichmann Arendt has complained about a "reluctance evident everywhere to make judgments in terms of individual moral responsibility," because of the tendency to think that no one has the right to judge somebody else. What public opinion permits us to judge and even to condemn are trends, or whole groups of people-the larger the better-in short, something so general that distinctions can no longer be made, names no longer named. Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Viking Press, 1965), 297, 296.
    • (1965) Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil , pp. 297
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 129
    • 2542575113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • Hannah Arendt, "Introduction," LOM.
    • LOM
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 130
    • 2542515699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking
    • Arendt, "Thinking," LOM, 97. Similarly, Castoriadis has argued that "If reflection does not will something, it is not reflection." Cornelius Castoriadis, The Castoriadis Reader, trans. David Ames Curtis (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 393.
    • LOM , pp. 97
    • Arendt1
  • 131
    • 0004231227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. David Ames Curtis (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Arendt, "Thinking," LOM, 97. Similarly, Castoriadis has argued that "If reflection does not will something, it is not reflection." Cornelius Castoriadis, The Castoriadis Reader, trans. David Ames Curtis (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 393.
    • (1997) The Castoriadis Reader , pp. 393
    • Castoriadis, C.1
  • 132
  • 133
    • 0001892831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Remarks on deconstruction and pragmatism
    • Jacques Derrida, "Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism," Deconstruction and Pragmatism, 84. In a similar vein, Laclau speaks of the subject of the decision as a "partial subject." Ernesto Laclau, "Identity and Hegemony: The Role of Universality in the Constitution of Political Logics," Contingency, Hegemony, Universality, ed. by Judith Butler, Emesto Laclau, and Slavoj Zizek (London: Verso, 2000), 83.
    • Deconstruction and Pragmatism , pp. 84
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 134
    • 0242598187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Identity and hegemony: The role of universality in the constitution of political logics
    • ed. by Judith Butler, Emesto Laclau, and Slavoj Zizek (London: Verso)
    • Jacques Derrida, "Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism," Deconstruction and Pragmatism, 84. In a similar vein, Laclau speaks of the subject of the decision as a "partial subject." Ernesto Laclau, "Identity and Hegemony: The Role of Universality in the Constitution of Political Logics," Contingency, Hegemony, Universality, ed. by Judith Butler, Emesto Laclau, and Slavoj Zizek (London: Verso, 2000), 83.
    • (2000) Contingency, Hegemony, Universality , pp. 83
    • Laclau, E.1
  • 141
    • 34249788849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The crisis of culture: Its social and political significance
    • emphasis added
    • Hannah Arendt, "The Crisis of Culture: Its Social and Political Significance," BPF, 223 (emphasis added).
    • BPF , pp. 223
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 142
    • 2542573567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deconstructions: The im-possible
    • ed. by Sylvère Lotringer and Sande Cohen (New York: Routledge)
    • Jacques Derrida, "Deconstructions: The Im-possible," French Theory in America, ed. by Sylvère Lotringer and Sande Cohen (New York: Routledge, 2001), 27; and Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Death, trans. Davil Wills (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 5-7, 25-26.
    • (2001) French Theory in America , pp. 27
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 143
    • 0004271135 scopus 로고
    • trans. Davil Wills (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • Jacques Derrida, "Deconstructions: The Im-possible," French Theory in America, ed. by Sylvère Lotringer and Sande Cohen (New York: Routledge, 2001), 27; and Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Death, trans. Davil Wills (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 5-7, 25-26.
    • (1995) The Gift of Death , pp. 5-7
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 144
    • 2542593497 scopus 로고
    • Arendt: The return of the political
    • Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanity Press
    • A possible answer to these questions can be extracted from Bernard Flynn's argument that the will cannot be of any political relevance for Arendt because it is mute and solitary, thus opposed to the dialogical, plural, and public character of politics. Flynn is right to claim that some properties of the will do not fit naturally in Arendt's understanding of the political. His claim cannot be accepted, however, if the question is not whether to replace the faculty of speech with the will, but to selectively introduce elements of the will in Arendt's theory of politics. Once we break with Flynn's either/or dilemmatic approach to the relationship between the will and politics, it becomes possible to adopt a more dialectical and selective approach. See Bernard Flynn, "Arendt: The Return of the Political," Political Philosophy at the Closure of Metaphysics (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanity Press, 1992), 116-118.
    • (1992) Political Philosophy at the Closure of Metaphysics , pp. 116-118
    • Flynn, B.1
  • 148
    • 39649093881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tradition in the modern age
    • Hannah Arendt, "Tradition in the Modern Age," BPF, 25.
    • BPF , pp. 25
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 149
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 7. By doing so, she becomes Schmitt's inverted mirror image: his monistic 'politics of the will" is replaced by her equally monistic 'will-less politics of opinion.'
    • Willing , pp. 7
    • Arendt1
  • 154
    • 2542596526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The abyss of freedom and the novus ordo seclorum
    • Arendt, "The Abyss of Freedom and the novus ordo seclorum," LOM, 203. In such a case, even Arendt's unattainable distinction between the social and the political can be overcome from within her own theoretical framework.
    • LOM , pp. 203
    • Arendt1
  • 155
    • 84893631903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, OR, 279, 280.
    • OR , pp. 279
    • Arendt1
  • 157
  • 158
    • 84871083767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, "Willing," 140; and Jacobitti, "Hannah Arendt and the Will," 54, 56.
    • Willing , pp. 140
    • Arendt1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.