메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 24, Issue 4, 1996, Pages 620-652

Politics and coercion

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 21444458960     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591796024004002     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (42)
  • 1
    • 85033059325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, chap. 13,9; Rawls
    • Leviathan, chap. 13,9; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 126.
    • A Theory of Justice , vol.126
  • 2
    • 85033046494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Part of Adeimantos's challenge to Socrates in Republic, 365 d.
    • Part of Adeimantos's challenge to Socrates in Republic, 365 d.
  • 3
    • 0003522397 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press
    • For example, Michael Taylor, Community, Anarchy, and Liberty (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 25-33.
    • (1982) Community, Anarchy, and Liberty , pp. 25-33
    • Taylor, M.1
  • 4
    • 85033044532 scopus 로고
    • New York: Free Press
    • For example, James Q. Wilson, The Moral Sense (New York: Free Press, 1993), 40-4, 126-31.
    • (1993) The Moral Sense , vol.40 , Issue.4 , pp. 126-131
    • Wilson, J.Q.1
  • 5
    • 85033050197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dante, Inferno, iii. 22-69.
    • See Dante, Inferno, iii. 22-69.
  • 6
    • 85033053730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In many early modern liberal theories the god of a civil religion was to exercise a substantial part of the coercive function. But that only drove the alienation deeper: either alienation from a fearsome god who seems radically other and remote, as in Hobbes, or, when it is the god of one's own reason, as in Rousseau, alienation of the empirical self, of one's particular will, from one's rational self, the general will.
    • In many early modern liberal theories the god of a civil religion was to exercise a substantial part of the coercive function. But that only drove the alienation deeper: either alienation from a fearsome god who seems radically other and remote, as in Hobbes, or, when it is the god of one's own reason, as in Rousseau, alienation of the empirical self, of one's particular will, from one's rational self, the general will.
  • 7
    • 85033047007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is, of course, possible to meld a certain historicist procedure with liberal rationalism, an example of which would be Ronald Dworkin's Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). But that is usually combined with a belief that liberal society is on the cutting edge of world-historic progress, either explicitly as in Kant's Perpetual Peace, or implicitly in Americans who take it for granted that their liberal legal order is the novus ordo seclorum as the reverse of the Great Seal of the United States has it.
    • It is, of course, possible to meld a certain historicist procedure with liberal rationalism, an example of which would be Ronald Dworkin's Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). But that is usually combined with a belief that liberal society is on the cutting edge of world-historic progress, either explicitly as in Kant's Perpetual Peace, or implicitly in Americans who take it for granted that their liberal legal order is the novus ordo seclorum as the reverse of the Great Seal of the United States has it.
  • 8
    • 85033055921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • References to the First Part of the Second Part of the Summa Theologica will be given in an abbreviated form in the text as follows: a full reference to I-II, q.' 95, art. 1, resp. will be abbreviated to 95.1 ; I-II, q. 95, art. 1, sed contra will be abbreviated to 95.1. sc; I-II, q. 95, art 1, obj. 2 will be abbreviated to 95.1.2; I-II, q. 95, art. 1, ad 2 will be abbreviated to 95.1. ad 2. References to other "parts" of the Summa Theologica will include the part number, for example, 1.96.4. Translations of Aquinas and others are our own.
    • References to the First Part of the Second Part of the Summa Theologica will be given in an abbreviated form in the text as follows: a full reference to I-II, q.' 95, art. 1, resp. will be abbreviated to 95.1 ; I-II, q. 95, art. 1, sed contra will be abbreviated to 95.1. sc; I-II, q. 95, art 1, obj. 2 will be abbreviated to 95.1.2; I-II, q. 95, art. 1, ad 2 will be abbreviated to 95.1. ad 2. References to other "parts" of the Summa Theologica will include the part number, for example, 1.96.4. Translations of Aquinas and others are our own.
  • 9
    • 85033056282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rationis ordinatio." An ordinatio is an ordinance in the sense of an ordering or arrangement. In the process of working dialectically toward his final definition, Thomas also calls it a "rule and measure of human acts" (90. 1), "a dictate of reason" (92. 1), or "some sort of reason directive of acts to an end" (93.3).
    • "Rationis ordinatio." An ordinatio is an ordinance in the sense of an ordering or arrangement. In the process of working dialectically toward his final definition, Thomas also calls it a "rule and measure of human acts" (90. 1), "a dictate of reason" (92. 1), or "some sort of reason directive of acts to an end" (93.3).
  • 10
    • 85033058447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas's prudentialism extends to the observation of rational laws as well. If there is a particular case where observance would damage the common welfare and safety, the law is not to be observed (96.1. ad 3). That may lead to lawlessness. So he poses a strong qualification: only those with authority to override the law are to apply the principle, except when the danger is so sudden as to preclude recourse to that authority (96.6). That qualification, in turn, applies only in cases where there is a political authority aiming at the common welfare, rather than a tyranny whose acts are politically irrational.
    • Thomas's prudentialism extends to the observation of rational laws as well. If there is a particular case where observance would damage the common welfare and safety, the law is not to be observed (96.1. ad 3). That may lead to lawlessness. So he poses a strong qualification: only those with authority to override the law are to apply the principle, except when the danger is so sudden as to preclude recourse to that authority (96.6). That qualification, in turn, applies only in cases where there is a political authority aiming at the common welfare, rather than a tyranny whose acts are politically irrational.
  • 11
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 241, 245-6, 303, 315, 351, 391, 577. The coincidence of approaches is amusing, given Rawls's evident distaste for Aquinas at 553-4.
    • A Theory of Justice , vol.241 , pp. 245-246
    • Rawls1
  • 13
    • 85033059837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our aim is only to explicate St. Thomas's theory. So we do not offer an interpretation of St. Augustine's view. But note, Thomas finds citations from Augustine to support his own view (e.g., 1.96.4).
    • Our aim is only to explicate St. Thomas's theory. So we do not offer an interpretation of St. Augustine's view. But note, Thomas finds citations from Augustine to support his own view (e.g., 1.96.4).
  • 14
    • 33750526265 scopus 로고
    • His terms are "oeconomica out civilis." For a detailed discussion of the terminology, see the dispute between R. A. Markus "Two Conceptions of Political Authority,"
    • His terms are "oeconomica out civilis." For a detailed discussion of the terminology, see the dispute between R. A. Markus ("Two Conceptions of Political Authority," Journal of Tlieological Studies n.s., 16 [1965]: 68-100);
    • (1965) Journal of Tlieological Studies N.s. , vol.16 , pp. 68-100
  • 15
    • 0040117670 scopus 로고
    • Augustine and Aquinas on Original Sin and the Function of Political Authority
    • We are indebted for these references to Jeanne M. Heffeman.
    • and Paul J. Weithman ("Augustine and Aquinas on Original Sin and the Function of Political Authority," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 [1992]: 353-76). We are indebted for these references to Jeanne M. Heffeman.
    • (1992) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.30 , pp. 353-376
    • Weithman, P.J.1
  • 16
    • 85033060391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Aristotle, The Constitution of Athens, xliii. 1; Ixi. Rawls, like most liberals, simply assumes that there is to be a government of elected officials without considering whether the division of political power ought not be the subject of the first principle of justice. Only a theory of justice essentially constructed for subjects rather than citizens would omit consideration of this most political subject.
    • See Aristotle, The Constitution of Athens, xliii. 1; Ixi. Rawls, like most liberals, simply assumes that there is to be a government of elected officials without considering whether the division of political power ought not be the subject of the first principle of justice. Only a theory of justice essentially constructed for subjects rather than citizens would omit consideration of this most political subject.
  • 18
    • 85033060275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.96.4, citing Augustine, De Civilaie Dei xix. 15.
    • 1.96.4, citing Augustine, De Civilaie Dei xix. 15.
  • 19
    • 85033037588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Like Aristotle and unlike most social contractarians, Thomas lays great stress on the moral value of friendship (amicitia as the love of mutual benevolence in a common conversation of deed and word and as the culminating consequence of all the moral virtues) and ties it to equity (epieikeia) as the highest form of justice (II-II. 23; II-II. 80.1. ad 2 and 3; II-II. 114; 1I-II. 120).
    • Like Aristotle and unlike most social contractarians, Thomas lays great stress on the moral value of friendship (amicitia as the love of mutual benevolence in a common conversation of deed and word and as the culminating consequence of all the moral virtues) and ties it to equity (epieikeia) as the highest form of justice (II-II. 23; II-II. 80.1. ad 2 and 3; II-II. 114; 1I-II. 120).
  • 20
    • 85033052726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 21.4. ad 3; II-II. 58.5,58.7 ad 2,61.1. ad 2,179-82.
    • See 21.4. ad 3; II-II. 58.5,58.7 ad 2,61.1. ad 2,179-82.
  • 21
    • 85033068488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He uses this term repeatedly. 1.18.2. ad 2,115.4; HI. 35.5. sc., 65.5,91.4,101.4 and ad 1 and 4,105.3,107.1; II-II. 23.1. ad 1,26. 8,114.1,145.1. ad 3,145.2,168.2.
    • He uses this term repeatedly. 1.18.2. ad 2,115.4; HI. 35.5. sc., 65.5,91.4,101.4 and ad 1 and 4,105.3,107.1; II-II. 23.1. ad 1,26. 8,114.1,145.1. ad 3,145.2,168.2.
  • 22
    • 85033039986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. 6.4; 9.4; 87.1; 93.5; 96.3-4; 97.3. ad 3; 1.96.4.
    • Cf. 6.4; 9.4; 87.1; 93.5; 96.3-4; 97.3. ad 3; 1.96.4.
  • 23
    • 85033043428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas also thinks there is one best constitutional order, monarchy, but it is at the level of God's governance of the universe. In human affairs, the requisite unity of order may be achieved under a number of constitutional arrangements, the excellence of which will vary according to circumstances (1.103.3; HI. 90.3.; 95.2. ad 3 and 4; 96.1. ad 3; 96.2. and ad 2; 96.6).
    • Thomas also thinks there is one best constitutional order, monarchy, but it is at the level of God's governance of the universe. In human affairs, the requisite unity of order may be achieved under a number of constitutional arrangements, the excellence of which will vary according to circumstances (1.103.3; HI. 90.3.; 95.2. ad 3 and 4; 96.1. ad 3; 96.2. and ad 2; 96.6).
  • 24
    • 85033035782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HI. 92. 2. 1. He gives the traditional list of Roman law: Digest I. iii. 7 and Gratian, Decretum, I. iii. 4.
    • HI. 92. 2. 1. He gives the traditional list of Roman law: Digest I. iii. 7 and Gratian, Decretum, I. iii. 4.
  • 25
    • 85033047178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 90.3. ad 2; 92.1. ad 2 and 3; 93.4 and ad 4; 93.6; 95.1 and ad 1; 96.5; 105.4. ad 5; IHI. 64.3.
    • See 90.3. ad 2; 92.1. ad 2 and 3; 93.4 and ad 4; 93.6; 95.1 and ad 1; 96.5; 105.4. ad 5; IHI. 64.3.
  • 26
    • 85033064011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Supra, n. 2.
    • Supra, n. 2.
  • 27
    • 84972623105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One thinks of Kant's race of intelligent devils (Perpetual Peace, First Supplement, 1. [B61; A60]). They are still around as the fictional folks in the "original position," choosing principles of justice under the "maximin rule" (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 150 ff.). Or they may be the actual folks of "political liberalism" who are reasonably scared by the religious wars at the end of the Middle Ages (Charles Larmore, "Political Liberalism," Political Theory 18 [1990]: 340,352; John Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], 159).
    • One thinks of Kant's race of intelligent devils (Perpetual Peace, First Supplement, 1. [B61; A60]). They are still around as the fictional folks in the "original position," choosing principles of justice under the "maximin rule" (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 150 ff.). Or they may be the actual folks of "political liberalism" who are reasonably scared by the religious wars at the end of the Middle Ages (Charles Larmore, "Political Liberalism," Political Theory 18 [1990]: 340,352; John Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], 159).
  • 28
    • 85033039210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I may internalize a law even when the rational process whereby it was chosen was not my own but that of another, the legislator/legislature. In this sense I remain subject to another. Nevertheless, I am not the subject of another in a different sense: freely choosing to be subject to that authority I make its laws my own.
    • I may internalize a law even when the rational process whereby it was chosen was not my own but that of another, the legislator/legislature. In this sense I remain subject to another. Nevertheless, I am not the subject of another in a different sense: freely choosing to be subject to that authority I make its laws my own.
  • 29
    • 85033037619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Paris: Gallimard, 1959-), 368, bk. 2, chap. 1, par. 3 (translation by E. A. Goemcr). Cf. bk. 1, chap. 7, par. 7.
    • Jean-Jacques Rousseau, On the Social Contract, vol. 3 of Oeuvres complètes (Paris: Gallimard, 1959-), 368, bk. 2, chap. 1, par. 3 (translation by E. A. Goemcr). Cf. bk. 1, chap. 7, par. 7.
    • On the Social Contract, Vol. 3 of Oeuvres Complètes , vol.3
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 30
    • 85033071652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The penalties may, of course, be partly psychological, and Rawls clearly relies heavily on this fact in arguing for the rationality of acting justly (A Theory of Justice, pt. HI, esp. 570 ff.). But one's merely psychological bent has no intrinsic normative status, and a "theory of rational choice" needs to ask whether bearing the costs of reshaping one's psychological responses so as to enjoy injustice is rational.
    • The penalties may, of course, be partly psychological, and Rawls clearly relies heavily on this fact in arguing for the rationality of acting justly (A Theory of Justice, pt. HI, esp. 570 ff.). But one's merely psychological bent has no intrinsic normative status, and a "theory of rational choice" needs to ask whether bearing the costs of reshaping one's psychological responses so as to enjoy injustice is rational.
  • 31
    • 85033044356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau, On the Social Contract, bk. 3, chap. 10.
    • Rousseau, On the Social Contract, bk. 3, chap. 10.
  • 34
    • 85033035363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas thinks one cannot lay down a universal rule about breaking bad customs by adopting contrary statutes. If the attempt fails, it may bring all law into disrespect (think of the prohibition amendment).
    • Thomas thinks one cannot lay down a universal rule about breaking bad customs by adopting contrary statutes. If the attempt fails, it may bring all law into disrespect (think of the prohibition amendment).
  • 35
    • 85033053810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Politics i. 1253a 30-2; and St. Thomas Aquinas, In Octo Libras Politicorum Aristotelis Expositio, I. i.
    • Aristotle, Politics i. 1253a 30-2; and St. Thomas Aquinas, In Octo Libras Politicorum Aristotelis Expositio, I. i.
  • 36
    • 85033066214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant might claim there was a politics that treated the subject as ends by invoking a kind of residual teleology, claiming that living in accord with universalizable rational laws was the ultimate end of the noumenal self. Modern liberals no longer try to demonstrate that.
    • Kant might claim there was a politics that treated the subject as ends by invoking a kind of residual teleology, claiming that living in accord with universalizable rational laws was the ultimate end of the noumenal self. Modern liberals no longer try to demonstrate that.
  • 39
    • 85033037897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls tried to overcome some of the radical individualism by envisaging the society as a "union of social unions" (A Theory of Justice, 527). But the component "social unions" are not political, not allowed to organize a particular kind of life within a common space. The common . space is that of the society as a whole from which no one and no manner of life may be excluded or publicly held in scorn.
    • Rawls tried to overcome some of the radical individualism by envisaging the society as a "union of social unions" (A Theory of Justice, 527). But the component "social unions" are not political, not allowed to organize a particular kind of life within a common space. The common . space is that of the society as a whole from which no one and no manner of life may be excluded or publicly held in scorn.
  • 40
    • 85033043876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the "Declaration of Religious Freedom" issued by the Second Vatican Council (The Documents of Vatican II, ed. Walter M. Abbott, S. J. [New York: Herder and Herder; Association Press, 1966], 672-700). See also Catechism of the Catholic Church (Washington, DC: United States Catholic Conference, 1994), §§160,1782,1738,1906-17,2104-9,2244.
    • See the "Declaration of Religious Freedom" issued by the Second Vatican Council (The Documents of Vatican II, ed. Walter M. Abbott, S. J. [New York: Herder and Herder; Association Press, 1966], 672-700). See also Catechism of the Catholic Church (Washington, DC: United States Catholic Conference, 1994), §§160,1782,1738,1906-17,2104-9,2244.
  • 41
    • 85033052086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In contrast to Political Liberalism, A Theory of Justice (215 ff.) is unprepared to find acceptable theological principles or other comprehensive doctrines of Aquinas and others even if they permit what, to Rawls, seems like a merely prudential check on political intolerance of heretical views and practices.
    • In contrast to Political Liberalism, A Theory of Justice (215 ff.) is unprepared to find acceptable theological principles or other comprehensive doctrines of Aquinas and others even if they permit what, to Rawls, seems like a merely prudential check on political intolerance of heretical views and practices.
  • 42
    • 85033054404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pope Gelasius I, in a fifth-century dispute with the Roman Emperor Zeno, wrote that "Christ, mindful of human weakness and of what suited the welfare of his people,"- separated the office of Emperor from that of bishops, "willing that his people be saved by humility lest human pride throw them back from the goal" (Tractatus iv. 11). Thus, "two there are, August Emperor, [rather than one, the Emperor or the Pope] by which this world is chiefly ruled: the sacred authority of the Pontiff and the Royal power" (Epistolae xii. 2).
    • Pope Gelasius I, in a fifth-century dispute with the Roman Emperor Zeno, wrote that "Christ, mindful of human weakness and of what suited the welfare of his people,"- separated the office of Emperor from that of bishops, "willing that his people be saved by humility lest human pride throw them back from the goal" (Tractatus iv. 11). Thus, "two there are, August Emperor, [rather than one, the Emperor or the Pope] by which this world is chiefly ruled: the sacred authority of the Pontiff and the Royal power" (Epistolae xii. 2).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.