메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 3, 2003, Pages 272-279

Defending transitivity against zeno's paradox

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 22544476048     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2003.00272.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (33)

References (19)
  • 1
    • 1042287762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Continuum argument for intransitivity
    • See Larry Temkin, "A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity," Philosophy & Public Affairs 25 (1996): 175-210;
    • (1996) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.25 , pp. 175-210
    • Temkin, L.1
  • 2
    • 33750000372 scopus 로고
    • unpublished undergraduate thesis, University of Oxford
    • Stuart Rachels, A Theory of Beneficence (unpublished undergraduate thesis, University of Oxford, 1993)
    • (1993) A Theory of Beneficence
    • Rachels, S.1
  • 3
    • 22544472841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Counterexamples to the transitivity of better than
    • "Counterexamples to the Transitivity of Better Than," Australasian lournal of Philosophy 76 (1998): 71-83
    • (1998) Australasian Lournal of Philosophy , vol.76 , pp. 71-83
  • 4
    • 22544480957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A set of solutions to parfit's problems
    • "A Set of Solutions to Parfit's Problems," Noûs 35 (2001): 214-38
    • (2001) Noûs , vol.35 , pp. 214-238
  • 5
    • 47249097496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intransitivity
    • (2nd ed.), ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte Becker ,London: Routledge
    • and "Intransitivity," in volume II of The Encyclopedia of Ethics (2nd ed.), ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte Becker (London: Routledge, 2001), pp. 877-79.
    • (2001) Encyclopedia of Ethics , vol.2 , pp. 877-879
  • 8
    • 78751668323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • mentions 100 times as long, while Temkin mentions twice as long. Nothing depends on this number
    • Rachels, "Counterexamples," p. 73, mentions 100 times as long, while Temkin mentions twice as long. Nothing depends on this number.
    • Counterexamples , vol.73
  • 11
    • 78751659953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note how our proposed utility function matches with Temkin
    • My model for this is something like the following. Torture's badness might range from 0 to 10, depending on its duration, with two years of torture being, say, a 7. A hangnail's badness might range from 0 to 1. Prolonging a hangnail increases the value of the decimal places representing its 'badness score', but the fundamental gap between 1 and 7 is never affected."
    • Note how our proposed utility function matches with Temkin, "Continuum," p. 192: "My model for this is something like the following. Torture's badness might range from 0 to 10, depending on its duration, with two years of torture being, say, a 7. A hangnail's badness might range from 0 to 1. Prolonging a hangnail increases the value of the decimal places representing its 'badness score', but the fundamental gap between 1 and 7 is never affected."
    • Continuum , vol.192
  • 14
    • 85098468541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intransitiv
    • "A Set of Solutions," pp. 215-16, and "Intransitivity. "
    • A Set of Solutions , pp. 215-216
  • 18
    • 0000291018 scopus 로고
    • The bargaining problem
    • The Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives was introduced by John Nash in "The Bargaining Problem," Econometrica 18 (1950): 155-62.
    • (1950) Econometrica , vol.18 , pp. 155-162
    • Nash, J.1
  • 19
    • 0001457237 scopus 로고
    • Internal consistency of choice
    • It differs from Kenneth Arrow's well-known condition of the same name that relates individual and social preferences.Amartya Sen, in "Internal Consistency of Choice," Econometricu 61 (1993): 495-521, expresses regret at the fact that Nash's and Arrow's conditions are often confused and renames Nash's condition "basic contraction consistency." If a choice function C specifies for any admissible nonempty set S of alternatives a nonempty subset C(S) called the choice set of S, then Sen formulates the condition as (x ∈ C(S) and x ∈ C(Q). For the condition to make sense, the alternatives must be formulated in a manner that makes it possible to eliminate alternatives from a feasible set without altering our relative valuation of the alternatives that remain. Sen describes cases where this property appears to be violated by a rational chooser, but all his examples involve cases where the removal of one of the unchosen options changes the (expected) worth of the remaining alternatives. This means that the removed options are not irrelevant to the remaining alternatives.
    • (1993) Econometrica , vol.61 , pp. 495-521
    • Sen, A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.