메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 79, Issue 1, 2004, Pages 1-58

Digital speech and democratic culture: A theory of freedom of expression for the information society

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 2442473073     PISSN: 00287881     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (336)

References (197)
  • 1
    • 0037483158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cyberspace and the law of the horse
    • See, e.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, Cyberspace and the Law of the Horse, 1996 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 207, 216 (arguing that clear rules, property rights, and facilitating bargains will resolve regulatory problems in cyberspace much as they do in real space); Joseph H. Sommer, Against Cyberlaw, 15 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 1145, 1148 (2000) ("[F]ew of the legal issues posed by the new informatics technologies are novel.").
    • (1996) U. Chi. Legal F. , pp. 207
    • Easterbrook, F.H.1
  • 2
    • 2442506544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against cyberlaw
    • See, e.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, Cyberspace and the Law of the Horse, 1996 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 207, 216 (arguing that clear rules, property rights, and facilitating bargains will resolve regulatory problems in cyberspace much as they do in real space); Joseph H. Sommer, Against Cyberlaw, 15 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 1145, 1148 (2000) ("[F]ew of the legal issues posed by the new informatics technologies are novel.").
    • (2000) Berkeley Tech. L.J. , vol.15 , pp. 1145
    • Sommer, J.H.1
  • 3
    • 84937291348 scopus 로고
    • Populism and progressivism as constitutional categories
    • See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). Media and popular culture theorist John Fiske has coined the term "semiotic democracy" to describe popular participation in the creation of meanings, often by turning existing forms of mass culture to different uses. JOHN FISKE, TELEVISION CULTURE 236-39 (1987); see also Michael Madow, Private Ownership of Public Image: Popular Culture and Publicity Rights, 81 CAL. L. REV. 125, 146 (1993) (defining semiotic democracy as "a society in which all persons are free and able to participate actively, if not equally, in the generation and circulation of meanings and values"). Fiske's idea has become particularly important in the intellectual property literature. See infra note 56.
    • (1995) Yale L.J. , vol.104 , pp. 1935
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 4
    • 0003746578 scopus 로고
    • reviewing
    • See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). Media and popular culture theorist John Fiske has coined the term "semiotic democracy" to describe popular participation in the creation of meanings, often by turning existing forms of mass culture to different uses. JOHN FISKE, TELEVISION CULTURE 236-39 (1987); see also Michael Madow, Private Ownership of Public Image: Popular Culture and Publicity Rights, 81 CAL. L. REV. 125, 146 (1993) (defining semiotic democracy as "a society in which all persons are free and able to participate actively, if not equally, in the generation and circulation of meanings and values"). Fiske's idea has become particularly important in the intellectual property literature. See infra note 56.
    • (1993) Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 5
    • 0004162144 scopus 로고
    • See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). Media and popular culture theorist John Fiske has coined the term "semiotic democracy" to describe popular participation in the creation of meanings, often by turning existing forms of mass culture to different uses. JOHN FISKE, TELEVISION CULTURE 236-39 (1987); see also Michael Madow, Private Ownership of Public Image: Popular Culture and Publicity Rights, 81 CAL. L. REV. 125, 146 (1993) (defining semiotic democracy as "a society in which all persons are free and able to participate actively, if not equally, in the generation and circulation of meanings and values"). Fiske's idea has become particularly important in the intellectual property literature. See infra note 56.
    • (1987) Television Culture , pp. 236-239
    • Fiske, J.1
  • 6
    • 79958214400 scopus 로고
    • Private ownership of public image: Popular culture and publicity rights
    • See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). Media and popular culture theorist John Fiske has coined the term "semiotic democracy" to describe popular participation in the creation of meanings, often by turning existing forms of mass culture to different uses. JOHN FISKE, TELEVISION CULTURE 236-39 (1987); see also Michael Madow, Private Ownership of Public Image: Popular Culture and Publicity Rights, 81 CAL. L. REV. 125, 146 (1993) (defining semiotic democracy as "a society in which all persons are free and able to participate actively, if not equally, in the generation and circulation of meanings and values"). Fiske's idea has become particularly important in the intellectual property literature. See infra note 56.
    • (1993) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 125
    • Madow, M.1
  • 7
    • 2442487608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra note 56
    • See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). See J.M. Balkin, Populism and Progressivism as Constitutional Categories, 104 YALE L.J. 1935, 1948-49 (1995) (reviewing CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993), and defining democratic culture as popular participation in culture). Media and popular culture theorist John Fiske has coined the term "semiotic democracy" to describe popular participation in the creation of meanings, often by turning existing forms of mass culture to different uses. JOHN FISKE, TELEVISION CULTURE 236-39 (1987); see also Michael Madow, Private Ownership of Public Image: Popular Culture and Publicity Rights, 81 CAL. L. REV. 125, 146 (1993) (defining semiotic democracy as "a society in which all persons are free and able to participate actively, if not equally, in the generation and circulation of meanings and values"). Fiske's idea has become particularly important in the intellectual property literature. See infra note 56.
  • 8
    • 2442477235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1948-49
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1948-49.
  • 10
    • 0039449064 scopus 로고
    • Limited Inc a b c ...
    • Cf. Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc a b c ..., in 2 GLYPH 162, 200 (1977) ("Iterability alters[.]"). Jed Rubenfeld expresses a similar idea through the metaphor of imagination. He argues that freedom of speech protects the rights of both authors and readers because acts of imagination are inevitably transformative, both for producers and receivers of cultural objects. Jed Rubenfeld, The Freedom of Imagination: Copyright's Constitutionality, 112 YALE L.J. 1, 37-38 (2002). Rebecca Tushnet points out that repetition of ideas or social scripts can be a way of expressing solidarity with others, support for a favored cause, or one's own sense of propriety as a member of a religious, political, or social group. Rebecca Tushnet, Copyright as a Model for Free Speech Law: What Copyright Has in Common with Anti-Pornography Laws, Campaign Finance Reform, and Telecommunications Regulation, 42 B.C. L. REV. 1, 16-17 (2001).
    • (1977) Glyph , vol.2 , pp. 162
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 11
    • 2442609498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The freedom of imagination: Copyright's constitutionality
    • Cf. Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc a b c ..., in 2 GLYPH 162, 200 (1977) ("Iterability alters[.]"). Jed Rubenfeld expresses a similar idea through the metaphor of imagination. He argues that freedom of speech protects the rights of both authors and readers because acts of imagination are inevitably transformative, both for producers and receivers of cultural objects. Jed Rubenfeld, The Freedom of Imagination: Copyright's Constitutionality, 112 YALE L.J. 1, 37-38 (2002). Rebecca Tushnet points out that repetition of ideas or social scripts can be a way of expressing solidarity with others, support for a favored cause, or one's own sense of propriety as a member of a religious, political, or social group. Rebecca Tushnet, Copyright as a Model for Free Speech Law: What Copyright Has in Common with Anti-Pornography Laws, Campaign Finance Reform, and Telecommunications Regulation, 42 B.C. L. REV. 1, 16-17 (2001).
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , Issue.1 , pp. 37-38
    • Rubenfeld, J.1
  • 12
    • 77951593529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Copyright as a model for free speech law: What copyright has in common with anti-pornography laws, campaign finance reform, and telecommunications regulation
    • Cf. Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc a b c ..., in 2 GLYPH 162, 200 (1977) ("Iterability alters[.]"). Jed Rubenfeld expresses a similar idea through the metaphor of imagination. He argues that freedom of speech protects the rights of both authors and readers because acts of imagination are inevitably transformative, both for producers and receivers of cultural objects. Jed Rubenfeld, The Freedom of Imagination: Copyright's Constitutionality, 112 YALE L.J. 1, 37-38 (2002). Rebecca Tushnet points out that repetition of ideas or social scripts can be a way of expressing solidarity with others, support for a favored cause, or one's own sense of propriety as a member of a religious, political, or social group. Rebecca Tushnet, Copyright as a Model for Free Speech Law: What Copyright Has in Common with Anti-Pornography Laws, Campaign Finance Reform, and Telecommunications Regulation, 42 B.C. L. REV. 1, 16-17 (2001).
    • (2001) B.C. L. Rev. , vol.42 , Issue.1 , pp. 16-17
    • Tushnet, R.1
  • 13
    • 2442554764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Apr. 4) (unpublished manuscript, on file with New York University Law Review)
    • See Jack M. Balkin, Free Speech From a Meme's Point of View 8, 13 (Apr. 4, 2003) (unpublished manuscript, on file with New York University Law Review) (explaining rapid growth of expression on Internet in terms of lowered costs of production and distribution of information).
    • (2003) Free Speech from a Meme's Point of View , pp. 8
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 14
    • 21344458236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Media filters, the V-Chip, and the foundations of broadcast regulation
    • See J.M. Balkin, Media Filters, the V-Chip, and the Foundations of Broadcast Regulation, 45 DUKE L.J. 1131, 1145 (1996) ("In the Information Age, the informational filter, not information itself, is king."); James Boyle, Foucault in Cyberspace: Surveillance, Sovereignty, and Hardwired Censors, 66 U. CIN. L. REV. 177, 194 (1997) (noting that filtering technologies supply state with "a different arsenal of methods with which to regulate content").
    • (1996) Duke L.J. , vol.45 , pp. 1131
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 15
    • 21944439424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foucault in cyberspace: Surveillance, sovereignty, and hardwired censors
    • See J.M. Balkin, Media Filters, the V-Chip, and the Foundations of Broadcast Regulation, 45 DUKE L.J. 1131, 1145 (1996) ("In the Information Age, the informational filter, not information itself, is king."); James Boyle, Foucault in Cyberspace: Surveillance, Sovereignty, and Hardwired Censors, 66 U. CIN. L. REV. 177, 194 (1997) (noting that filtering technologies supply state with "a different arsenal of methods with which to regulate content").
    • (1997) U. Cin. L. Rev. , vol.66 , pp. 177
    • Boyle, J.1
  • 16
    • 2442554797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Lowering the costs of distribution also allows more speakers to reach across existing cultural, geographical, and disciplinary boundaries. It allows information to get past previously closed communities, it enables new communities to form based on existing interests, and it helps create new interests around which communities can form.
  • 17
    • 0141616764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I borrow this term from C. EDWIN BAKER, MEDIA, MARKETS, AND DEMOCRACY 7-14 (2002) (noting important differences between media products and typical noninformation goods).
    • (2002) Media, Markets, and Democracy , pp. 7-14
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 18
    • 2442539990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On The Phantom Edit, see Richard Fausset, A Phantom Menace?, L.A. TIMES, June 1, 2002, at F1.
    • The Phantom Edit
  • 19
    • 0242685821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A phantom menace?
    • June 1
    • On The Phantom Edit, see Richard Fausset, A Phantom Menace?, L.A. TIMES, June 1, 2002, at F1.
    • (2002) L.A. Times
    • Fausset, R.1
  • 20
    • 2442510766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The genius of the system: George Lucas talks to Gavin Smith about painting by numbers, mind-numbing minutiae, and final cuts
    • July-Aug.
    • Asked about the phenomenon by an interviewer, Lucas explained, [E]verybody wants to be a filmmaker. Part of what I was hoping for with making movies in the first place was to inspire people to be creative. The Phantom Edit was fine as long as they didn't start selling it. Once they started selling it, it became a piracy issue. I'm on the Artist Rights Foundation board, and the issue of non-creators of a movie going in and changing things and then selling it as something else is wrong. Gavin Smith, The Genius of the System: George Lucas Talks to Gavin Smith About Painting by Numbers, Mind-Numbing Minutiae, and Final Cuts, FILM COMMENT, July-Aug. 2002, at 31, 32.
    • (2002) Film Comment , pp. 31
    • Smith, G.1
  • 21
    • 0042725394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A politics of intellectual property: Environmentalism for the net?
    • James Boyle argues that a characteristic feature of the information society is that an increasing proportion of product cost goes to content creation rather than to distribution, and to message rather than medium. James Boyle, A Politics of Intellectual Property: Environmentalism for the Net?, 47 DUKE L.J. 87, 93-94 (1997). That is not necessarily inconsistent with my argument that digital technologies lower costs of innovation: Both content creation and distribution costs are lowered, but distribution costs decline much more rapidly. In the meantime, digital technologies spur new forms of content creation that would have been prohibitively expensive (or impossible) in the past.
    • (1997) Duke L.J. , vol.47 , pp. 87
    • Boyle, J.1
  • 22
    • 84862356822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • last visited Nov. 17, 2003
    • For a list of some of the most popular blogs, see The Truth Laid Bear's Blogosphere Ecosystem, at http://www.truthlaidbear.com/ecosystem.php (last visited Nov. 17, 2003).
    • The Truth Laid Bear's Blogosphere Ecosystem
  • 23
    • 84862356929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • last visited Oct. 27, 2003
    • See http://www.televisionwithoutpity.com (last visited Oct. 27, 2003).
  • 24
    • 35248849296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The remote controllers
    • Oct. 20, (Magazine)
    • Marshall Sella, The Remote Controllers, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 20, 2002, (Magazine), at 70 (noting that "[i]t is now standard Hollywood practice for executive producers ... to scurry into Web groups moments after an episode is shown on the East Coast," hoping to discover what core viewers like and dislike).
    • (2002) N.Y. Times , pp. 70
    • Sella, M.1
  • 25
    • 84862359939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • last visited July 10, 2003
    • For examples of fan fiction, see generally http://www.fanfiction.net (last visited July 10, 2003). On the clash between fan fiction and copyright law, see Rebecca Tushnet, Legal Fictions: Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law, 17 LOY. L.A. ENT. L.J. 651 (1997); Ariana Eunjung Cha, Harry Potter and the Copyright Lawyer, WASH. POST, June 18, 2003, at A1; Tracy Mayor, Taking Liberties with Harry Potter, BOSTON GLOBE, June 29, 2003, (Magazine), at 14. The practice predates the Internet, see HENRY JENKINS, TEXTUAL POACHERS: TELEVISION FANS & PARTICIPATORY CULTURE 152-62 (1992), but the Internet has helped spur the formation of new communities of fan fiction writers, whose collective efforts have drawn the attention (and occasionally the ire) of television producers.
  • 26
    • 2442452346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal fictions: Copyright, fan fiction, and a new common law
    • For examples of fan fiction, see generally http://www.fanfiction.net (last visited July 10, 2003). On the clash between fan fiction and copyright law, see Rebecca Tushnet, Legal Fictions: Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law, 17 LOY. L.A. ENT. L.J. 651 (1997); Ariana Eunjung Cha, Harry Potter and the Copyright Lawyer, WASH. POST, June 18, 2003, at A1; Tracy Mayor, Taking Liberties with Harry Potter, BOSTON GLOBE, June 29, 2003, (Magazine), at 14. The practice predates the Internet, see HENRY JENKINS, TEXTUAL POACHERS: TELEVISION FANS & PARTICIPATORY CULTURE 152-62 (1992), but the Internet has helped spur the formation of new communities of fan fiction writers, whose collective efforts have drawn the attention (and occasionally the ire) of television producers.
    • (1997) Loy. L.A. Ent. L.J. , vol.17 , pp. 651
    • Tushnet, R.1
  • 27
    • 2442624325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harry Potter and the copyright lawyer
    • June 18
    • For examples of fan fiction, see generally http://www.fanfiction.net (last visited July 10, 2003). On the clash between fan fiction and copyright law, see Rebecca Tushnet, Legal Fictions: Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law, 17 LOY. L.A. ENT. L.J. 651 (1997); Ariana Eunjung Cha, Harry Potter and the Copyright Lawyer, WASH. POST, June 18, 2003, at A1; Tracy Mayor, Taking Liberties with Harry Potter, BOSTON GLOBE, June 29, 2003, (Magazine), at 14. The practice predates the Internet, see HENRY JENKINS, TEXTUAL POACHERS: TELEVISION FANS & PARTICIPATORY CULTURE 152-62 (1992), but the Internet has helped spur the formation of new communities of fan fiction writers, whose collective efforts have drawn the attention (and occasionally the ire) of television producers.
    • (2003) Wash. Post
    • Cha, A.E.1
  • 28
    • 2442431287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking liberties with Harry Potter
    • June 29, (Magazine)
    • For examples of fan fiction, see generally http://www.fanfiction.net (last visited July 10, 2003). On the clash between fan fiction and copyright law, see Rebecca Tushnet, Legal Fictions: Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law, 17 LOY. L.A. ENT. L.J. 651 (1997); Ariana Eunjung Cha, Harry Potter and the Copyright Lawyer, WASH. POST, June 18, 2003, at A1; Tracy Mayor, Taking Liberties with Harry Potter, BOSTON GLOBE, June 29, 2003, (Magazine), at 14. The practice predates the Internet, see HENRY JENKINS, TEXTUAL POACHERS: TELEVISION FANS & PARTICIPATORY CULTURE 152-62 (1992), but the Internet has helped spur the formation of new communities of fan fiction writers, whose collective efforts have drawn the attention (and occasionally the ire) of television producers.
    • (2003) Boston Globe , pp. 14
    • Mayor, T.1
  • 29
    • 0003850663 scopus 로고
    • For examples of fan fiction, see generally http://www.fanfiction.net (last visited July 10, 2003). On the clash between fan fiction and copyright law, see Rebecca Tushnet, Legal Fictions: Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law, 17 LOY. L.A. ENT. L.J. 651 (1997); Ariana Eunjung Cha, Harry Potter and the Copyright Lawyer, WASH. POST, June 18, 2003, at A1; Tracy Mayor, Taking Liberties with Harry Potter, BOSTON GLOBE, June 29, 2003, (Magazine), at 14. The practice predates the Internet, see HENRY JENKINS, TEXTUAL POACHERS: TELEVISION FANS & PARTICIPATORY CULTURE 152-62 (1992), but the Internet has helped spur the formation of new communities of fan fiction writers, whose collective efforts have drawn the attention (and occasionally the ire) of television producers.
    • (1992) Textual Poachers: Television Fans & Participatory Culture , pp. 152-62
    • Jenkins, H.1
  • 30
    • 0003725885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the major concern of LAWRENCE LESSIG, CODE AND OTHER LAWS OF CYBERSPACE (1999) [hereinafter LESSIG, CODE AND OTHER LAWS OF CYBERSPACE], and LAWRENCE LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS: THE FATE OF THE COMMONS IN A CONNECTED WORLD (2001) [hereinafter LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS].
    • (1999) Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 31
    • 0003725885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • hereinafter
    • This is the major concern of LAWRENCE LESSIG, CODE AND OTHER LAWS OF CYBERSPACE (1999) [hereinafter LESSIG, CODE AND OTHER LAWS OF CYBERSPACE], and LAWRENCE LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS: THE FATE OF THE COMMONS IN A CONNECTED WORLD (2001) [hereinafter LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS].
    • Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace
    • Lessig1
  • 32
  • 33
    • 0003981873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • hereinafter
    • This is the major concern of LAWRENCE LESSIG, CODE AND OTHER LAWS OF CYBERSPACE (1999) [hereinafter LESSIG, CODE AND OTHER LAWS OF CYBERSPACE], and LAWRENCE LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS: THE FATE OF THE COMMONS IN A CONNECTED WORLD (2001) [hereinafter LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS].
    • The Future of Ideas
    • Lessig1
  • 34
    • 17144416354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Through the looking glass: Alice and the constitutional foundations of the public domain
    • The basic conflict between centralized control of information production and distribution and routing around and glomming on that I have identified here has many different aspects. Yochai Benkler views the conflict in terms of contrasting methods of information production-a conflict between, on the one hand, an industrial model of protection that produces mass culture prepackaged for consumption, and, on the other, various models of nonproprietary and peer production. Yochai Benkler, Through the Looking Glass: Alice and the Constitutional Foundations of the Public Domain, 66 LAW AND CONTEMP. PROBS. 173, 181 (2003) [hereinafter Benkler, The Public Domain]; see also Yochai Benkler, From Consumers to Users: Shifting the Deeper Structures of Regulation Toward Sustainable Commons and User Access, 52 FED. COMM. L.J. 561, 562 (2000). The same technologies that allow the industrialization of the goods of the mind also make possible new forms of peer production and collaboration. See J.M. Balkin, What Is a Postmodern Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 1966, 1974, 1983 (1992) (defining postmodern era as era of industrialization of products of mind); see also Yochai Benkler, Coase's Penguin, or, Linux and The Nature of the Firm, 112 YALE L.J. 369, 375-90 (2002) (describing rise of collaborative methods for commons-based peer production). The struggle between these models of production, which is waged both in politics and in law, will determine the "institutional ecology" of information production in the next century. Benkler, The Public Domain, supra, at 181.
    • (2003) Law and Contemp. Probs. , vol.66 , pp. 173
    • Benkler, Y.1
  • 35
    • 2442631222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • hereinafter
    • The basic conflict between centralized control of information production and distribution and routing around and glomming on that I have identified here has many different aspects. Yochai Benkler views the conflict in terms of contrasting methods of information production-a conflict between, on the one hand, an industrial model of protection that produces mass culture prepackaged for consumption, and, on the other, various models of nonproprietary and peer production. Yochai Benkler, Through the Looking Glass: Alice and the Constitutional Foundations of the Public Domain, 66 LAW AND CONTEMP. PROBS. 173, 181 (2003) [hereinafter Benkler, The Public Domain]; see also Yochai Benkler, From Consumers to Users: Shifting the Deeper Structures of Regulation Toward Sustainable Commons and User Access, 52 FED. COMM. L.J. 561, 562 (2000). The same technologies that allow the industrialization of the goods of the mind also make possible new forms of peer production and collaboration. See J.M. Balkin, What Is a Postmodern Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 1966, 1974, 1983 (1992) (defining postmodern era as era of industrialization of products of mind); see also Yochai Benkler, Coase's Penguin, or, Linux and The Nature of the Firm, 112 YALE L.J. 369, 375-90 (2002) (describing rise of collaborative methods for commons-based peer production). The struggle between these models of production, which is waged both in politics and in law, will determine the "institutional ecology" of information production in the next century. Benkler, The Public Domain, supra, at 181.
    • The Public Domain
    • Benkler1
  • 36
    • 0037922883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From consumers to users: Shifting the deeper structures of regulation toward sustainable commons and user access
    • The basic conflict between centralized control of information production and distribution and routing around and glomming on that I have identified here has many different aspects. Yochai Benkler views the conflict in terms of contrasting methods of information production-a conflict between, on the one hand, an industrial model of protection that produces mass culture prepackaged for consumption, and, on the other, various models of nonproprietary and peer production. Yochai Benkler, Through the Looking Glass: Alice and the Constitutional Foundations of the Public Domain, 66 LAW AND CONTEMP. PROBS. 173, 181 (2003) [hereinafter Benkler, The Public Domain]; see also Yochai Benkler, From Consumers to Users: Shifting the Deeper Structures of Regulation Toward Sustainable Commons and User Access, 52 FED. COMM. L.J. 561, 562 (2000). The same technologies that allow the industrialization of the goods of the mind also make possible new forms of peer production and collaboration. See J.M. Balkin, What Is a Postmodern Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 1966, 1974, 1983 (1992) (defining postmodern era as era of industrialization of products of mind); see also Yochai Benkler, Coase's Penguin, or, Linux and The Nature of the Firm, 112 YALE L.J. 369, 375-90 (2002) (describing rise of collaborative methods for commons-based peer production). The struggle between these models of production, which is waged both in politics and in law, will determine the "institutional ecology" of information production in the next century. Benkler, The Public Domain, supra, at 181.
    • (2000) Fed. Comm. L.J. , vol.52 , pp. 561
    • Benkler, Y.1
  • 37
    • 0011257932 scopus 로고
    • What is a postmodern constitutionalism
    • The basic conflict between centralized control of information production and distribution and routing around and glomming on that I have identified here has many different aspects. Yochai Benkler views the conflict in terms of contrasting methods of information production-a conflict between, on the one hand, an industrial model of protection that produces mass culture prepackaged for consumption, and, on the other, various models of nonproprietary and peer production. Yochai Benkler, Through the Looking Glass: Alice and the Constitutional Foundations of the Public Domain, 66 LAW AND CONTEMP. PROBS. 173, 181 (2003) [hereinafter Benkler, The Public Domain]; see also Yochai Benkler, From Consumers to Users: Shifting the Deeper Structures of Regulation Toward Sustainable Commons and User Access, 52 FED. COMM. L.J. 561, 562 (2000). The same technologies that allow the industrialization of the goods of the mind also make possible new forms of peer production and collaboration. See J.M. Balkin, What Is a Postmodern Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 1966, 1974, 1983 (1992) (defining postmodern era as era of industrialization of products of mind); see also Yochai Benkler, Coase's Penguin, or, Linux and The Nature of the Firm, 112 YALE L.J. 369, 375-90 (2002) (describing rise of collaborative methods for commons-based peer production). The struggle between these models of production, which is waged both in politics and in law, will determine the "institutional ecology" of information production in the next century. Benkler, The Public Domain, supra, at 181.
    • (1992) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 1966
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 38
    • 0242685828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coase's penguin, or, linux and the nature of the firm
    • The basic conflict between centralized control of information production and distribution and routing around and glomming on that I have identified here has many different aspects. Yochai Benkler views the conflict in terms of contrasting methods of information production-a conflict between, on the one hand, an industrial model of protection that produces mass culture prepackaged for consumption, and, on the other, various models of nonproprietary and peer production. Yochai Benkler, Through the Looking Glass: Alice and the Constitutional Foundations of the Public Domain, 66 LAW AND CONTEMP. PROBS. 173, 181 (2003) [hereinafter Benkler, The Public Domain]; see also Yochai Benkler, From Consumers to Users: Shifting the Deeper Structures of Regulation Toward Sustainable Commons and User Access, 52 FED. COMM. L.J. 561, 562 (2000). The same technologies that allow the industrialization of the goods of the mind also make possible new forms of peer production and collaboration. See J.M. Balkin, What Is a Postmodern Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 1966, 1974, 1983 (1992) (defining postmodern era as era of industrialization of products of mind); see also Yochai Benkler, Coase's Penguin, or, Linux and The Nature of the Firm, 112 YALE L.J. 369, 375-90 (2002) (describing rise of collaborative methods for commons-based peer production). The struggle between these models of production, which is waged both in politics and in law, will determine the "institutional ecology" of information production in the next century. Benkler, The Public Domain, supra, at 181.
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , pp. 369
    • Benkler, Y.1
  • 39
    • 2442631222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • The basic conflict between centralized control of information production and distribution and routing around and glomming on that I have identified here has many different aspects. Yochai Benkler views the conflict in terms of contrasting methods of information production-a conflict between, on the one hand, an industrial model of protection that produces mass culture prepackaged for consumption, and, on the other, various models of nonproprietary and peer production. Yochai Benkler, Through the Looking Glass: Alice and the Constitutional Foundations of the Public Domain, 66 LAW AND CONTEMP. PROBS. 173, 181 (2003) [hereinafter Benkler, The Public Domain]; see also Yochai Benkler, From Consumers to Users: Shifting the Deeper Structures of Regulation Toward Sustainable Commons and User Access, 52 FED. COMM. L.J. 561, 562 (2000). The same technologies that allow the industrialization of the goods of the mind also make possible new forms of peer production and collaboration. See J.M. Balkin, What Is a Postmodern Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 1966, 1974, 1983 (1992) (defining postmodern era as era of industrialization of products of mind); see also Yochai Benkler, Coase's Penguin, or, Linux and The Nature of the Firm, 112 YALE L.J. 369, 375-90 (2002) (describing rise of collaborative methods for commons-based peer production). The struggle between these models of production, which is waged both in politics and in law, will determine the "institutional ecology" of information production in the next century. Benkler, The Public Domain, supra, at 181.
    • The Public Domain , pp. 181
    • Benkler1
  • 40
    • 0002141111 scopus 로고
    • A contribution to the critique of political economy
    • Robert C. Tucker ed.
    • Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, in THE MARX-ENGELS READER 4, 4-5 (Robert C. Tucker ed., 1978).
    • (1978) The Marx-Engels Reader , pp. 4
    • Marx, K.1
  • 41
    • 0038359079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional bounds of database protection: The role of judicial review in the creation and definition of private rights in information
    • On the emerging conflict between freedom of speech and intellectual property, see Yochai Benkler, Constitutional Bounds of Database Protection: The Role of Judicial Review in the Creation and Definition of Private Rights in Information, 15 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 535, 587-600 (2000) (suggesting conflict between free speech rights and database protection); Yochai Benkler, Free as the Air to Common Use: First Amendment Constraints on Enclosure of the Public Domain, 74 N.Y.U. L. REV. 354, 393-401, 412-14 (1999) (arguing that given emerging methods of production of digital information, copyright promotes neither diversity of information nor free expression).
    • (2000) Berkeley Tech. L.J. , vol.15 , pp. 535
    • Benkler, Y.1
  • 42
    • 17144378788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Free as the air to common use: First amendment constraints on enclosure of the public domain
    • On the emerging conflict between freedom of speech and intellectual property, see Yochai Benkler, Constitutional Bounds of Database Protection: The Role of Judicial Review in the Creation and Definition of Private Rights in Information, 15 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 535, 587-600 (2000) (suggesting conflict between free speech rights and database protection); Yochai Benkler, Free as the Air to Common Use: First Amendment Constraints on Enclosure of the Public Domain, 74 N.Y.U. L. REV. 354, 393-401, 412-14 (1999) (arguing that given emerging methods of production of digital information, copyright promotes neither diversity of information nor free expression).
    • (1999) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.74 , pp. 354
    • Benkler, Y.1
  • 43
    • 0003939864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom of speech and injunctions in intellectual property cases
    • See generally Mark Lemley & Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and Injunctions in Intellectual Property Cases, 48 DUKE L.J. 147 (1998).
    • (1998) Duke L.J. , vol.48 , pp. 147
    • Lemley, M.1    Volokh, E.2
  • 44
    • 0035539406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locating copyright in the first amendment skein
    • For a summary of the expansion in copyright law, particularly since 1970, see Neil Netanel, Locating Copyright in the First Amendment Skein, 54 STAN. L. REV. 1, 18-26 (2001).
    • (2001) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.54 , pp. 1
    • Netanel, N.1
  • 45
    • 84862356493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pub. L. No. 105-298, 112 Stat. 2827 (1998) (codified at 17 U.S.C. § 302 (2000))
    • Pub. L. No. 105-298, 112 Stat. 2827 (1998) (codified at 17 U.S.C. § 302 (2000)).
  • 46
    • 84862356494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pub. L. No. 105-304, 112 Stat. 2860 (1998) (codified at 17 U.S.C. §1201 (2000))
    • Pub. L. No. 105-304, 112 Stat. 2860 (1998) (codified at 17 U.S.C. §1201 (2000)).
  • 47
    • 0003981873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17
    • See generally LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 180-217; Niva Elkin-Koren, It's All About Control: Rethinking Copyright in the New Information Landscape, in THE COMMODIFICATION OF INFORMATION 79 (Niva Elkin-Koren & Neil W. Netanel eds., 2002).
    • The Future of Ideas , pp. 180-217
    • Lessig1
  • 48
    • 2442441766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It's all about control: Rethinking copyright in the new information landscape
    • Niva Elkin-Koren & Neil W. Netanel eds.
    • See generally LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 180-217; Niva Elkin-Koren, It's All About Control: Rethinking Copyright in the New Information Landscape, in THE COMMODIFICATION OF INFORMATION 79 (Niva Elkin-Koren & Neil W. Netanel eds., 2002).
    • (2002) The Commodification of Information , pp. 79
    • Elkin-Koren, N.1
  • 49
    • 2442512976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turner Broad. v. FCC (Turner I), 512 U.S. 622, 656 (1994)
    • Cf. Turner Broad. v. FCC (Turner I), 512 U.S. 622, 656 (1994) (arguing that monopoly power and cable architecture create bottlenecks and exclude others from speaking); Red Lion Broad. Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367, 388-392, 392 (1969) ("There is no sanctuary in the First Amendment for unlimited private censorship operating in a medium not open to all.").
  • 50
    • 2442603215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Red Lion Broad. Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367, 388-392, 392 (1969)
    • Cf. Turner Broad. v. FCC (Turner I), 512 U.S. 622, 656 (1994) (arguing that monopoly power and cable architecture create bottlenecks and exclude others from speaking); Red Lion Broad. Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367, 388-392, 392 (1969) ("There is no sanctuary in the First Amendment for unlimited private censorship operating in a medium not open to all.").
  • 51
    • 84862360935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 52
    • 84862356491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 53
    • 84862356492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 54
    • 84862356925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 55
    • 84862356489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 56
    • 84862356926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 57
    • 84862359937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000)
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
  • 58
    • 2442626391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S.
    • See 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(7) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to "allow reasonable access to or ... permit purchase of reasonable amounts of time" to "legally qualified candidate[s] for Federal elective office"); 47 U.S.C. § 315(a) (2000) (establishing "equal opportunities" rule requiring broadcasters who permit one candidate to "use" station to permit candidate's opponents to "use" station as well); 47 U.S.C. § 315(b) (2000) (requiring broadcasters to sell time at lowest unit charge to political candidates); 47 U.S.C. § 531(b) (2000) (authorizing franchise authorities to require cable companies to set aside space for public access, educational and government channels); 47 U.S.C. § 532(b)(1) (2000) (establishing "leased access" provisions which require cable operators to set aside channel capacity for use by commercial programmers unaffiliated with cable franchise operator); 47 U.S.C. § 541(a)(3) (2000) (requiring assurances in awarding cable franchises that cable access "is not denied to any group of potential residential cable subscribers because of the income of the residents of the local area in which such group resides"); 47 U.S.C. § 335(b)(1) (2000) (requiring direct broadcast satellite operators to set aside portion of "channel capacity, equal to not less than 4 percent nor more than 7 percent, exclusively for noncommercial programming of an educational or informational nature"); Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 373-75 (describing fairness doctrine).
    • Red Lion , vol.395 , pp. 373-375
  • 59
    • 2442626361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001)
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
  • 60
    • 2442437566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000)
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
  • 61
    • 2442544201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994)
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
  • 62
    • 2442617943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S.
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
    • (1996) Vacated as Moot , vol.516 , pp. 1155
  • 63
    • 2442574634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994)
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
  • 64
    • 2442609471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S.
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
    • (1996) Vacated as Moot , vol.516 , pp. 415
  • 65
    • 2442489677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56
    • See, e.g., Time Warner Entm't Co. v. FCC, 240 F.3d 1126, 1136, 1139 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (invalidating FCC's limits on vertical and horizontal integration of cable carriers); Comcast Cablevision, Inc. v. Broward County, 124 F. Supp. 2d 685, 694 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (holding that open access requirements for broadband cable violate First Amendment rights of cable system owners); see also U.S. West, Inc. v. United States, 48 F.3d 1092, 1095 (9th Cir. 1994) (striking down ban on telephone companies also selling video content to the public), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 1155 (1996); Chesapeake & Potomac Tel. Co. v. United States, 42 F.3d 181, 202 (4th Cir. 1994) (same), vacated as moot, 516 U.S. 415 (1996). The last two cases were held moot by the Supreme Court in light of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-104, 110 Stat. 56 (codified in scattered sections of 42 U.S.C. (2000)), which repealed the statutory ban on cross-ownership.
  • 66
    • 0003981873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17
    • See LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 156-58 (quoting Jerome Saltzer, "Open Access" is Just the Tip of the Iceberg (Oct. 22, 1999), at http://web.mit.edu/Saltzer/www/publications/openaccess.html (last visited Oct. 20, 2003) (offering examples of gatekeeping by cable networks)).
    • The Future of Ideas , pp. 156-58
    • Lessig1
  • 67
    • 8844267239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oct. 22 (last visited Oct. 20, 2003)
    • See LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 156-58 (quoting Jerome Saltzer, "Open Access" is Just the Tip of the Iceberg (Oct. 22, 1999), at http://web.mit.edu/Saltzer/www/publications/openaccess.html (last visited Oct. 20, 2003) (offering examples of gatekeeping by cable networks)).
    • (1999) "Open Access" is Just the Tip of the Iceberg
    • Saltzer, J.1
  • 68
    • 2442544200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The regulation of interactive television in the United States and the European Union
    • See Hernan Galperin & Francois Bar, The Regulation of Interactive Television in the United States and the European Union, 55 FED. COMM. L.J. 61, 62-64, 69-72 (2002) (discussing strategy of walled gardens in interactive television services); Daniel L. Rubinfeld & Hal J. Singer, Open Access to Broadband Networks: A Case Study of the AOL/Time Warner Merger, 16 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 631, 656 (2001) (noting dangers of conduit discrimination as well as content discrimination).
    • (2002) Fed. Comm. L.J. , vol.55 , pp. 61
    • Galperin, H.1    Bar, F.2
  • 69
    • 0039337765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Open access to broadband networks: A case study of the AOL/Time Warner Merger
    • See Hernan Galperin & Francois Bar, The Regulation of Interactive Television in the United States and the European Union, 55 FED. COMM. L.J. 61, 62-64, 69-72 (2002) (discussing strategy of walled gardens in interactive television services); Daniel L. Rubinfeld & Hal J. Singer, Open Access to Broadband Networks: A Case Study of the AOL/Time Warner Merger, 16 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 631, 656 (2001) (noting dangers of conduit discrimination as well as content discrimination).
    • (2001) Berkeley Tech. L.J. , vol.16 , pp. 631
    • Rubinfeld, D.L.1    Singer, H.J.2
  • 70
    • 84862360934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Data Sheet (last visited Oct. 20, 2003)
    • Data Sheet, Cisco 6400 Service Selection Gateway, at http://www.cisco.com/warp/public/cc/pd/as/6400/prodlit/c6510_ds.htm (last visited Oct. 20, 2003); see also Jeffrey A. Chester, Web Behind Walls, TECH. REV., June 2001, at 94, 94, available at http://www.democraticmedia.org/resources/articles/webbehindwalls.html (last visited Oct. 20, 2003).
  • 71
    • 84862360322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Web behind walls
    • June (last visited Oct. 20, 2003)
    • Data Sheet, Cisco 6400 Service Selection Gateway, at http://www.cisco.com/warp/public/cc/pd/as/6400/prodlit/c6510_ds.htm (last visited Oct. 20, 2003); see also Jeffrey A. Chester, Web Behind Walls, TECH. REV., June 2001, at 94, 94, available at http://www.democraticmedia.org/resources/articles/webbehindwalls.html (last visited Oct. 20, 2003).
    • (2001) Tech. Rev. , pp. 94
    • Chester, J.A.1
  • 72
    • 2442554765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eldred v. Reno, 239 F.3d 372, 380 (D.C. Cir. 2000)
    • See Eldred v. Reno, 239 F.3d 372, 380 (D.C. Cir. 2000), aff'd sub nom. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 222 (2003) (holding that First Amendment poses no obstacle to Congressional extension of copyright terms that shrink scope of public domain, even when extension is retroactive); Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Reimerdes, 111 F. Supp. 2d 294 (S.D.N.Y. 2000) (upholding constitutionality of application of Digital Millenium Copyright Act to DeCSS and enjoining linking to websites from which DeCSS might be obtained), aff'd sub nom. Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429 (2001); supra note 26 (citing additional cases).
  • 73
    • 2442443870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • aff'd sub nom. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 222 (2003)
    • See Eldred v. Reno, 239 F.3d 372, 380 (D.C. Cir. 2000), aff'd sub nom. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 222 (2003) (holding that First Amendment poses no obstacle to Congressional extension of copyright terms that shrink scope of public domain, even when extension is retroactive); Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Reimerdes, 111 F. Supp. 2d 294 (S.D.N.Y. 2000) (upholding constitutionality of application of Digital Millenium Copyright Act to DeCSS and enjoining linking to websites from which DeCSS might be obtained), aff'd sub nom. Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429 (2001); supra note 26 (citing additional cases).
  • 74
    • 2442539991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Reimerdes, 111 F. Supp. 2d 294 (S.D.N.Y. 2000)
    • See Eldred v. Reno, 239 F.3d 372, 380 (D.C. Cir. 2000), aff'd sub nom. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 222 (2003) (holding that First Amendment poses no obstacle to Congressional extension of copyright terms that shrink scope of public domain, even when extension is retroactive); Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Reimerdes, 111 F. Supp. 2d 294 (S.D.N.Y. 2000) (upholding constitutionality of application of Digital Millenium Copyright Act to DeCSS and enjoining linking to websites from which DeCSS might be obtained), aff'd sub nom. Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429 (2001); supra note 26 (citing additional cases).
  • 75
    • 2442493845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • aff'd sub nom. Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429 (2001); supra note 26
    • See Eldred v. Reno, 239 F.3d 372, 380 (D.C. Cir. 2000), aff'd sub nom. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 222 (2003) (holding that First Amendment poses no obstacle to Congressional extension of copyright terms that shrink scope of public domain, even when extension is retroactive); Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Reimerdes, 111 F. Supp. 2d 294 (S.D.N.Y. 2000) (upholding constitutionality of application of Digital Millenium Copyright Act to DeCSS and enjoining linking to websites from which DeCSS might be obtained), aff'd sub nom. Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Corley, 273 F.3d 429 (2001); supra note 26 (citing additional cases).
  • 76
    • 0346680888 scopus 로고
    • Some realism about pluralism: Legal realist approaches to the first amendment
    • See J.M. Balkin, Some Realism About Pluralism: Legal Realist Approaches to the First Amendment, 1990 DUKE L.J. 375, 375-87 (noting "ideological drift" of free speech principle to protect propertied and corporate interests).
    • (1990) Duke L.J. , pp. 375
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 77
    • 2442558917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. West, Inc. v. FCC, 182 F.3d 1224, 1235, 1239 (10th Cir. 1999)
    • See, e.g., U.S. West, Inc. v. FCC, 182 F.3d 1224, 1235, 1239 (10th Cir. 1999) (invalidating, on First Amendment grounds, FCC regulations protecting privacy and sale of telephone customers' personal information). On some of the problems faced in squaring consumer privacy with a libertarian conception of freedom of speech, see Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and Information Privacy: The Troubling Implications of a Right to Stop People from Speaking About You,
  • 78
    • 0347315060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom of speech and information privacy: The troubling implications of a right to stop people from speaking about you
    • See, e.g., U.S. West, Inc. v. FCC, 182 F.3d 1224, 1235, 1239 (10th Cir. 1999) (invalidating, on First Amendment grounds, FCC regulations protecting privacy and sale of telephone customers' personal information). On some of the problems faced in squaring consumer privacy with a libertarian conception of freedom of speech, see Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and Information Privacy: The Troubling Implications of a Right to Stop People from Speaking About You, 52 STAN. L. REV. 1049 (2000).
    • (2000) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.52 , pp. 1049
    • Volokh, E.1
  • 79
    • 2442537886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 33, at 384
    • Balkin, supra note 33, at 384; Mark Tushnet, Corporations and Free Speech, in THE POLITICS OF LAW: A PROGRESSIVE CRITIQUE 253 (David Kairys ed., 1982); Mark Tushnet, An Essay on Rights, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1363, 1386-92 (1984).
  • 80
    • 1542558158 scopus 로고
    • Corporations and free speech
    • David Kairys ed.
    • Balkin, supra note 33, at 384; Mark Tushnet, Corporations and Free Speech, in THE POLITICS OF LAW: A PROGRESSIVE CRITIQUE 253 (David Kairys ed., 1982); Mark Tushnet, An Essay on Rights, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1363, 1386-92 (1984).
    • (1982) The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique , pp. 253
    • Tushnet, M.1
  • 81
    • 34447536569 scopus 로고
    • An essay on rights
    • Balkin, supra note 33, at 384; Mark Tushnet, Corporations and Free Speech, in THE POLITICS OF LAW: A PROGRESSIVE CRITIQUE 253 (David Kairys ed., 1982); Mark Tushnet, An Essay on Rights, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1363, 1386-92 (1984).
    • (1984) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 1363
    • Tushnet, M.1
  • 82
    • 0003981873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17
    • LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 196-202; Elkin-Koren, supra note 25, at 84-85, 88-98.
    • The Future of Ideas , pp. 196-202
    • Lessig1
  • 83
    • 2442431288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elkin-Koren, supra note 25, at 84-85, 88-98
    • LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 196-202; Elkin-Koren, supra note 25, at 84-85, 88-98.
  • 84
    • 2442617944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U.S. 312, 328 (1921)
    • Cf. Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U.S. 312, 328 (1921) (holding that attempt to ban labor injunctions violated property rights of business owner).
  • 85
    • 0011531909 scopus 로고
    • Laissez-Faire and liberty: A re-evaluation of the meaning and origins of laissez-faire constitutionalism
    • A substantial literature has developed explaining how Gilded Age ideas of freedom of contract were created out of Jacksonian and free labor ideals. See, e.g., Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LAW & HIST. REV. 293 (1985); William E. Forbath, The Ambiguities of Free Labor: Labor and the Law in the Gilded Age, 1985 WIS. L. REV. 767, 798-99 (1985); Charles W. McCurdy, The Roots of "Liberty of Contract" Reconsidered: Major Premises in the Law of Employment, 1867-1937, 1984 YEARBOOK OF THE SUPREME COURT HISTORICAL SOCIETY 20. Revisions of this view have suggested that other influences were also at work, see Stephen A. Siegel, The Revision Thickens, 20 LAW & HIST. REV. 631 (2002), but have not undermined the basic point that corporate interests made ample use of these rhetorical resources.
    • (1985) Law & Hist. Rev. , vol.3 , pp. 293
    • Les Benedict, M.1
  • 86
    • 84878374419 scopus 로고
    • The ambiguities of free labor: Labor and the law in the gilded age
    • A substantial literature has developed explaining how Gilded Age ideas of freedom of contract were created out of Jacksonian and free labor ideals. See, e.g., Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LAW & HIST. REV. 293 (1985); William E. Forbath, The Ambiguities of Free Labor: Labor and the Law in the Gilded Age, 1985 WIS. L. REV. 767, 798-99 (1985); Charles W. McCurdy, The Roots of "Liberty of Contract" Reconsidered: Major Premises in the Law of Employment, 1867-1937, 1984 YEARBOOK OF THE SUPREME COURT HISTORICAL SOCIETY 20. Revisions of this view have suggested that other influences were also at work, see Stephen A. Siegel, The Revision Thickens, 20 LAW & HIST. REV. 631 (2002), but have not undermined the basic point that corporate interests made ample use of these rhetorical resources.
    • (1985) Wis. L. Rev. , vol.1985 , pp. 767
    • Forbath, W.E.1
  • 87
    • 0040911658 scopus 로고
    • The roots of "liberty of contract" reconsidered: Major premises in the law of employment, 1867-1984
    • A substantial literature has developed explaining how Gilded Age ideas of freedom of contract were created out of Jacksonian and free labor ideals. See, e.g., Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LAW & HIST. REV. 293 (1985); William E. Forbath, The Ambiguities of Free Labor: Labor and the Law in the Gilded Age, 1985 WIS. L. REV. 767, 798-99 (1985); Charles W. McCurdy, The Roots of "Liberty of Contract" Reconsidered: Major Premises in the Law of Employment, 1867-1937, 1984 YEARBOOK OF THE SUPREME COURT HISTORICAL SOCIETY 20. Revisions of this view have suggested that other influences were also at work, see Stephen A. Siegel, The Revision Thickens, 20 LAW & HIST. REV. 631 (2002), but have not undermined the basic point that corporate interests made ample use of these rhetorical resources.
    • (1937) Yearbook of the Supreme Court Historical Society , pp. 20
    • McCurdy, C.W.1
  • 88
    • 2442506513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The revision thickens
    • A substantial literature has developed explaining how Gilded Age ideas of freedom of contract were created out of Jacksonian and free labor ideals. See, e.g., Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LAW & HIST. REV. 293 (1985); William E. Forbath, The Ambiguities of Free Labor: Labor and the Law in the Gilded Age, 1985 WIS. L. REV. 767, 798-99 (1985); Charles W. McCurdy, The Roots of "Liberty of Contract" Reconsidered: Major Premises in the Law of Employment, 1867-1937, 1984 YEARBOOK OF THE SUPREME COURT HISTORICAL SOCIETY 20. Revisions of this view have suggested that other influences were also at work, see Stephen A. Siegel, The Revision Thickens, 20 LAW & HIST. REV. 631 (2002), but have not undermined the basic point that corporate interests made ample use of these rhetorical resources.
    • (2002) Law & Hist. Rev. , vol.20 , pp. 631
    • Siegel, S.A.1
  • 90
    • 2442565398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 128-62
    • Id. at 128-62; see Balkin, supra note 33, at 383-87.
  • 91
    • 2442620084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 33, at 383-387
    • Id. at 128-62; see Balkin, supra note 33, at 383-87.
  • 94
    • 2442489647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 33, at 375-87
    • The comparison between the ideological drift of the principles of freedom of contract and freedom of speech is explored in Balkin, supra note 33, at 375-87, and J.M. Balkin, Ideological Drift and the Struggle over Meaning, 25 CONN. L. REV. 869 (1993).
  • 95
    • 0347053139 scopus 로고
    • Ideological drift and the struggle over meaning
    • The comparison between the ideological drift of the principles of freedom of contract and freedom of speech is explored in Balkin, supra note 33, at 375-87, and J.M. Balkin, Ideological Drift and the Struggle over Meaning, 25 CONN. L. REV. 869 (1993).
    • (1993) Conn. L. Rev. , vol.25 , pp. 869
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 96
    • 2442425020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Council Directive 96/9, 1996 O.J. (L 77/20)
    • Council Directive 96/9, 1996 O.J. (L 77/20) (providing for legal protection of databases which, "by reason of the selection or arrangements of their contents, constitute[] the author's own intellectual creation").
  • 97
    • 0346239096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The database debate: In support of an inequitable solution
    • For a discussion of recent attempts, see Dov S. Greenbaum, The Database Debate: In Support of an Inequitable Solution, 13 ALB. L.J. Sci. & TECH. 431, 468-78 (2003).
    • (2003) Alb. L.J. Sci. & Tech. , vol.13 , pp. 431
    • Greenbaum, D.S.1
  • 98
    • 0037412582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Edison to the broadcast flag: Mechanisms of consent and refusal and the propertization of copyright
    • Cf. Randal C. Picker, From Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of Copyright, 70 U. CHI. L. REV. 281, 293-96 (2003) (noting that digital rights management permits perfection of continuing control over use of intellectual property in digital content even after media product has been purchased).
    • (2003) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.70 , pp. 281
    • Picker, R.C.1
  • 99
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cyberspace: The new economic orthodoxy of "Rights Management"
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
    • (1998) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 462
    • Cohen, J.1    Lochner2
  • 100
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905)
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 101
    • 2442584281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eldred and Lochner: Copyright term extension and intellectual property as constitutional property
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
    • (2003) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , pp. 2331
    • Schwartz, P.M.1    Treanor, W.M.2
  • 102
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
    • Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition , pp. 15-21
  • 103
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003)
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 104
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-222
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 105
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919)
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 106
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919)
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 107
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925)
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 108
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 109
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938)
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 110
    • 0039274116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407
    • Or, in Julie Cohen's memorable phrase, we are entering the era of "Lochner in Cyberspace." Julie Cohen, Lochner in Cyberspace: The New Economic Orthodoxy of "Rights Management," 97 MICH. L. REV. 462 (1998). Paul Schwartz and William Treanor argue, by contrast, that calls for constitutional limitations on the expansion of intellectual property are the best analogy to the laissezfaire constitutional conservatism of the Gilded Age; they compare arguments for constitutional protection of the public domain to Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). Paul M. Schwartz & William Michael Treanor, Eldred and Lochner: Copyright Term Extension and Intellectual Property as Constitutional Property, 112 YALE L.J. 2331, 2334-35, 2394-95, 2411 (2003). They fail to consider the social and economic context in which the debate over laissez-faire conservatism occurred. In effect, Schwartz and Treanor argue that small-scale artists, software programmers, Internet end users, and consumers who seek a robust public domain are the functional equivalent of the Robber Barons and concentrated economic interests of the Gilded Age, while today's media corporations like Microsoft, Disney and Viacom are the functional equivalent of immigrant laborers in sweatshops at the turn of the century. Because they focus exclusively on arguments about the scope of the Copyright Clause, and pay no attention to telecommunications law, Schwartz and Treanor do not recognize that the free speech principle is the key battleground for the legal protection of capital in the information economy. Opposition to the Copyright Term Extension Act turned precisely on the fact that the political economy of the information age blurs distinctions between regulations of speech and regulations of business practices in media corporations, and that ever-expanding property rights in patent, trademark, and copyright adversely affect freedom of expression. See Brief of Jack M. Balkin et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Petition at 15-21, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), available at 2002 WL 1041899. Much more troubling than the Court's conclusions about the Copyright Clause in Eldred is its cavalier dismissal of the important free speech interests in limited copyright terms. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 218-22. From this perspective, Eldred most closely resembles not Lochner v. New York, but the early twentieth-century cases Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919), Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919), and Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925), in which the Court rejected free speech claims and exercised judicial restraint. The danger is that an unrestrained legislature beholden to media interests will continually ramp up intellectual property protections at the expense of the free speech interests of others. Schwartz and Treanor note the argument that the expansion of intellectual property arises from rent-seeking by media corporations that have corrupted the political process. Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2406. However, failing to recognize the First Amendment interests involved, they assume that the only issue is the adjustment of property rights between competing stakeholders. They argue that the defects of political process, even if serious, cannot justify heightened judicial review, see United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938), because the theory of process protection should not apply to ordinary economic and social legislation but only to "the representation of minorities." Schwartz & Treanor, supra, at 2407. Perhaps tellingly, they omit the Carolene Products Court's argument that the theory of process protection is equally concerned with securing freedom of speech.
  • 111
    • 0347936365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARK A. GRABER, TRANSFORMING FREE SPEECH: THE AMBIGUOUS LEGACY OF CIVIL LIBERTARIANISM 92-93, 122-26 (1991) (noting rise of democratic conception in Progressive period and discussing democratic elements in Zechariah Chafee, Jr.'s theory of free expression); David M. Rabban, Free Speech in Progressive Social Thought, 74 TEX. L. REV. 951, 954-88 (1996) (discussing free speech theories of early twentieth-century progressive thinkers, including John Dewey and Herbert Croly).
    • (1991) Transforming Free Speech: The Ambiguous Legacy of Civil Libertarianism , pp. 92-93
    • Graber, M.A.1
  • 112
    • 0347936365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Free speech in progressive social thought
    • See MARK A. GRABER, TRANSFORMING FREE SPEECH: THE AMBIGUOUS LEGACY OF CIVIL LIBERTARIANISM 92-93, 122-26 (1991) (noting rise of democratic conception in Progressive period and discussing democratic elements in Zechariah Chafee, Jr.'s theory of free expression); David M. Rabban, Free Speech in Progressive Social Thought, 74 TEX. L. REV. 951, 954-88 (1996) (discussing free speech theories of early twentieth-century progressive thinkers, including John Dewey and Herbert Croly).
    • (1996) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.74 , pp. 951
    • Rabban, D.M.1
  • 113
    • 0004053887 scopus 로고
    • hereinafter MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM
    • See generally ALEXANDER MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM: THE CONSTITUTIONAL POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1960) [hereinafter MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM]; Alexander Meiklejohn, The First Amendment is an Absolute, 1961 SUP. CT. REV. 245 [hereinafter Meiklejohn, First Amendment].
    • (1960) Political Freedom: The Constitutional Powers of the People
    • Meiklejohn, A.1
  • 114
    • 0039097850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first amendment is an absolute
    • hereinafter Meiklejohn, First Amendment
    • See generally ALEXANDER MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM: THE CONSTITUTIONAL POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1960) [hereinafter MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM]; Alexander Meiklejohn, The First Amendment is an Absolute, 1961 SUP. CT. REV. 245 [hereinafter Meiklejohn, First Amendment].
    • Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.1961 , pp. 245
    • Meiklejohn, A.1
  • 115
    • 0004188294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH
    • See, e.g., OWEN M. FISS, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH (1996) [hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH]; CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405 (1986) [hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure]; Owen M. Fiss, Why the State?, 100 HARV. L. REV. 781 (1987) [hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?]; Harry Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SUP. CT. REV. 191. Fiss well describes the centrality of this theory in twentieth-century legal thought: The theory that animates this protection [of the speaker's autonomy], and that inspired Kalven, and before him Meiklejohn, and that now dominates the field, casts the underlying purpose of the first amendment in social or political terms: The purpose of free speech is not individual self-actualization, but rather the preservation of democracy, and the right of a people, as a people, to decide what kind of life it wishes to live. Autonomy is protected not because of its intrinsic value, as a Kantian might insist, but rather as a means or instrument of collective self-determination. We allow people to speak so others can vote. Speech allows people to vote intelligently and freely, aware of all the options and in possession of all the relevant information. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra, at 1409-10.
    • (1996) The Irony of Free Speech
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 116
    • 0003746578 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., OWEN M. FISS, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH (1996) [hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH]; CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405 (1986) [hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure]; Owen M. Fiss, Why the State?, 100 HARV. L. REV. 781 (1987) [hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?]; Harry Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SUP. CT. REV. 191. Fiss well describes the centrality of this theory in twentieth-century legal thought: The theory that animates this protection [of the speaker's autonomy], and that inspired Kalven, and before him Meiklejohn, and that now dominates the field, casts the underlying purpose of the first amendment in social or political terms: The purpose of free speech is not individual self-actualization, but rather the preservation of democracy, and the right of a people, as a people, to decide what kind of life it wishes to live. Autonomy is protected not because of its intrinsic value, as a Kantian might insist, but rather as a means or instrument of collective self-determination. We allow people to speak so others can vote. Speech allows people to vote intelligently and freely, aware of all the options and in possession of all the relevant information. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra, at 1409-10.
    • (1993) Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 117
    • 0040311462 scopus 로고
    • Free speech and social structure
    • hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure
    • See, e.g., OWEN M. FISS, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH (1996) [hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH]; CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405 (1986) [hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure]; Owen M. Fiss, Why the State?, 100 HARV. L. REV. 781 (1987) [hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?]; Harry Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SUP. CT. REV. 191. Fiss well describes the centrality of this theory in twentieth-century legal thought: The theory that animates this protection [of the speaker's autonomy], and that inspired Kalven, and before him Meiklejohn, and that now dominates the field, casts the underlying purpose of the first amendment in social or political terms: The purpose of free speech is not individual self-actualization, but rather the preservation of democracy, and the right of a people, as a people, to decide what kind of life it wishes to live. Autonomy is protected not because of its intrinsic value, as a Kantian might insist, but rather as a means or instrument of collective self-determination. We allow people to speak so others can vote. Speech allows people to vote intelligently and freely, aware of all the options and in possession of all the relevant information. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra, at 1409-10.
    • (1986) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 1405
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 118
    • 84928460367 scopus 로고
    • Why the state?
    • hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?
    • See, e.g., OWEN M. FISS, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH (1996) [hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH]; CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405 (1986) [hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure]; Owen M. Fiss, Why the State?, 100 HARV. L. REV. 781 (1987) [hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?]; Harry Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SUP. CT. REV. 191. Fiss well describes the centrality of this theory in twentieth-century legal thought: The theory that animates this protection [of the speaker's autonomy], and that inspired Kalven, and before him Meiklejohn, and that now dominates the field, casts the underlying purpose of the first amendment in social or political terms: The purpose of free speech is not individual self-actualization, but rather the preservation of democracy, and the right of a people, as a people, to decide what kind of life it wishes to live. Autonomy is protected not because of its intrinsic value, as a Kantian might insist, but rather as a means or instrument of collective self-determination. We allow people to speak so others can vote. Speech allows people to vote intelligently and freely, aware of all the options and in possession of all the relevant information. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra, at 1409-10.
    • (1987) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.100 , pp. 781
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 119
    • 0042598641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The New York Times case: A note on "The central meaning of the First Amendment"
    • See, e.g., OWEN M. FISS, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH (1996) [hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH]; CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405 (1986) [hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure]; Owen M. Fiss, Why the State?, 100 HARV. L. REV. 781 (1987) [hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?]; Harry Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SUP. CT. REV. 191. Fiss well describes the centrality of this theory in twentieth-century legal thought: The theory that animates this protection [of the speaker's autonomy], and that inspired Kalven, and before him Meiklejohn, and that now dominates the field, casts the underlying purpose of the first amendment in social or political terms: The purpose of free speech is not individual self-actualization, but rather the preservation of democracy, and the right of a people, as a people, to decide what kind of life it wishes to live. Autonomy is protected not because of its intrinsic value, as a Kantian might insist, but rather as a means or instrument of collective self-determination. We allow people to speak so others can vote. Speech allows people to vote intelligently and freely, aware of all the options and in possession of all the relevant information. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra, at 1409-10.
    • Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.1964 , pp. 191
    • Kalven, H.1
  • 120
    • 0347645925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • See, e.g., OWEN M. FISS, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH (1996) [hereinafter Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH]; CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993); Owen M. Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, 71 IOWA L. REV. 1405 (1986) [hereinafter Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure]; Owen M. Fiss, Why the State?, 100 HARV. L. REV. 781 (1987) [hereinafter Fiss, Why the State?]; Harry Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central
    • Free Speech and Social Structure , pp. 1409-1410
    • Fiss1
  • 121
    • 2442506514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker, supra note 9, at 126-27, 138-43, 152-53, 170-76
    • On the connections between democratic free speech theory and republicanism, see BAKER, supra note 9, at 126-27, 138-43, 152-53, 170-76. On the connection to the thought of the Progressive Era, see GRABER, supra note 47, at 75-121; Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58; Rabban, supra note 47.
  • 122
    • 2442531560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Graber, supra note 47, at 75-121
    • On the connections between democratic free speech theory and republicanism, see BAKER, supra note 9, at 126-27, 138-43, 152-53, 170-76. On the connection to the thought of the Progressive Era, see GRABER, supra note 47, at 75-121; Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58; Rabban, supra note 47.
  • 123
    • 2442569629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58
    • On the connections between democratic free speech theory and republicanism, see BAKER, supra note 9, at 126-27, 138-43, 152-53, 170-76. On the connection to the thought of the Progressive Era, see GRABER, supra note 47, at 75-121; Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58; Rabban, supra note 47.
  • 124
    • 2442479326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rabban, supra note 47
    • On the connections between democratic free speech theory and republicanism, see BAKER, supra note 9, at 126-27, 138-43, 152-53, 170-76. On the connection to the thought of the Progressive Era, see GRABER, supra note 47, at 75-121; Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58; Rabban, supra note 47.
  • 125
    • 2442582187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1947-48, 1956-58.
  • 126
    • 0039264909 scopus 로고
    • A marketplace approach to broadcast regulation
    • See, e.g., Mark S. Fowler & David L. Brenner, A Marketplace Approach to Broadcast Regulation, 60 TEX. L. REV. 207 (1982) (arguing for repeal of most forms of broadcast regulation).
    • (1982) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.60 , pp. 207
    • Fowler, M.S.1    Brenner, D.L.2
  • 127
    • 0040267387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 48
    • Meiklejohn was perhaps most overt about this, arguing that the First Amendment "has no concern about the 'needs of many men to express their opinions'" but rather is concerned with "the common needs of all the members of the body politic." MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 55; see also id. at 56-57, 61 (criticizing Zechariah Chafee, Jr. for being "misled by his inclusion of an individual interest within the scope of the First Amendment," and Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes for his "excessive individualism"). Owen Fiss, likewise, has emphasized that the First Amendment's concern with autonomy is primarily instrumental: "Autonomy may be protected, but only when it enriches public debate." Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 786.
    • Political Freedom , pp. 55
    • Meiklejohn1
  • 128
    • 2442429193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id. at 56-57, 61
    • Meiklejohn was perhaps most overt about this, arguing that the First Amendment "has no concern about the 'needs of many men to express their opinions'" but rather is concerned with "the common needs of all the members of the body politic." MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 55; see also id. at 56-57, 61 (criticizing Zechariah Chafee, Jr. for being "misled by his inclusion of an individual interest within the scope of the First Amendment," and Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes for his "excessive individualism"). Owen Fiss, likewise, has emphasized that the First Amendment's concern with autonomy is primarily instrumental: "Autonomy may be protected, but only when it enriches public debate." Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 786.
  • 129
    • 2442576698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 49
    • Meiklejohn was perhaps most overt about this, arguing that the First Amendment "has no concern about the 'needs of many men to express their opinions'" but rather is concerned with "the common needs of all the members of the body politic." MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 55; see also id. at 56-57, 61 (criticizing Zechariah Chafee, Jr. for being "misled by his inclusion of an individual interest within the scope of the First Amendment," and Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes for his "excessive individualism"). Owen Fiss, likewise, has emphasized that the First Amendment's concern with autonomy is primarily instrumental: "Autonomy may be protected, but only when it enriches public debate." Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 786.
    • Why the State? , pp. 786
    • Fiss1
  • 131
    • 0041702925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The constitution of status
    • On the social features of democracy implicit in the idea of a democratic culture, see J.M. Balkin, The Constitution of Status, 106 YALE L.J. 2313, 2314 (1997); J.M. Balkin, The Declaration and the Promise of a Democratic Culture, 4 WIDENER L. Symp. J. 167 (1999).
    • (1997) Yale L.J. , vol.106 , pp. 2313
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 132
    • 0041702925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The declaration and the promise of a democratic culture
    • On the social features of democracy implicit in the idea of a democratic culture, see J.M. Balkin, The Constitution of Status, 106 YALE L.J. 2313, 2314 (1997); J.M. Balkin, The Declaration and the Promise of a Democratic Culture, 4 WIDENER L. Symp. J. 167 (1999).
    • (1999) Widener L. Symp. J. , vol.4 , pp. 167
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 133
    • 0346818208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property and contract on the Internet
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1998) Chi.-Kent L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 1203
    • Fisher III, W.W.1
  • 134
    • 85012120602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Local discourse and the social issues
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (2000) Cardozo Stud. L. & Lit. , vol.12 , pp. 1
    • Karst, K.1
  • 135
    • 0003981873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • The Future of Ideas , pp. 9-10
    • Lessig1
  • 136
    • 2442594735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reimagining the public domain
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (2003) Law & Contemp. Probs. , vol.66 , pp. 463
    • Lange, D.1
  • 137
    • 0011645566 scopus 로고
    • Author/izing the celebrity: Publicity rights, postmodern politics, and unauthorized genders
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1992) Cardozo Arts & Ent. L.J. , vol.10 , pp. 365
    • Coombe, R.J.1
  • 138
    • 0011590121 scopus 로고
    • Objects of property and subjects of politics: Intellectual property laws and democratic dialogue
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1991) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.69 , pp. 1853
    • Coombe, R.1
  • 139
    • 0001411546 scopus 로고
    • Publicity rights and political aspiration: Mass culture, gender identity, and democracy
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1992) New Eng. L. Rev. , vol.26 , pp. 1221
    • Coombe, R.J.1
  • 140
    • 0039831888 scopus 로고
    • Expressive genericity: Trademarks as language in the Pepsi Generation
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1990) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 397
    • Dreyfuss, R.C.1
  • 141
    • 0242601875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cyberlaw and social change: A democratic approach to copyright law in cyberspace
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1996) Cardozo Arts & Ent. L.J. , vol.14 , pp. 215
    • Elkin-Koren, N.1
  • 142
    • 84933494284 scopus 로고
    • At play in the fields of the word: Copyright and the construction of authorship in the post-literate millennium
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1992) Law & Contemp. Probs. , vol.55 , pp. 139
    • Lange, D.1
  • 143
    • 0001059749 scopus 로고
    • The public domain
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1990) Emory L.J. , vol.39 , pp. 965
    • Litman, J.1
  • 144
    • 2442611597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Madow, supra note 2
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
  • 145
    • 2442493846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • last visited Dec. 3, 2003
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • Theories of Intellectual Property
    • Fisher, W.1
  • 146
    • 0038628726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Copyright and a democratic civil society
    • hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (1996) Yale L.J. , vol.106 , pp. 283
    • Netanel, N.W.1
  • 147
    • 0347740468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Market hierarchy and copyright in our system of free expression
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • (2000) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.53 , pp. 1879
    • Netanel, N.W.1
  • 148
    • 2442500277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • Legal scholars influenced by John Fiske have argued that intellectual property law should also serve the goals of promoting popular participation in culture, or what Fiske called "semiotic democracy." See, e.g., William W. Fisher III, Property and Contract on the Internet, 73 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1203, 1217 (1998) ("In an attractive society, all persons would be able to participate in the process of meaning-making. Instead of being merely passive consumers of cultural artifacts produced by others, they would be producers, helping to shape the world of ideas and symbols in which they live."); see also Kenneth Karst, Local Discourse and the Social Issues, 12 CARDOZO STUD. L. & LIT. 1, 27 (2000) (defining cultural democracy as "the broadest possible participation in the cultural processes that define and redefine the sort of society we shall be"). Larry Lessig's recent call for "free culture," see LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-10, also has important connections to the principles of semiotic democracy and democratic culture, as does David Lange's notion of free appropriation as a right of citizenship exercised in the public domain, see David Lange, Reimagining the Public Domain, 66 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 463, 475-83 (2003). Important examples of this trend in intellectual property scholarship include Rosemary J. Coombe, Author/izing the Celebrity: Publicity Rights, Postmodern Politics, and Unauthorized Genders, 10 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 365 (1992); Rosemary J. Coombe, Objects of Property and Subjects of Politics: Intellectual Property Laws and Democratic Dialogue, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1853 (1991); Rosemary J. Coombe, Publicity Rights and Political Aspiration: Mass Culture, Gender Identity, and Democracy, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 1221 (1992); Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the Pepsi Generation, 65 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 397 (1990); Niva Elkin-Koren, Cyberlaw and Social Change: A Democratic Approach to Copyright Law in Cyberspace, 14 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 215, 272-73 (1996); David Lange, At Play in the Fields of the Word: Copyright and the Construction of Authorship in the Post-Literate Millennium, 55 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 139 (1992); Jessica Litman, The Public Domain, 39 EMORY L.J. 965 (1990); Madow, supra note 2; William Fisher, Theories of Intellectual Property, at http://www.law.harvard.edu/Academic_Affairs/coursepages/tfisher/iptheory.html (last visited Dec. 3, 2003). Other scholars have sought to connect the proper scope of copyright, fair use and the public domain to the promotion of democracy in the sense of public discussion of public issues. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 347-65 (1996) [hereinafter Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society] (arguing that copyright promotes democracy by funding independent sectors of creativity); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Market Hierarchy and Copyright in Our System of Free Expression, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1879 (2000). This strand of intellectual property scholarship is somewhat closer to the republican or progressivist model; it emphasizes the importance of democratic public discourse and views popular culture as valuable to the extent that it contributes to a democratic civil society. See Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, supra, at 351 n.310.
    • Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society , vol.310 , pp. 351
    • Netanel1
  • 149
    • 34547951290 scopus 로고
    • Recuperating first amendment doctrine
    • For a helpful discussion, see Robert Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, 47 STAN. L. REV. 1249, 1253-55 (1995). Post argues that social practices and media for the communication of ideas are central to the formation of public opinion. Robert Post, Reconciling Theory and Doctrine in First Amendment Jurisprudence, 88 CAL. L. REV. 2353, 2367-69 (2000); Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, supra, at 1275-77.
    • (1995) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.47 , pp. 1249
    • Post, R.1
  • 150
    • 0042279875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reconciling theory and doctrine in first amendment jurisprudence
    • For a helpful discussion, see Robert Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, 47 STAN. L. REV. 1249, 1253-55 (1995). Post argues that social practices and media for the communication of ideas are central to the formation of public opinion. Robert Post, Reconciling Theory and Doctrine in First Amendment Jurisprudence, 88 CAL. L. REV. 2353, 2367-69 (2000); Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, supra, at 1275-77.
    • (2000) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 2353
    • Post, R.1
  • 151
    • 2442592559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • For a helpful discussion, see Robert Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, 47 STAN. L. REV. 1249, 1253-55 (1995). Post argues that social practices and media for the communication of ideas are central to the formation of public opinion. Robert Post, Reconciling Theory and Doctrine in First Amendment Jurisprudence, 88 CAL. L. REV. 2353, 2367-69 (2000); Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, supra, at 1275-77.
    • Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine , pp. 1275-1277
    • Post1
  • 152
    • 2442531559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 57, (discussing Mutual Film Corp. v. Industrial Comm., 236 U.S. 230, 243-45 (1915)
    • It was not always thus. See Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, supra note 57, at 1252-53 (discussing Mutual Film Corp. v. Industrial Comm., 236 U.S. 230, 243-45 (1915), in which Supreme Court originally held that motion pictures were not "organs of public opinion"). By 1952, the Supreme Court had come around, stating that "it cannot be doubted that motion pictures are a significant medium for the communication of ideas." Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.S. 495, 501 (1952). The difference between the Court's statements in 1915 and 1952 reflects important changes in American society to which the Court's First Amendment doctrines eventually responded. The scope of the free speech principle always grows out of a normatively inflected recognition of sociological realities.
    • Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine , pp. 1252-1253
    • Post1
  • 153
    • 2442533694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.S. 495, 501 (1952)
    • It was not always thus. See Post, Recuperating First Amendment Doctrine, supra note 57, at 1252-53 (discussing Mutual Film Corp. v. Industrial Comm., 236 U.S. 230, 243-45 (1915), in which Supreme Court originally held that motion pictures were not "organs of public opinion"). By 1952, the Supreme Court had come around, stating that "it cannot be doubted that motion pictures are a significant medium for the communication of ideas." Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.S. 495, 501 (1952). The difference between the Court's statements in 1915 and 1952 reflects important changes in American society to which the Court's First Amendment doctrines eventually responded. The scope of the free speech principle always grows out of a normatively inflected recognition of sociological realities.
  • 154
    • 2442500278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 377-78 (1968)
    • The free speech principle also applies to regulations of conduct that do not involve a generally recognized medium for the communication of ideas when the government regulates conduct because it disagrees with or desires to suppress the ideas it believes the conduct expresses. See United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 377-78 (1968) (holding that reasons for regulation of conduct must be unrelated to suppression of free expression). Thus, when government effectively treats conduct as a medium for the communication of ideas and punishes it on that basis, the free speech principle is also implicated.
  • 155
    • 2442588434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844, 850 (1997)
    • See, e.g., Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844, 850 (1997) ("The Internet is 'a unique and wholly new medium of worldwide human communication.'" (quoting ACLU v. Reno, 929 F. Supp. 824, 844 (E.D. Pa. 1996))).
  • 156
    • 2442443871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoting ACLU v. Reno, 929 F. Supp. 824, 844 (E.D. Pa. 1996)
    • See, e.g., Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844, 850 (1997) ("The Internet is 'a unique and wholly new medium of worldwide human communication.'" (quoting ACLU v. Reno, 929 F. Supp. 824, 844 (E.D. Pa. 1996))).
  • 157
    • 84884060136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 48
    • Meiklejohn himself argued that works of art were protected speech because they promoted knowledge, sharpened intelligence, and developed sensitivity to human values, thus helping people to make political decisions. Meiklejohn, First Amendment, supra note 48, at 255-57. Other scholars have recognized that not all artistic expression equally promotes democratic self-government. See, e.g., SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 153-59 (1993) (suggesting that nonpolitical art should be relegated to lower tier of First Amendment protection). And of course Robert Bork, who also had a democracy-based theory of the First Amendment, famously argued that art should receive no First Amendment protection if it was not political speech. Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 IND. L.J. 1, 26-28 (1971). Owen Fiss believes, to the contrary, that art, particularly unorthodox art and art underappreciated by market forces, furthers the goals of collective self-determination and democratic deliberation. He argues that government programs like the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) that subsidize art should look to art that is concerned with issues on the public agenda or that should be on the public agenda of discussion and comment. Thus, government subsidy of art should be designed to promote discussion of important public issues. Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH, supra note 49, at 40-45.
    • First Amendment , pp. 255-257
    • Meiklejohn1
  • 158
    • 2442467613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein, supra note 49, at 153-59 (1993)
    • Meiklejohn himself argued that works of art were protected speech because they promoted knowledge, sharpened intelligence, and developed sensitivity to human values, thus helping people to make political decisions. Meiklejohn, First Amendment, supra note 48, at 255-57. Other scholars have recognized that not all artistic expression equally promotes democratic self-government. See, e.g., SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 153-59 (1993) (suggesting that nonpolitical art should be relegated to lower tier of First Amendment protection). And of course Robert Bork, who also had a democracy-based theory of the First Amendment, famously argued that art should receive no First Amendment protection if it was not political speech. Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 IND. L.J. 1, 26-28 (1971). Owen Fiss believes, to the contrary, that art, particularly unorthodox art and art underappreciated by market forces, furthers the goals of collective self-determination and democratic deliberation. He argues that government programs like the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) that subsidize art should look to art that is concerned with issues on the public agenda or that should be on the public agenda of discussion and comment. Thus, government subsidy of art should be designed to promote discussion of important public issues. Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH, supra note 49, at 40-45.
  • 159
    • 0003374013 scopus 로고
    • Neutral principles and some first amendment problems
    • Meiklejohn himself argued that works of art were protected speech because they promoted knowledge, sharpened intelligence, and developed sensitivity to human values, thus helping people to make political decisions. Meiklejohn, First Amendment, supra note 48, at 255-57. Other scholars have recognized that not all artistic expression equally promotes democratic self-government. See, e.g., SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 153-59 (1993) (suggesting that nonpolitical art should be relegated to lower tier of First Amendment protection). And of course Robert Bork, who also had a democracy-based theory of the First Amendment, famously argued that art should receive no First Amendment protection if it was not political speech. Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 IND. L.J. 1, 26-28 (1971). Owen Fiss believes, to the contrary, that art, particularly unorthodox art and art underappreciated by market forces, furthers the goals of collective self-determination and democratic deliberation. He argues that government programs like the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) that subsidize art should look to art that is concerned with issues on the public agenda or that should be on the public agenda of discussion and comment. Thus, government subsidy of art should be designed to promote discussion of important public issues. Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH, supra note 49, at 40-45.
    • (1971) Ind. L.J. , vol.47 , pp. 1
    • Bork, R.H.1
  • 160
    • 0004188294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 49
    • Meiklejohn himself argued that works of art were protected speech because they promoted knowledge, sharpened intelligence, and developed sensitivity to human values, thus helping people to make political decisions. Meiklejohn, First Amendment, supra note 48, at 255-57. Other scholars have recognized that not all artistic expression equally promotes democratic self-government. See, e.g., SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 153-59 (1993) (suggesting that nonpolitical art should be relegated to lower tier of First Amendment protection). And of course Robert Bork, who also had a democracy-based theory of the First Amendment, famously argued that art should receive no First Amendment protection if it was not political speech. Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 IND. L.J. 1, 26-28 (1971). Owen Fiss believes, to the contrary, that art, particularly unorthodox art and art underappreciated by market forces, furthers the goals of collective self-determination and democratic deliberation. He argues that government programs like the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) that subsidize art should look to art that is concerned with issues on the public agenda or that should be on the public agenda of discussion and comment. Thus, government subsidy of art should be designed to promote discussion of important public issues. Fiss, THE IRONY OF FREE SPEECH, supra note 49, at 40-45.
    • The Irony of Free Speech , pp. 40-45
    • Fiss1
  • 161
    • 0346808125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The unruly character of politics
    • Cf. Owen M. Fiss, The Unruly Character of Politics, 29 MCGEORGE L. REV. 1, 2-7 (1997) (noting limitations of Meiklejohnian metaphor of town meeting as applied to confrontational politics).
    • (1997) McGeorge L. Rev. , vol.29 , pp. 1
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 163
    • 0001006507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A right to read anonymously: A closer look at "Copyright management" in Cyberspace
    • As Julie Cohen reminds us, digital technologies tend to blur the boundaries between production and reception, speaking and reading, or even between viewing and copying. See Julie E. Cohen, A Right to Read Anonymously: A Closer Look at "Copyright Management" in Cyberspace, 28 CONN. L. REV. 981, 1004-09 (1996); see also Rubenfeld, supra note 5, at 34-36 (arguing that theories of freedom of expression based in autonomy and self expression do not sufficiently account for First Amendment right to read as well as to express one's self).
    • (1996) Conn. L. Rev. , vol.28 , pp. 981
    • Cohen, J.E.1
  • 164
    • 2442433351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rubenfeld, supra note 5, at 34-36
    • As Julie Cohen reminds us, digital technologies tend to blur the boundaries between production and reception, speaking and reading, or even between viewing and copying. See Julie E. Cohen, A Right to Read Anonymously: A Closer Look at "Copyright Management" in Cyberspace, 28 CONN. L. REV. 981, 1004-09 (1996); see also Rubenfeld, supra note 5, at 34-36 (arguing that theories of freedom of expression based in autonomy and self expression do not sufficiently account for First Amendment right to read as well as to express one's self).
  • 165
    • 0004149207 scopus 로고
    • Memetics is an evolutionary theory that attempts to explain the development of culture through the transmission of bits of culture, or memes, which replicate themselves in human minds. The term "meme" was coined by the zoologist Richard Dawkins. See RICHARD DAWKINS, THE SELFISH GENE 189-94 (1977). Memetic theory often tends to undermine agency and selfhood, see, e.g., SUSAN BLACKMORE, THE MEME MACHINE (1999), and thus would seem an odd choice for a theory of self expression. But memetics can also be employed to explain concepts central to agency and selfhood like freedom, see DANIEL C. DENNETT, FREEDOM EVOLVES 175-92, 266 (2003), or the growth of human belief systems and human innovation, see BALKIN, supra note 63, at 42-97, 173-75. The idea of memetic democracy emphasizes the deep connections between self and agency on the one hand, and cultural evolution and the shaping of the self through cultural exchange on the other. Memetic democracy means that everyone gets to participate in the distribution and dissemination of memes, which are the building blocks of the cultural software that constitutes individuals as individuals.
    • (1977) The Selfish Gene , pp. 189-194
    • Dawkins, R.1
  • 166
    • 0003768085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Memetics is an evolutionary theory that attempts to explain the development of culture through the transmission of bits of culture, or memes, which replicate themselves in human minds. The term "meme" was coined by the zoologist Richard Dawkins. See RICHARD DAWKINS, THE SELFISH GENE 189-94 (1977). Memetic theory often tends to undermine agency and selfhood, see, e.g., SUSAN BLACKMORE, THE MEME MACHINE (1999), and thus would seem an odd choice for a theory of self expression. But memetics can also be employed to explain concepts central to agency and selfhood like freedom, see DANIEL C. DENNETT, FREEDOM EVOLVES 175-92, 266 (2003), or the growth of human belief systems and human innovation, see BALKIN, supra note 63, at 42-97, 173-75. The idea of memetic democracy emphasizes the deep connections between self and agency on the one hand, and cultural evolution and the shaping of the self through cultural exchange on the other. Memetic democracy means that everyone gets to participate in the distribution and dissemination of memes, which are the building blocks of the cultural software that constitutes individuals as individuals.
    • (1999) The Meme Machine
    • Blackmore, S.1
  • 167
    • 0038629814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Memetics is an evolutionary theory that attempts to explain the development of culture through the transmission of bits of culture, or memes, which replicate themselves in human minds. The term "meme" was coined by the zoologist Richard Dawkins. See RICHARD DAWKINS, THE SELFISH GENE 189-94 (1977). Memetic theory often tends to undermine agency and selfhood, see, e.g., SUSAN BLACKMORE, THE MEME MACHINE (1999), and thus would seem an odd choice for a theory of self expression. But memetics can also be employed to explain concepts central to agency and selfhood like freedom, see DANIEL C. DENNETT, FREEDOM EVOLVES 175-92, 266 (2003), or the growth of human belief systems and human innovation, see BALKIN, supra note 63, at 42-97, 173-75. The idea of memetic democracy emphasizes the deep connections between self and agency on the one hand, and cultural evolution and the shaping of the self through cultural exchange on the other. Memetic democracy means that everyone gets to participate in the distribution and dissemination of memes, which are the building blocks of the cultural software that constitutes individuals as individuals.
    • (2003) Freedom Evolves , pp. 175-192
    • Dennett, D.C.1
  • 168
    • 2442463009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 63, at 42-97, 173-75
    • Memetics is an evolutionary theory that attempts to explain the development of culture through the transmission of bits of culture, or memes, which replicate themselves in human minds. The term "meme" was coined by the zoologist Richard Dawkins. See RICHARD DAWKINS, THE SELFISH GENE 189-94 (1977). Memetic theory often tends to undermine agency and selfhood, see, e.g., SUSAN BLACKMORE, THE MEME MACHINE (1999), and thus would seem an odd choice for a theory of self expression. But memetics can also be employed to explain concepts central to agency and selfhood like freedom, see DANIEL C. DENNETT, FREEDOM EVOLVES 175-92, 266 (2003), or the growth of human belief systems and human innovation, see BALKIN, supra note 63, at 42-97, 173-75. The idea of memetic democracy emphasizes the deep connections between self and agency on the one hand, and cultural evolution and the shaping of the self through cultural exchange on the other. Memetic democracy means that everyone gets to participate in the distribution and dissemination of memes, which are the building blocks of the cultural software that constitutes individuals as individuals.
  • 169
    • 0040876046 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., LEE C. BOLLINGER, IMAGES OF A FREE PRESS 138-41 (1991) (contrasting burdens of education for civic life with pleasantness of entertainment); SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 84-91 (decrying "low quality" programming that appeals to tastes of uneducated); Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra note 49, at 1413 ("From the perspective of a free and open debate, the choice between Love Boat and Fantasy Island is trivial."); Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 788 (contrasting reruns of "I Love Lucy" and MTV with "the information [members of the electorate] need to make free and intelligent choices about government policy, the structure of government, or the nature of society."). Once again, this familiar progressivist theme is already present in Meiklejohn. See MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 87 (attacking commercial radio for "corrupt[ing] both our morals and our intelligence"). Even Justice Louis Brandeis fell prey to this sort of cultural elitism, which pervades his famous call for protecting the right of privacy from a particular form of speech. See Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 196 (1890) (arguing that "personal gossip," "[e]asy of comprehension [and] appealing to that weak side of human nature," "crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community," and "destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling").
    • (1991) Images of a Free Press , pp. 138-141
    • Bollinger, L.C.1
  • 170
    • 2442556923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein, supra note 49, at 84-91
    • See, e.g., LEE C. BOLLINGER, IMAGES OF A FREE PRESS 138-41 (1991) (contrasting burdens of education for civic life with pleasantness of entertainment); SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 84-91 (decrying "low quality" programming that appeals to tastes of uneducated); Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra note 49, at 1413 ("From the perspective of a free and open debate, the choice between Love Boat and Fantasy Island is trivial."); Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 788 (contrasting reruns of "I Love Lucy" and MTV with "the information [members of the electorate] need to make free and intelligent choices about government policy, the structure of government, or the nature of society."). Once again, this familiar progressivist theme is already present in Meiklejohn. See MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 87 (attacking commercial radio for "corrupt[ing] both our morals and our intelligence"). Even Justice Louis Brandeis fell prey to this sort of cultural elitism, which pervades his famous call for protecting the right of privacy from a particular form of speech. See Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 196 (1890) (arguing that "personal gossip," "[e]asy of comprehension [and] appealing to that weak side of human nature," "crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community," and "destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling").
  • 171
    • 0347645925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 49
    • See, e.g., LEE C. BOLLINGER, IMAGES OF A FREE PRESS 138-41 (1991) (contrasting burdens of education for civic life with pleasantness of entertainment); SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 84-91 (decrying "low quality" programming that appeals to tastes of uneducated); Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra note 49, at 1413 ("From the perspective of a free and open debate, the choice between Love Boat and Fantasy Island is trivial."); Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 788 (contrasting reruns of "I Love Lucy" and MTV with "the information [members of the electorate] need to make free and intelligent choices about government policy, the structure of government, or the nature of society."). Once again, this familiar progressivist theme is already present in Meiklejohn. See MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 87 (attacking commercial radio for "corrupt[ing] both our morals and our intelligence"). Even Justice Louis Brandeis fell prey to this sort of cultural elitism, which pervades his famous call for protecting the right of privacy from a particular form of speech. See Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 196 (1890) (arguing that "personal gossip," "[e]asy of comprehension [and] appealing to that weak side of human nature," "crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community," and "destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling").
    • Free Speech and Social Structure , pp. 1413
    • Fiss1
  • 172
    • 2442576698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 49
    • See, e.g., LEE C. BOLLINGER, IMAGES OF A FREE PRESS 138-41 (1991) (contrasting burdens of education for civic life with pleasantness of entertainment); SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 84-91 (decrying "low quality" programming that appeals to tastes of uneducated); Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra note 49, at 1413 ("From the perspective of a free and open debate, the choice between Love Boat and Fantasy Island is trivial."); Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 788 (contrasting reruns of "I Love Lucy" and MTV with "the information [members of the electorate] need to make free and intelligent choices about government policy, the structure of government, or the nature of society."). Once again, this familiar progressivist theme is already present in Meiklejohn. See MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 87 (attacking commercial radio for "corrupt[ing] both our morals and our intelligence"). Even Justice Louis Brandeis fell prey to this sort of cultural elitism, which pervades his famous call for protecting the right of privacy from a particular form of speech. See Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 196 (1890) (arguing that "personal gossip," "[e]asy of comprehension [and] appealing to that weak side of human nature," "crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community," and "destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling").
    • Why the State , pp. 788
    • Fiss1
  • 173
    • 0040267387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 48
    • See, e.g., LEE C. BOLLINGER, IMAGES OF A FREE PRESS 138-41 (1991) (contrasting burdens of education for civic life with pleasantness of entertainment); SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 84-91 (decrying "low quality" programming that appeals to tastes of uneducated); Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra note 49, at 1413 ("From the perspective of a free and open debate, the choice between Love Boat and Fantasy Island is trivial."); Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 788 (contrasting reruns of "I Love Lucy" and MTV with "the information [members of the electorate] need to make free and intelligent choices about government policy, the structure of government, or the nature of society."). Once again, this familiar progressivist theme is already present in Meiklejohn. See MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 87 (attacking commercial radio for "corrupt[ing] both our morals and our intelligence"). Even Justice Louis Brandeis fell prey to this sort of cultural elitism, which pervades his famous call for protecting the right of privacy from a particular form of speech. See Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 196 (1890) (arguing that "personal gossip," "[e]asy of comprehension [and] appealing to that weak side of human nature," "crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community," and "destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling").
    • Political Freedom , pp. 87
    • Meiklejohn1
  • 174
    • 0000320829 scopus 로고
    • The right to privacy
    • See, e.g., LEE C. BOLLINGER, IMAGES OF A FREE PRESS 138-41 (1991) (contrasting burdens of education for civic life with pleasantness of entertainment); SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 84-91 (decrying "low quality" programming that appeals to tastes of uneducated); Fiss, Free Speech and Social Structure, supra note 49, at 1413 ("From the perspective of a free and open debate, the choice between Love Boat and Fantasy Island is trivial."); Fiss, Why the State?, supra note 49, at 788 (contrasting reruns of "I Love Lucy" and MTV with "the information [members of the electorate] need to make free and intelligent choices about government policy, the structure of government, or the nature of society."). Once again, this familiar progressivist theme is already present in Meiklejohn. See MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM, supra note 48, at 87 (attacking commercial radio for "corrupt[ing] both our morals and our intelligence"). Even Justice Louis Brandeis fell prey to this sort of cultural elitism, which pervades his famous call for protecting the right of privacy from a particular form of speech. See Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 196 (1890) (arguing that "personal gossip," "[e]asy of comprehension [and] appealing to that weak side of human nature," "crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community," and "destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling").
    • (1890) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.4 , pp. 193
    • Warren, S.1    Brandeis, L.2
  • 175
    • 2442491782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1948-49 (footnotes omitted)
    • In this sense the Internet simply empowers the popular appropriation and transformation of mass culture that already existed: Much of mass culture involves programming, advertisements, architecture, and artwork produced by corporations and designed to sell products and make money. Many critiques of mass culture warn of the deleterious consequences of consumerism and mass consumption.... But a populist view [of democratic culture] also emphasizes that ordinary people are not mere passive receptors of the messages offered in advertising, television programming, and other elements of contemporary mass culture. Such assumptions are just another way of denigrating the intelligence and abilities of ordinary people. People do not uncritically absorb and assimilate the images they see on the television screen-they process, discuss, and appropriate them. People are active interpreters and rearrangers of what they find in mass culture. They use the raw materials of mass culture to articulate and express their values. Through this process, they produce and reproduce popular culture. Balkin, supra note 2, at 1948-49 (footnotes omitted).
  • 176
    • 0003981873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17
    • The reference is to Apple's famous commercial instructing users of its iPod to "[R]ip, mix, and burn.... After all, it's your music." Larry Lessig uses the slogan as a metaphor for a free culture. LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS, supra note 17, at 9-11.
    • The Future of Ideas , pp. 9-11
    • Lessig1
  • 177
    • 0346302271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein, supra note 49, at 87-91
    • See SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 87-91; see also Cass R. Sunstein, Television and the Public Interest, 88 CAL. L. REV. 499, 518 (2000) (arguing that goal of television regulation is to promote deliberative democracy).
  • 178
    • 0346302271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Television and the public interest
    • See SUNSTEIN, supra note 49, at 87-91; see also Cass R. Sunstein, Television and the Public Interest, 88 CAL. L. REV. 499, 518 (2000) (arguing that goal of television regulation is to promote deliberative democracy).
    • (2000) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 499
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 179
    • 2442586303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 2, at 1948
    • See Balkin, supra note 2, at 1948 ("[P]opular culture is neither a debilitated version of democratic culture nor a mere diversion from the sober processes of deliberation imagined by progressivism. It is not a sideshow or distraction from democratic culture but the main event. Moreover, [a] populis[t] [approach to free expression] accepts, as progressivism does not, that popular culture-which is also democratic culture-is by nature unkempt and unruly, occasionally raucous and even vulgar. It is by turns both eloquent and mawkish, noble and embarrassing, wise and foolish, resistant to blandishments and gullible in the extreme. It is imperfect in precisely the same sense that democracy itself is imperfect.").
  • 180
    • 85055295295 scopus 로고
    • Managing deliberation: The quandary of democratic dialogue
    • Robert Post has emphasized this limitation of the Meiklejohn model, arguing that the autonomy of public discourse, necessary for democratic self-government, is undermined by imposing managerial methods to cabin its scope and agendas. See generally Robert Post, Managing Deliberation: The Quandary of Democratic Dialogue, 103 ETHICS 654 (1993); Robert Post, Meiklejohn's Mistake: Individual Autonomy and the Reform of Public Discourse, 64 U. COLO. L. REV. 1109 (1993).
    • (1993) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 654
    • Post, R.1
  • 181
    • 0039970778 scopus 로고
    • Meiklejohn's mistake: Individual autonomy and the reform of public discourse
    • Robert Post has emphasized this limitation of the Meiklejohn model, arguing that the autonomy of public discourse, necessary for democratic self-government, is undermined by imposing managerial methods to cabin its scope and agendas. See generally Robert Post, Managing Deliberation: The Quandary of Democratic Dialogue, 103 ETHICS 654 (1993); Robert Post, Meiklejohn's Mistake: Individual Autonomy and the Reform of Public Discourse, 64 U. COLO. L. REV. 1109 (1993).
    • (1993) U. Colo. L. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 1109
    • Post, R.1
  • 184
    • 2442603216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker, supra note 9, at 13, 24-26, 88-91, 182-90
    • Indeed, the standard progressivist/republican arguments for regulation of broadcast, cable, and satellite can and should be rearticulated in terms of the more populist perspective of promoting democratic culture. The key point is that the United States has adopted a hybrid system: Instead of separating the functions of editor and distributor, and treating all distribution networks as common carriers like telephone companies, it has allowed a small number of editors/speakers to own powerful distribution networks not open to all in return for accepting various public service obligations and regulations. Thus the hybrid system is based on the model of a contract or a quid pro quo. Although the hybrid system denies the vast majority of people free access to key distribution networks, it may nevertheless have been justified in the past by its economic advantages. Arguably it offers necessary incentives for broadcasters, cable companies, and owners of satellite systems to invest in, produce, and deliver a wide variety of diverse programming for viewers and listeners that will enrich public debate and public culture. Thus, it provides considerable grist for the mill of a democratic culture. Nevertheless, a hybrid system is hardly perfect. Heavy reliance on advertising tends to create a significant mismatch between what broadcasters deliver and what viewers want, in part because advertisers seek content that appeals to the common tastes of certain valued demographic groups (whose preferences may otherwise be quite heterogenous) rather than content that cross-cuts demographic groups or appeals to groups with comparatively little disposable income or comparatively unmanipulable consumption patterns. See BAKER, supra note 9, at 13, 24-26, 88-91, 182-90. Advertisers will also tend to push for content that helps induce greater consumption instead of content that appeals to and fulfils other values that viewers might have. For example, viewers may value many kinds of content that are not strongly tied to shopping, purchasing, and consumption. They may value content that educates them or inspires them to change their lives, rethink their values, or make use of their creative powers. Finally, market forces also will, almost by definition, underproduce content that has high positive externalities (like educational content, or balanced and informative coverage of news) because the value of that content to society cannot be captured by market forces, and, all other things being equal, the greater the positive externalities, the more underproduction there will be. Id. at 41-62, 114-18. The hybrid model of media regulation is not constitutionally required. Rather, it is a quid pro quo or contractual arrangement, and it is constitutional to the extent that it promotes the values of a democratic culture. To be sure, regulatory quid pro quos can violate free speech rights if they impose an unconstitutional condition on free speech. However, structural regulations of the mass media that seek to counteract the limitations of mass media markets should be constitutional if there is a clear nexus between the goals of the regulation and the purposes behind the choice of a hybrid system. To the extent that structural regulations and public interest obligations of mass media compensate for the limitations of a hybrid model, they are tied to the very justifications for issuing broadcast licenses and cable franchises in the first place: They help further the goal of promoting a rich public sphere and a vibrant, participatory, and democratic culture. If government can make a sufficiently good case that the regulations will have this effect, the regulations should not be regarded as unconstitutional conditions on a media company's First Amendment rights. Likewise, public broadcasting that supplements existing markets with content that government reasonably believes to be valuable (like children's programming) should also be constitutionally permissible.
  • 185
    • 2442433352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 41-62, 114-18
    • Indeed, the standard progressivist/republican arguments for regulation of broadcast, cable, and satellite can and should be rearticulated in terms of the more populist perspective of promoting democratic culture. The key point is that the United States has adopted a hybrid system: Instead of separating the functions of editor and distributor, and treating all distribution networks as common carriers like telephone companies, it has allowed a small number of editors/speakers to own powerful distribution networks not open to all in return for accepting various public service obligations and regulations. Thus the hybrid system is based on the model of a contract or a quid pro quo. Although the hybrid system denies the vast majority of people free access to key distribution networks, it may nevertheless have been justified in the past by its economic advantages. Arguably it offers necessary incentives for broadcasters, cable companies, and owners of satellite systems to invest in, produce, and deliver a wide variety of diverse programming for viewers and listeners that will enrich public debate and public culture. Thus, it provides considerable grist for the mill of a democratic culture. Nevertheless, a hybrid system is hardly perfect. Heavy reliance on advertising tends to create a significant mismatch between what broadcasters deliver and what viewers want, in part because advertisers seek content that appeals to the common tastes of certain valued demographic groups (whose preferences may otherwise be quite heterogenous) rather than content that cross-cuts demographic groups or appeals to groups with comparatively little disposable income or comparatively unmanipulable consumption patterns. See BAKER, supra note 9, at 13, 24-26, 88-91, 182-90. Advertisers will also tend to push for content that helps induce greater consumption instead of content that appeals to and fulfils other values that viewers might have. For example, viewers may value many kinds of content that are not strongly tied to shopping, purchasing, and consumption. They may value content that educates them or inspires them to change their lives, rethink their values, or make use of their creative powers. Finally, market forces also will, almost by definition, underproduce content that has high positive externalities (like educational content, or balanced and informative coverage of news) because the value of that content to society cannot be captured by market forces, and, all other things being equal, the greater the positive externalities, the more underproduction there will be. Id. at 41-62, 114-18. The hybrid model of media regulation is not constitutionally required. Rather, it is a quid pro quo or contractual arrangement, and it is constitutional to the extent that it promotes the values of a democratic culture. To be sure, regulatory quid pro quos can violate free speech rights if they impose an unconstitutional condition on free speech. However, structural regulations of the mass media that seek to counteract the limitations of mass media markets should be constitutional if there is a clear nexus between the goals of the regulation and the purposes behind the choice of a hybrid system. To the extent that structural regulations and public interest obligations of mass media compensate for the limitations of a hybrid model, they are tied to the very justifications for issuing broadcast licenses and cable franchises in the first place: They help further the goal of promoting a rich public sphere and a vibrant, participatory, and democratic culture. If government can make a sufficiently good case that the regulations will have this effect, the regulations should not be regarded as unconstitutional conditions on a media company's First Amendment rights. Likewise, public broadcasting that supplements existing markets with content that government reasonably believes to be valuable (like children's programming) should also be constitutionally permissible.
  • 186
    • 2442527437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 68
    • See supra note 68.
  • 187
    • 2442565399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Balkin, supra note 63, at 17-19
    • See BALKIN, supra note 63, at 17-19.
  • 188
    • 0036444783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cultural dissent
    • See Madhavi Sunder, Cultural Dissent, 54 STAN. L. REV. 495, 498 (2001) (noting ubiquitous disputes within cultural groups about values of group and terms of membership).
    • (2001) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.54 , pp. 495
    • Sunder, M.1
  • 189
    • 0003762704 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JUDITH P. BUTLER, GENDER TROUBLE: FEMINISM AND THE SUBVERSION OF IDENTITY 141-49 (1990) (noting possibilities for subversion of existing sexual roles and creation of new ones through repetition and through performance); Amy M. Adler, What's Left?, 84 CAL. L. REV. 1499, 1529-31 (1996) (describing how pornography has been appropriated for feminist purposes); Judith P. Butler, The Force of Fantasy: Feminism, Mapplethorpe, and Discursive Excess, 2 DIFFERENCES 105, 119-20 (1990) (arguing that "discursive excess" offers opportunities for subversion and parody).
    • (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity , pp. 141-149
    • Butler, J.P.1
  • 190
    • 0346044970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What's left?
    • See, e.g., JUDITH P. BUTLER, GENDER TROUBLE: FEMINISM AND THE SUBVERSION OF IDENTITY 141-49 (1990) (noting possibilities for subversion of existing sexual roles and creation of new ones through repetition and through performance); Amy M. Adler, What's Left?, 84 CAL. L. REV. 1499, 1529-31 (1996) (describing how pornography has been appropriated for feminist purposes); Judith P. Butler, The Force of Fantasy: Feminism, Mapplethorpe, and Discursive Excess, 2 DIFFERENCES 105, 119-20 (1990) (arguing that "discursive excess" offers opportunities for subversion and parody).
    • (1996) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 1499
    • Adler, A.M.1
  • 191
    • 84935445837 scopus 로고
    • The force of fantasy: Feminism, mapplethorpe, and discursive excess
    • See, e.g., JUDITH P. BUTLER, GENDER TROUBLE: FEMINISM AND THE SUBVERSION OF IDENTITY 141-49 (1990) (noting possibilities for subversion of existing sexual roles and creation of new ones through repetition and through performance); Amy M. Adler, What's Left?, 84 CAL. L. REV. 1499, 1529-31 (1996) (describing how pornography has been appropriated for feminist purposes); Judith P. Butler, The Force of Fantasy: Feminism, Mapplethorpe, and Discursive Excess, 2 DIFFERENCES 105, 119-20 (1990) (arguing that "discursive excess" offers opportunities for subversion and parody).
    • (1990) Differences , vol.2 , pp. 105
    • Butler, J.P.1
  • 192
    • 2442529523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baker, supra note 9, at 41-55
    • See BAKER, supra note 9, at 41-55.
  • 193
    • 2442582152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Purchasing media products is a kind of liberty, because it involves choice. It is also a kind of creativity, because an agreement between a willing buyer and a willing seller creates wealth. But it does not exhaust the forms of choice and creativity with which freedom of speech is concerned.
  • 194
    • 0347433636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Designing deliberative democracy in cyberspace: The role of the cyber-lawyer
    • See Beth Simone Noveck, Designing Deliberative Democracy in Cyberspace: The Role of the Cyber-Lawyer, 9 B.U.J. Sci. & TECH. L. 1, 5, 8-10 (2003).
    • (2003) B.U.J. Sci. & Tech. L. , vol.9 , pp. 1
    • Noveck, B.S.1
  • 196
    • 0035545035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal historicism and legal academics: The roles of law professors in the wake of Bush v. Gore
    • For a more general account of legal historicism, of which dynamism is a special case, see Jack M. Balkin & Sanford Levinson, Legal Historicism and Legal Academics: The Roles of Law Professors in the Wake of Bush v. Gore, 90 GEO. L.J. 173, 174-75 (2001) (defining legal historicism as claim that legal conventions and forms of legal argument gradually change in response to political and social struggles that are waged through them). See also PAUL BREST, SANFORD LEVINSON, J.M. BALKIN & AKHIL REED AMAR, PROCESSES OF CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONMAKING, at xxxi-xxxii (4th ed. 2000) (articulating theory of constitutional historicism). I am using the term "dynamism" rather than historicism in order to emphasize two separate points: First, rights dynamism is internal to participants in the practice of rights discourse rather than a stance that merely studies the discourse from the outside with no particular stake in its outcome. Second, rights dynamism is forward-looking, concerned with the future of a practice whose full contours cannot be known in advance, rather than a backward-looking historicism that attempts to articulate and comprehend changes that occurred in the distant past.
    • (2001) Geo. L.J. , vol.90 , pp. 173
    • Balkin, J.M.1    Levinson, S.2
  • 197
    • 0035545035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4th ed
    • For a more general account of legal historicism, of which dynamism is a special case, see Jack M. Balkin & Sanford Levinson, Legal Historicism and Legal Academics: The Roles of Law Professors in the Wake of Bush v. Gore, 90 GEO. L.J. 173, 174-75 (2001) (defining legal historicism as claim that legal conventions and forms of legal argument gradually change in response to political and social struggles that are waged through them). See also PAUL BREST, SANFORD LEVINSON, J.M. BALKIN & AKHIL REED AMAR, PROCESSES OF CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONMAKING, at xxxi-xxxii (4th ed. 2000) (articulating theory of constitutional historicism). I am using the term "dynamism" rather than historicism in order to emphasize two separate points: First, rights dynamism is internal to participants in the practice of rights discourse rather than a stance that merely studies the discourse from the outside with no particular stake in its outcome. Second, rights dynamism is forward-looking, concerned with the future of a practice whose full contours cannot be known in advance, rather than a backward-looking historicism that attempts to articulate and comprehend changes that occurred in the distant past.
    • (2000) Processes of Constitutional Decisionmaking
    • Brest, P.1    Levinson, S.2    Balkin, J.M.3    Reed, A.A.4


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.