메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 41, Issue 1, 2002, Pages 25-42

The psychological basis of historical explanation: Reenactment, simulation, and the fusion of horizons

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 24944477947     PISSN: 00182656     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1468-2303.00189     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (36)

References (32)
  • 1
    • 0003626641 scopus 로고
    • New York: Free Press, and David-Hillel Ruben, Explaining Explanation, London: Routledge
    • See Carl Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanations (New York: Free Press, 1965), and David-Hillel Ruben, Explaining Explanation (London: Routledge, 1990).
    • (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanations
    • Hempel, C.1
  • 2
    • 0013081829 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For an excellent analysis of Collingwood's claim regarding the scope of reenactment, see W. H. Dray, History as Re-enactment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995). I benefited greatly from Dray's interpretation of Collingwood. Nevertheless, it is helpful to situate Collingwood in the contemporary debate about simulation theory for a systematic reconstruction and evaluation of his theory of reenactment
    • (1995) History as Re-enactment
    • Dray, W.H.1
  • 3
    • 0004233481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of History [1945] (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 219
    • (1945) The Idea of History , pp. 219
    • Collingwood, R.G.1
  • 4
    • 0004215560 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass, MIT Press, chap. 4
    • For a brief description of our folk-psychological repertoire, see H. Wellman, The Child's Theory of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990), chap. 4
    • (1990) The Child's Theory of Mind
    • Wellman, H.1
  • 5
    • 0004229883 scopus 로고
    • the introduction in, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
    • For good survey of the debate in the philosophy of mind and psychology, see the introduction in Folk Psychology, ed. Martin Davies and Tony Stone (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1995)
    • (1995) Folk Psychology
    • Davies, M.1    Stone, T.2
  • 6
    • 24744440286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an analysis of it in the context of traditional philosophy of social science, see especially the detailed introduction in Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences, ed. Hans Herbert Kögler and Karsten Stueber (Boulder: Westview Press, 2000)
    • (2000) Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences
  • 7
    • 80054129360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Replication and Functionalism
    • Davies and Stone, eds. , 47 and Alvin Goldman, Interpretation Psychologized, in ibid
    • Jane Heal, "Replication and Functionalism," in Davies and Stone, eds. Folk Psychology, 47 and Alvin Goldman, "Interpretation Psychologized," in ibid., 85
    • Folk Psychology , pp. 85
    • Heal, J.1
  • 8
    • 0003350621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in ibid
    • For a distinct and radical version of simulation theory, see also Robert Gordon, "Folk Psychology as Simulation," in ibid., 60-73
    • Folk Psychology as Simulation , pp. 60-73
    • Gordon, R.1
  • 9
    • 0002572037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Radical' Simulationism
    • Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge University Press
    • and "'Radical' Simulationism," in Theories of Theories of Mind, ed. Peter Carruthers and Peter Smith (Cambridge, Eng. : Cambridge University Press, 1996), 11-21
    • (1996) Theories of Theories of Mind , pp. 11-21
    • Carruthers, P.1    Smith, P.2
  • 10
    • 0000811122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cognitive Penetrability, Rationality and Restricted Simulation
    • Stephen Stich and Shaun Nichols, "Cognitive Penetrability, Rationality and Restricted Simulation," Mind and Language 12 (1997), 297-326
    • (1997) Mind and Language , vol.12 , pp. 297-326
    • Stich, S.1    Nichols, S.2
  • 12
    • 84869924766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empathy and Agency, Introduction
    • For a survey about this topic and the debate between Dray and Hempel see Kögler and Stueber, eds. Empathy and Agency, Introduction, 12-17, In the recently discovered manuscript The Principles of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999) Collingwood seems to focus more on this aspect of the difference between history and the natural sciences. Indeed he does not mention reenactment at all. He stresses rather that in contrast to the natural sciences, the historical sciences are essentially "criteriological" sciences (84), because they cannot investigate human action and thought without appealing to normative distinctions such as acting wisely or foolishly and thinking truly or falsely. However, as I will argue in the following, there is a close connection between the necessity for reenactment and the criteriological character of the historical sciences
    • (1999) The Principles of History
    • Kögler1    Stueber2
  • 13
    • 0003362978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simulation, Theory and Content
    • Carruthers and Smith
    • Heal, "Simulation, Theory and Content," in Carruthers and Smith, eds. , Theories of Theories of Mind, 79.
    • Theories of Theories of Mind , pp. 79
    • Heal1
  • 14
    • 34250834850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simulation and Epistemic Competence
    • Kögler and Stueber, eds., 123ff
    • For an elaboration of this argument see also David Henderson and Terry Horgan, "Simulation and Epistemic Competence," in Kögler and Stueber, eds., Empathy and Agency, 123ff
    • Empathy and Agency
    • Henderson, D.1    Horgan, T.2
  • 16
    • 85047112349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding Other Minds and the Problem of Rationality
    • Kögler and Stueber, eds
    • Karsten Stueber, "Understanding Other Minds and the Problem of Rationality," in Kögler and Stueber, eds., Empathy and Agency, 144-162
    • Empathy and Agency , pp. 144-162
    • Stueber, K.1
  • 17
    • 31844438338 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, 16. Ibid., 104
    • R. G. Collingwood, Autobiography (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1939), 101. 16. Ibid., 104
    • (1939) Autobiography , pp. 101
    • Collingwood, R.G.1
  • 18
    • 84869957665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the continental tradition of philosophy Dieter Henrich and Manfred Frank argue similarly. especially M. Frank, Selbstbewußtsein und Selbsterkenntnis Stuttgart: Reclam, 1991
    • In the continental tradition of philosophy Dieter Henrich and Manfred Frank argue similarly. See especially M. Frank, Selbstbewußtsein und Selbsterkenntnis (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1991)
  • 19
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고
    • transl. Norman Kemp Smith London: Macmillan
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, transl. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1953), B131
    • (1953) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 20
    • 0040811436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reason and the First Person
    • ed. C. Wright, B. Smith, and C. Macdonald Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Tyler Burge, "Reason and the First Person," in Knowing Our Own Minds, ed. C. Wright, B. Smith, and C. Macdonald (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), 256
    • (1998) Knowing Our Own Minds , pp. 256
    • Burge, T.1
  • 21
    • 0009028835 scopus 로고
    • The Problem of the Essential Indexical
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • John Perry, "The Problem of the Essential Indexical," in The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 33-52.
    • (1993) The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays , pp. 33-52
    • Perry, J.1
  • 22
    • 80054172429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, The T Think, and Self-Awareness
    • See Robert Howell, "Kant, The T Think,' and Self-Awareness," in Kant's Legacy, Essays in Honor of Lewis White Beck, ed. Predrag Cicovacki (Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 2001) supporting this point of view. In her article, "On Interpreting Kant's Thinker as Wittgenstein's T,"' in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2000), 33-63, Patricia Kitcher takes issue with this interpretation of Kant. She reminds us that Kant's reflections on the have to be situated within his larger epistemic project. I think that, insofar as her critique of McDowell's take on Kant is concerned, her point is well taken. Yet, pace Kitcher, I do not think that Perry-like considerations about the "I" are necessarily incompatible with Kant's larger epistemological project. Kitcher argues that Kant could be interpreted in that manner only if he had asserted a "philosophically interesting asymmetry between first person and third person ascriptions of mental states" (49). She cites the same passage that 1 quote, in support of the view that Kant did not acknowledge such an asymmetry. Yet only in the context of a Cartesian conception of the mind, which Kant rejects, does the other mind problem arise. If one accepts, on the other hand, that other persons are psychologically structured similarly as I am, either for empirical or transcendental reasons, then one can accept simulation as a method of recognizing other minds and at the same time acknowledge the special status of the I-concept. More importantly, if I am right, accepting such special status supports a conception of interpretation favored by Collingwood and simulation theorists."I"
    • (2000) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.61 , pp. 33-63
    • Howell, R.1
  • 23
    • 0004225610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2nd rev. edition New York: Crossroad Publishing
    • Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd rev. edition (New York: Crossroad Publishing, 1989), 373
    • (1989) Truth and Method , pp. 373
    • Gadamer H., -G.1
  • 24
    • 84891872690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am mainly interested in what I take to be Gadamer's paradigmatic critique of reenactment as a psychologistic conception of interpretation, not in an exhaustive critique of Gadamer. At times Gadamer even seems to admit the role of intentions in interpretations and comes close to arguing for something like reenactment. See, for example, Truth and Method, 333-334. One thus could see the difference between Gadamer and Collingwood as quantitative and not qualitative, as one reader for this journal has suggested. They differ in regard to how optimistic they are in regard to our ability to connect to other minds. This indeed is a plausible and maybe the most charitable interpretation of Gadamer. Yet in his explicit critique of Collingwood, Gadamer seems to reject Collingwood's notion of reenactment wholeheartedly; I am interested in probing whether his arguments hold up under scrutiny in this respect. Interestingly enough, Gadamer distinguishes strictly between the understanding of another person in everyday oral communication and the understanding of the written tradition. In an oral communication we understand a speaker only if we reconstruct his intentions; only then can we grasp what he or she meant. Yet such a psychological conception of understanding does not apply to our understanding of written texts
    • Truth and Method , pp. 333-334
  • 25
    • 0009398665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflections on My Philosophical Journey
    • Chicago: Open Court
    • See his "Reflections on My Philosophical Journey," in The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer, ed. L. E. Hahn (Chicago: Open Court, 1997), 52f. As my argument in this section will show, however, such a strict distinction can hardly be sustained
    • (1997) The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer
    • Hahn, L.E.1
  • 27
    • 80054172443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Source of the Subjective
    • I therefore agree with Ramberg, who maintains against Gadamer that we have to take into account the intention of agents, otherwise "agents drop out of the picture along with authors." See B. Ramberg, "The Source of the Subjective," in Hahn, ed., The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer, 465. Yet this critique of Gadamer applies only insofar as the rationalizing explanation of action and the interpretation of certain texts are concerned. It does not apply immediately to literary texts whose interpretation Gadamer takes to be paradigmatic
    • The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer , pp. 465
    • Ramberg, B.1
  • 28
    • 85047162398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Object of Understanding
    • See in this regard the work of Paul Roth, who argues for a position of narrative antirealism. See especially his article "The Object of Understanding," in Kogler and Stueber, eds. , Empathy and Agency, 243-269. However, given the argument I present in this article, I would opt for a realistically grounded conception of historical narratives; but this needs to be developed in more detail in another article
    • Empathy and Agency , pp. 243-269
    • Kogler1    Stueber2
  • 31
    • 80054129300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding Other Minds and the Problem of Rationality. especially 154-160
    • See my "Understanding Other Minds and the Problem of Rationality." especially 154-160
  • 32
    • 80054188287 scopus 로고
    • Understanding Truth and Objectivity: A Dialogue Between Donald Davidson and Hans Georg Gadamer
    • Chicago: Northwestern University Press
    • For my take on the question of interpretive relativism, see also the last section of my "Understanding Truth and Objectivity: A Dialogue Between Donald Davidson and Hans Georg Gadamer," in Hermeneutics and Truth, ed. Brice Wachterhauser (Chicago: Northwestern University Press, 1994), 183-189
    • (1994) Hermeneutics and Truth , pp. 183-189
    • Wachterhauser, B.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.