메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 60, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 661-683

Rousseau on self-love: What we've learned, what we might have learned

(1)  Cooper, Laurence D a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 1842746894     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500050841     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (54)
  • 1
    • 77954059503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau of course was not the first to defend self-love. Indeed, the celebration of self-love and pride had been central to classical moral philosophy and had been a source of its critique of Christianity (as well as a source of Christianity's critique of it). But much of Rousseau's defense of self-love was original-most particularly his insistence on the perfect innocence and sufficiency of original self-love and the claim that it is the source of compassion. And it is precisely these elements, and not the more stringent classical teaching, that seem to me to predominate in the contemporary rehabilitation of self-love
    • Rousseau of course was not the first to defend self-love. Indeed, the celebration of self-love and pride had been central to classical moral philosophy and had been a source of its critique of Christianity (as well as a source of Christianity's critique of it). But much of Rousseau's defense of self-love was original-most particularly his insistence on the perfect innocence and sufficiency of original self-love and the claim that it is the source of compassion. And it is precisely these elements, and not the more stringent classical teaching, that seem to me to predominate in the contemporary rehabilitation of self-love.
  • 2
    • 77954076097 scopus 로고
    • Rousseau of course was not the first to defend self-love. Indeed, the celebration of self-love and pride had been central to classical moral philosophy and had been a source of its critique of Christianity (as well as a source of Christianity's critique of it). But much of Rousseau's defense of self-love was original-most particularly his insistence on the perfect innocence and sufficiency of original self-love and the claim that it is the source of compassion. And it is precisely these elements, and not the more stringent classical teaching, that seem to me to predominate in the contemporary rehabilitation of self-love. "the familiar and widely accepted account", [Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers], (The work which presents Rousseau's comprehensive, balanced view of amour-propre is Emile, a work which unfortunately is much less well known than either the Second Discourse or the Social Contract. It is from Emile that the bulk of the ensuing argument is drawn.)
    • Rousseau of course was not the first to defend self-love. Indeed, the celebration of self-love and pride had been central to classical moral philosophy and had been a source of its critique of Christianity (as well as a source of Christianity's critique of it). But much of Rousseau's defense of self-love was original-most particularly his insistence on the perfect innocence and sufficiency of original self-love and the claim that it is the source of compassion. And it is precisely these elements, and not the more stringent classical teaching, that seem to me to predominate in the contemporary rehabilitation of self-love. "the familiar and widely accepted account" (A Rousseau Dictionary [Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1992], pp. 33-34). (The work which presents Rousseau's comprehensive, balanced view of amour-propre is Emile, a work which unfortunately is much less well known than either the Second Discourse or the Social Contract. It is from Emile that the bulk of the ensuing argument is drawn.)
    • (1992) A Rousseau Dictionary , pp. 33-34
  • 3
    • 77954080941 scopus 로고
    • For examples of what in my view are overly harsh interpretations of Rousseau's amour-propre, see, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), and 85
    • For examples of what in my view are overly harsh interpretations of Rousseau's amour-propre, see John Charvet, The Social Problem in Rousseau's Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974), pp. 69 and 85
    • (1974) The Social Problem in Rousseau's Philosophy , pp. 69
    • Charvet, J.1
  • 4
    • 0039651659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Toronto: University of Toronto Press)
    • and Asher Horowitz, Rousseau, Nature, and History (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1987), p. 93.
    • (1987) Rousseau Nature, and History , pp. 93
    • Horowitz, A.1
  • 6
    • 84974115097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • Second Discourse , Ibid., pp. 146-7.
    • Second Discourse , pp. 146-147
  • 8
    • 84974115097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. 151
    • Second Discourse, Ibid., pp. 149,151.
    • Second Discourse , pp. 149
  • 9
    • 0004327677 scopus 로고
    • trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books), HI
    • Emile, or on Education, trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979), HI: 205.
    • (1979) Emile, or on Education , pp. 205
  • 10
    • 77954049279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A qualification: The happiness that Emile possesses is the greatest available to "ordinary minds." That which is available to someone with the natural gifts of Rousseau himself, the happiness described in the late autobiographical writings, would seem to be the greatest of all
    • A qualification: The happiness that Emile possesses is the greatest available to "ordinary minds." That which is available to someone with the natural gifts of Rousseau himself, the happiness described in the late autobiographical writings, would seem to be the greatest of all.
  • 11
    • 77954082211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue is always the servant of abstract principle: Rousseau defines it as "obedience to law" (On the Social Contract, in On the Social Contract with Geneva Manuscript and Political Economy, ed. Roger D. Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters [New York: St. Martin's Press, 1978], 1. 8. 56), or conforming to the general will (Discourse on Political Economy, in Masters and Masters, On the Social Contract, p. 218)
    • Virtue is always the servant of abstract principle: Rousseau defines it as "obedience to law" (On the Social Contract, in On the Social Contract with Geneva Manuscript and Political Economy, ed. Roger D. Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters [New York: St. Martin's Press, 1978], 1. 8. 56), or conforming to the general will (Discourse on Political Economy, in Masters and Masters, On the Social Contract, p. 218).
  • 12
    • 77954079193 scopus 로고
    • 4 vols. (Paris: Gallimard, Bibliotheque de la Peiade), The desire for recognition would seem to be a nearly universal source of motivation. Even the wise man "is not insensitive to glory" (First Discourse, in Master and Master, First and Second Discourses, p. 58)
    • Fragments Politique, in Oeuvres Completes, 4 vols. (Paris: Gallimard, Bibliotheque de la Peiade, 1959-1969), vol 3, p. 501. The desire for recognition would seem to be a nearly universal source of motivation. Even the wise man "is not insensitive to glory" (First Discourse, in Master and Master, First and Second Discourses, p. 58).
    • (1959) Oeuvres Completes , vol.3 , pp. 501
    • Politique, F.1
  • 13
    • 77954068354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau's insistence on self-love as the psychological basis of virtue reveals the eudaimonistic cast of his moral thought and hence its distance from Kantian moral philosophy
    • Rousseau's insistence on self-love as the psychological basis of virtue reveals the eudaimonistic cast of his moral thought and hence its distance from Kantian moral philosophy.
  • 14
    • 77954046990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Emile, IV: 317
    • See Emile, IV: 317.
  • 15
    • 77954067860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., IV: 221-231
    • Ibid., IV: 221-231
  • 16
    • 0039651659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., IV: 229, emphasis added. That amour-propre plays such an important role in inculcating pity does not alter the fact that the source of pity, i.e., the "stuff" of which it is made, is amour de soi. Amour-propre's role is that of buttress and facilitator. Others have made the same general point, albeit with different notions of the particulars. See, for example
    • Ibid., IV: 229, emphasis added. That amour-propre plays such an important role in inculcating pity does not alter the fact that the source of pity, i.e., the "stuff" of which it is made, is amour de soi. Amour-propre's role is that of buttress and facilitator. Others have made the same general point, albeit with different notions of the particulars. See, for example, Horowitz, Rousseau, Nature, and History, p. 237
    • Rousseau, Nature, and History , pp. 237
    • Horowitz1
  • 18
    • 77954075239 scopus 로고
    • The confessions
    • See, for example, ed. Christopher Kelly, Roger D. Masters, and Peter S. Stillman and trans. Christopher Kelly (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England), VI, where Rousseau explains one such incident as follows: "pride might perhaps have as great a part in my resolution as virtue; but if this pride is not virtue itself it has such similar effects that it is pardonable to mistake it for virtue." The incident in question is one in which Rousseau was inspired by amour-propre (in the form of pride) to pass up a rather seamy assignation. Beyond such instances as this, Rousseau claims that amour-propre produced in him a moral transformation of nearly six years' duration. He refers to the years 1749 to 1754 or 1755 (during which time he wrote both Discourses and conceived of his entire philosophic system) as a period in which "the noblest pride sprang up on the ruins of uprooted vanity"(IX:350)
    • See, for example, The Confessions, in The Collected Writings of Rousseau, vol.5, ed. Christopher Kelly, Roger D. Masters, and Peter S. Stillman and trans. Christopher Kelly (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1986), VI: 218, where Rousseau explains one such incident as follows: "pride might perhaps have as great a part in my resolution as virtue; but if this pride is not virtue itself it has such similar effects that it is pardonable to mistake it for virtue." The incident in question is one in which Rousseau was inspired by amour-propre (in the form of pride) to pass up a rather seamy assignation. Beyond such instances as this, Rousseau claims that amour-propre produced in him a moral transformation of nearly six years' duration. He refers to the years 1749 to 1754 or 1755 (during which time he wrote both Discourses and conceived of his entire philosophic system) as a period in which "the noblest pride sprang up on the ruins of uprooted vanity"(IX:350).
    • (1986) The Collected Writings of Rousseau , vol.5 , pp. 218
  • 19
    • 0003459483 scopus 로고
    • For a different and somewhat harsher view of amour-propre''s role in this moral transformation, see, (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press)
    • For a different and somewhat harsher view of amour-propre''s role in this moral transformation, see Carol Blum, Rousseau and the Republic of Virtue (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986), pp. 4CM3.
    • (1986) Rousseau and the Republic of Virtue
    • Blum, C.1
  • 20
    • 77954050955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emile IV: 264
    • Emile, IV: 264.
  • 21
    • 77954069336 scopus 로고
    • trans. Charles E. Butterworth (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company), emphasis added
    • Reveries of a Solitary Walker, trans. Charles E. Butterworth (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1992), VIII: 115-116, emphasis added.
    • (1992) Reveries of A Solitary Walker , vol.8 , pp. 115-116
  • 22
    • 0010066168 scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of Rousseau's views of Cato and Socrates and how they compare to himself, see, (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), and 64-75
    • For a discussion of Rousseau's views of Cato and Socrates and how they compare to himself, see Christopher Kelly, Rousseau's Exemplary Life: The Confessions as Political Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987), pp. 50-57 and 64-75.
    • (1987) Rousseau's Exemplary Life: The Confessions As Political Philosophy , pp. 50-57
    • Kelly, C.1
  • 23
    • 77954046989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This fragment appears in Jean-facques entre Socrate et Caton, ed. Claude Pichois and Rene Pintard (Paris: Jose Corti, 1972), p. 54
    • This fragment appears in Jean-facques entre Socrate et Caton, ed. Claude Pichois and Rene Pintard (Paris: Jose Corti, 1972), p. 54.
  • 24
    • 0007342483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for further discussion of the necessity of amour-propre for moral action. Melzer interprets Rousseau's authorial activity in this light
    • See Melzer, Natural Goodness of Man, pp. 256-261, for further discussion of the necessity of amour-propre for moral action. Melzer interprets Rousseau's authorial activity in this light.
    • Natural Goodness of Man , pp. 256-261
    • Melzer1
  • 25
    • 77954074024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Constitutional Project for Corsica, in The Collected Political Writings of Rousseau, trans, and ed. Frederick Watkins (Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1986), pp. 25-29
    • See Constitutional Project for Corsica, in The Collected Political Writings of Rousseau, trans, and ed. Frederick Watkins (Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1986), pp. 25-29.
  • 26
    • 0004056310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is explicitly advised in Corsica is implicitly advised elsewhere. As Ruth Grant observes, "Rousseau hopes to use pride precisely in order to inculcate integrity", [Chicago: University of Chicago Press], Indeed, the inculcation of pride as a source of public-spiritedness can be seen as the centerpiece of the civic ethos, i.e., as the key to successful republicanism, in Rousseau's view
    • What is explicitly advised in Corsica is implicitly advised elsewhere. As Ruth Grant observes, "Rousseau hopes to use pride precisely in order to inculcate integrity" (Hypocrisy and Integrity: Machiavelli, Rousseau, and the Ethics of Politics [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997], p. 167). Indeed, the inculcation of pride as a source of public-spiritedness can be seen as the centerpiece of the civic ethos, i.e., as the key to successful republicanism, in Rousseau's view
    • (1997) Hypocrisy and Integrity: Machiavelli, Rousseau, and the Ethics of Politics , pp. 167
  • 27
    • 0003637252 scopus 로고
    • As Judith Shklar writes, "The civic ethos . . . redirects amourpropre from pursuing personal exploitation to positive public enterprises. The whole political structure of Sparta has no other end", [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press]
    • As Judith Shklar writes, "The civic ethos . . . redirects amourpropre from pursuing personal exploitation to positive public enterprises. The whole political structure of Sparta has no other end" (Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969], p. 19)
    • (1969) Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory , pp. 19
  • 28
    • 77954065150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corsica, p. 326.
    • Corsica , pp. 326
  • 29
    • 77954072998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even in the later writings the distinction is not maintained with perfect consistency. See note 28 below
    • Even in the later writings the distinction is not maintained with perfect consistency. See note 28 below.
  • 30
    • 77954049278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emile IV: 215
    • Emile, IV: 215.
  • 31
    • 77954065396 scopus 로고
    • "I do not accuse the men of this century of having all the vices; they have only the vices of cowardly souls; they are only rogues and knaves" {Last Reply by /.-/. Rousseau of Geneva [to Bordes], trans, and ed. Victor Gourevitch [New York: Harper & Row], "Vile and cowardly even in their vices, they have only small souls" (Emile, IV: 335)
    • "I do not accuse the men of this century of having all the vices; they have only the vices of cowardly souls; they are only rogues and knaves" {Last Reply by /.-/. Rousseau of Geneva [to Bordes], in The First and Second Discourses Together with the Replies to Critics and Essay on the Origin of Languages, trans, and ed. Victor Gourevitch [New York: Harper & Row, 1990], p. 72). "Vile and cowardly even in their vices, they have only small souls" (Emile, IV: 335).
    • (1990) The First and Second Discourses Together with the Replies to Critics and Essay on the Origin of Languages , pp. 72
  • 32
    • 77954050497 scopus 로고
    • See, for example, (London: Longman Group, Limited)
    • See, for example, John Plamenatz, Man and Society, vol.2 (London: Longman Group, Limited, 1963), pp. 420-423
    • (1963) Man and Society , vol.2 , pp. 420-423
    • Plamenatz, J.1
  • 33
    • 77954055761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Admittedly, Rousseau is not perfectly consistent in his use of the terms pride and vanity. What he lacks in semantic consistency, however, is largely made up by conceptual consistency. That is, it is possible to discern what kinds of amourpropre he approves of and what kinds he does not, and why-and it is that distinction which matters most. (Even Plamenatz, who complains that Rousseau is unclear on the distinction, admits that Rousseau "might have distinguished vanity from pride, if he had ever troubled to do so" [Man and Society, pp. 420-23].)
    • Admittedly, Rousseau is not perfectly consistent in his use of the terms pride and vanity. What he lacks in semantic consistency, however, is largely made up by conceptual consistency. That is, it is possible to discern what kinds of amourpropre he approves of and what kinds he does not, and why-and it is that distinction which matters most. (Even Plamenatz, who complains that Rousseau is unclear on the distinction, admits that Rousseau "might have distinguished vanity from pride, if he had ever troubled to do so" [Man and Society, pp. 420-23].)
  • 34
    • 77954070947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corsica, p. 236.
    • Corsica , pp. 236
  • 35
    • 77954074487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid..
  • 36
    • 77954041476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Confessions, I: 21
    • See Confessions, I: 21.
  • 37
    • 77954060443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One who, like Emile, "does not stop at appearances but judges the happiness of men only by the condition of their hearts will see their miseries in their very successes; he will see their desires and their gnawing cares extend and increase with their fortune; he will see them getting out of breath in advancing without ever reaching their goals" (Emile, IV: 242)
    • One who, like Emile, "does not stop at appearances but judges the happiness of men only by the condition of their hearts will see their miseries in their very successes; he will see their desires and their gnawing cares extend and increase with their fortune; he will see them getting out of breath in advancing without ever reaching their goals" (Emile, IV: 242).
  • 38
    • 77954066083 scopus 로고
    • Machiavelli's confidence in our ability-or at least his ability-to discern the respective roles of skill and fortune is evident from the title of chapter 25 of The Prince:, (Prince, trans. Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr. [Chicago: University of Chicago Press])
    • Machiavelli's confidence in our ability-or at least his ability-to discern the respective roles of skill and fortune is evident from the title of chapter 25 of The Prince: "How Much Fortune Can Do in Human Affairs, and in What Mode It May Be Opposed" (Prince, trans. Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr. [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985]).
    • (1985) How Much Fortune Can Do in Human Affairs, and in What Mode It May Be Opposed
  • 39
    • 77954050025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Rousseau's characterization of conscience's dictates as perfect and universal see Emile, IV: 290 and V: 382
    • For Rousseau's characterization of conscience's dictates as perfect and universal see Emile, IV: 290 and V: 382
  • 41
    • 77954075483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emile IV: 339
    • Emile, IV: 339.
  • 42
    • 77954045738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p, 245
    • Ibid., p, 245.
  • 43
    • 77954040979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid..
  • 44
    • 77954081751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., V: 402-05
    • Ibid., V: 402-05.
  • 45
    • 77954053178 scopus 로고
    • For the discussion of Alceste, the title character of the Misanthrope, see, trans. Allan Bloom in Politics and the Arts (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press)
    • For the discussion of Alceste, the title character of the Misanthrope, see Letter to M. d'Alembert on the Theater, trans. Allan Bloom in Politics and the Arts (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1968), pp. 34-45.
    • (1968) Letter to M. d'Alembert on the Theater , pp. 34-45
  • 46
    • 77954063696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The three versions are: virtuous citizenship in an austere republic; the life of solitary contemplation depicted in the Reveries of the Solitary Walker; and the life of Emile, described as "the natural man living in the state of society" (Emile, III: 205). Rousseau expresses admiration for various other lives, but he does so only to the extent that those lives partake of one of these three ideals
    • The three versions are: virtuous citizenship in an austere republic; the life of solitary contemplation depicted in the Reveries of the Solitary Walker; and the life of Emile, described as "the natural man living in the state of society" (Emile, III: 205). Rousseau expresses admiration for various other lives, but he does so only to the extent that those lives partake of one of these three ideals.
  • 47
    • 77954066580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Reveries, VIII: 117-18 and Rousseau, judge of Jean-Jacques: Dialogues in The Collected Writings of Rousseau, vol.1, ed. Roger D. Masters and Christopher Kelly and trans. Judith R. Bush, Christopher Kelly, and Roger D. Masters (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1990), II: 106
    • See Reveries, VIII: 117-18 and Rousseau, judge of Jean-Jacques: Dialogues in The Collected Writings of Rousseau, vol.1, ed. Roger D. Masters and Christopher Kelly and trans. Judith R. Bush, Christopher Kelly, and Roger D. Masters (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1990), II: 106.
  • 48
    • 77954051992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emile "is a new system of education the plan of which I present for the study of the wise and not a method for fathers and mothers" (Oeuvres Completes, III: 783)
    • Emile "is a new system of education the plan of which I present for the study of the wise and not a method for fathers and mothers" (Oeuvres Completes, III: 783).
  • 49
    • 77954053179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such steps toward civilized naturalness are specified in the Lettres morales. The Lettres, ostensibly addressed to the Comtesse d'Houdetot and written at her request, offer specific instructions aimed at achieving a more natural life
    • Such steps toward civilized naturalness are specified in the Lettres morales. The Lettres, ostensibly addressed to the Comtesse d'Houdetot and written at her request, offer specific instructions aimed at achieving a more natural life.
  • 51
    • 84974115097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. 45. I am indebted to Kelly on this point
    • Second Discourse, Ibid., p. 222. 45. I am indebted to Kelly on this point.
    • Second Discourse , pp. 222
  • 52
    • 77954080200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rousseau's Exemplary Life, pp. 98-99
    • See Rousseau's Exemplary Life, pp. 98-99.
  • 53
    • 77954054648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau concedes in the First Discourse that vanity has led to a certain amount of useful knowledge and invention. But it has led to far more harm than good. Nor can it serve-nor can any private vice serve-as the basis of a good social order. See the Preface to Narcissus, in Gourevitch, First and Second Discourses, pp. 104-106 Rousseau does seem to suggest that vanity could be used to greater advantage than it has been, however. "Vanity is the greatest spring of human conduct" (Corsica, p. 325). As such, it could be used by the wise legislator. Vanity could even be used against vanity, as it were: Rousseau advises that sumptuary laws could be made effective by the legislator who "make[s] simplicity a point of vanity"(Cors!C, p. 324)
    • Rousseau concedes in the First Discourse that vanity has led to a certain amount of useful knowledge and invention. But it has led to far more harm than good. Nor can it serve-nor can any private vice serve-as the basis of a good social order. See the Preface to Narcissus, in Gourevitch, First and Second Discourses, pp. 104-106 Rousseau does seem to suggest that vanity could be used to greater advantage than it has been, however. "Vanity is the greatest spring of human conduct" (Corsica, p. 325). As such, it could be used by the wise legislator. Vanity could even be used against vanity, as it were: Rousseau advises that sumptuary laws could be made effective by the legislator who "make[s] simplicity a point of vanity"(Cors!C, p. 324).
  • 54
    • 77954056013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corsica, p. 326
    • Corsica , pp. 326


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.