-
1
-
-
0003707688
-
-
New York: St. Martin's Press
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1982)
Nationalism and the State
, pp. 9
-
-
Breuilly, J.1
-
2
-
-
0004287948
-
-
New York: Holmes and Meier
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1983)
Theories of Nationalism, 2nd Ed.
, pp. 84
-
-
Smith, A.D.1
-
3
-
-
0003733447
-
-
Blackwell: Oxford
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1983)
Nations and Nationalism
, pp. 108-109
-
-
Gellner, E.1
-
4
-
-
0003434446
-
-
New York: Cambridge University Press
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1990)
Nations and Nationalism since 1780
, pp. 78
-
-
Hobsbawm, E.J.1
-
5
-
-
0003950449
-
-
New York: Basil Blackwell
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1986)
The Ethnic Origins of Nations
-
-
Smith, A.D.1
-
6
-
-
0004053831
-
-
Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1982)
Nations before Nationalism
-
-
Armstrong, J.A.1
-
7
-
-
0003771579
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1992)
Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity
-
-
Greenfeld, L.1
-
8
-
-
0003462380
-
-
New York: Verso/New Left Books
-
This is part of a larger project in which I examine similarities and differences in the development of national identity in Australia and the United States in a series of public events in each country. Until recently, the historical record that has been most salient in generating general accounts of nation formation included the emergence of the first European nation-states, the spread of national identity as a principle of political legitimacy in the nineteenth century, the mobilization of nationalist claims in anticolonial movements of the twentieth century, and the contemporary nationalist claims within industrialized polities. Influential theoretical overviews of this record emphasize, to different degrees, modernization, state-oriented politics, or the reconstruction of ethnic identifications, and settler countries are treated as peripheral cases, explicitly marginalized, or mentioned only as counterexamples to other theories. See, for example, John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1982), 9; Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 2nd ed. (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1983), 84, 183; Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Blackwell: Oxford, 1983), 108-9; or E. J. Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism Since 1780 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 78. Some recent work on nationalism has shown a shift in emphasis, returning to a more direct focus on accounting for meanings associated with national identities, rather than nationalist politics and policies, and does discuss less canonical cases; overviews representing this shift in concerns include those of Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986); John A. Armstrong, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1982); Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (New York: Verso/New Left Books, 1991). Anderson discusses "official nationalisms" (ch. 6).
-
(1991)
Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, Rev. Ed.
-
-
Anderson, B.1
-
9
-
-
84909157014
-
-
Thus, I ask here not how national identities formed in contrast to more particularistic status orders but how national identities were understood as they were mobilized in contrast with more local and cosmopolitan identities. Anderson and Greenfeld, although their arguments are otherwise very different, both contrast national identity with identities based on more particularistic status orders, as "the location of sovereignty within the people and the recognition of the fundamental equality among its various strata" or a "deep horizontal comradeship;" and they agree that the United States early possessed some national identity in this sense. See Greenfeld, Five Roads, 10, 402; Anderson, Imagined Communities, 7. Although both countries shared this liberal inheritance, the formation of specific national identities involved more than muting the political salience of status orders, as both Greenfeld and Anderson would recognize. Examining the development of national identity by contrast to more local and cosmopolitan identities helps to illuminate how two different national identities develop from similar, comparatively liberal origins.
-
Five Roads
, pp. 10
-
-
Greenfeld1
-
10
-
-
0004135073
-
-
Thus, I ask here not how national identities formed in contrast to more particularistic status orders but how national identities were understood as they were mobilized in contrast with more local and cosmopolitan identities. Anderson and Greenfeld, although their arguments are otherwise very different, both contrast national identity with identities based on more particularistic status orders, as "the location of sovereignty within the people and the recognition of the fundamental equality among its various strata" or a "deep horizontal comradeship;" and they agree that the United States early possessed some national identity in this sense. See Greenfeld, Five Roads, 10, 402; Anderson, Imagined Communities, 7. Although both countries shared this liberal inheritance, the formation of specific national identities involved more than muting the political salience of status orders, as both Greenfeld and Anderson would recognize. Examining the development of national identity by contrast to more local and cosmopolitan identities helps to illuminate how two different national identities develop from similar, comparatively liberal origins.
-
Imagined Communities
, pp. 7
-
-
Anderson1
-
11
-
-
0008990255
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, passim
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1964)
Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology
, pp. 71
-
-
Arieli, Y.1
-
12
-
-
0004257595
-
-
Toronto: Collier Books, 1944
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1967)
The Idea of Nationalism
, pp. 276-281
-
-
Kohn, H.1
-
13
-
-
0003883042
-
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
Nationalism
-
-
Greenfeld1
-
14
-
-
0040796694
-
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
Ethnic Origins
, pp. 216
-
-
Smith1
-
15
-
-
0003458041
-
-
New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1964)
The Founding of New Societies
-
-
Hartz, L.1
-
16
-
-
5844378077
-
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
Comments
, pp. 279-284
-
-
Hartz, L.1
-
17
-
-
5844427140
-
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
Conflicts Within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition
, pp. 274-278
-
-
Jaffa, H.V.1
-
18
-
-
5844374742
-
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
A View from a Farther Shore
, pp. 269-273
-
-
Krieger, L.1
-
19
-
-
5844349323
-
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal
, pp. 261-268
-
-
Myers, M.1
-
20
-
-
5844331732
-
-
April
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture
-
(1963)
Comparative Studies in Society and History
, vol.5
, Issue.3
-
-
-
21
-
-
5844331730
-
Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society
-
Winter
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1985)
Daedalus
, vol.114
, pp. 146-149
-
-
Collins, H.1
-
22
-
-
60949961754
-
Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1984)
Historical Studies
, vol.21
, pp. 85-104
-
-
Hirst, J.1
-
23
-
-
0004279642
-
-
Sydney: Allen and Unwin
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1988)
The Rise of Colonial Nationalism
-
-
Eddy, J.1
Schreuder, D.2
-
24
-
-
0004087165
-
-
New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1973J
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1979)
The First New Nation: The United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective
-
-
Lipset, S.M.1
-
25
-
-
85028863565
-
The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation
-
Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1973)
Essays on the American Revolution
, pp. 197-255
-
-
McLaughlin, W.G.1
-
26
-
-
5744219784
-
-
Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1992)
Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805
-
-
Sandoz, E.1
-
27
-
-
0003594310
-
-
Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1991)
Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology
-
-
Olson, L.C.1
-
28
-
-
0003455289
-
-
Sydney: George Allen and Unwin
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1981)
Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980
-
-
White, R.1
-
29
-
-
84971790231
-
Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought
-
July
-
On the identification with liberal political principles in the United States, see for example, Yehoshua Arieli, Individualism and Nationalism in American Ideology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), 71 and 1-89, passim: and Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (Toronto: Collier Books, 1967 [1944]), 276-81. Greenfeld, in Nationalism, develops Kohn's distinction between Eastern and Western, more ethnic and more liberal, nationalisms. Smith, in Ethnic Origins, 216, also contrasts the liberal, territorial basis of American national identity with more ethnic national identities but suggests that "a closer examination always reveals the ethnic core of civic nations . . . with their early pioneering and dominant (English or Spanish) culture in America, Australia, or Argentina, a culture that provided the myths and language of the would-be nation." If what was ethnic was, to colonists, quintessentially liberal, these are not, of course, mutually exclusive alternatives. Because of the liberal basis of these early identity claims, comparative studies of political culture cast further light on differences in national identity in the settler nations. See Louis Hartz et al., The Founding of New Societies (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1964); four articles (Louis Hartz, "Comments," 279-84; Harry V. Jaffa, "Conflicts within the Idea of the Liberal Tradition," 274-8; Leonard Krieger, "A View from a Farther Shore," 269-73; and Marvin Myers, "Louis Hartz: The Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal," 261-8) in Comparative Studies in Society and History, 5:3 (April 1963). Australian developments of the Hartz thesis are discussed in Hugh Collins, "Political Ideology in a Benthamite Society," Daedalus, 114 (Winter 1985), 146-9; and John Hirst "Keeping Colonial History Colonial: The Hartz Thesis Revisited," Historical Studies, 21 (1984), 85-104. Other relevant comparative explorations of political culture include John Eddy and Deryck Schreuder, eds., The Rise of Colonial Nationalism (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 1988), and Seymour M. Lipset, The First New Nation: the United States in Comparative and Historical Perspective (New York: W. W. Norton and Co., 1979[1973J). that claims about the nation are likely to be those most familiar to delegates, preoccupied as they are with furthering other agendas. But while it is true that elites in both settler colonies did conceptualize their commonalities in terms of political values, something of what it means to be American or Australian at this time is likely to be missing. As I will note later, these contexts did not evoke much explicit concern about domestic others who might act as negative referents to the liberal national identities in the process of construction. It is also important to note that the local and the vernacular images of the nation, to the extent that they existed, are not represented here. McLaughlin, for example, argues for the importance of religious self-image in American identity: see William G. McLaughlin, "The Role of Religion in the Revolution: Liberty of Conscience and Cultural Cohesion in the New Nation," in Stephen G. Kurtz and James H. Hutson, eds., Essays on the American Revolution (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 197-255; and Ellis Sandoz, ed., Political Sermons of the American Founding Era: 1730-1805 (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1992). Broader evidence about how "all political factions in Britain and America . . . communicate[d] their ideas about the nature of American unity" is also assembled in Lester C. Olson, Emblems of American Community in the Revolutionary Era: A Study in Rhetorical Iconology (Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), xiv. A broader overview of Australian identity of the period, including the popular racism not directly captured in the conventions, is given in Richard White, Inventing Australia: Images and Identify 1608-1980 (Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1981). See also Susan Baggett Barham, "Conceptualizations of Women within Australian Egalitarian Thought," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 30:3 (July 1988), 483-510. In the course of her analysis Barham discusses important vernacular symbols of Australian national identity. But while there was certainly more to national identity than that evoked by the elite and technical context of the conventions, they do represent the most plausible claims about what defines the people which were available to political elites. These claims are significant because in neither case were vernacular claims about national identity directly influential at the time.
-
(1988)
Comparative Studies in Society and History
, vol.30
, Issue.3
, pp. 483-510
-
-
Barham, S.B.1
-
30
-
-
0003771544
-
-
Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1986)
Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788
-
-
Greene, J.P.1
-
31
-
-
5844325625
-
-
New York: Alfred A. Knopf
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1979)
The Beginnings of National Politics: An Interpretive History of the Continental Congress
-
-
Rakove, J.N.1
-
32
-
-
0003590084
-
-
New York: W. W. Norton
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1969)
The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787
-
-
Wood, G.S.1
-
33
-
-
0346884771
-
Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective
-
July
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1990)
William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3)
, vol.47
, Issue.3
, pp. 341-375
-
-
Onuf, P.S.1
-
34
-
-
5844384437
-
-
Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co.
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1907)
The Early Federation Movement of Australia
-
-
Allin, C.D.1
-
35
-
-
5844351179
-
-
Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1979)
The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography
-
-
Crisp, L.F.1
-
36
-
-
0004215939
-
-
Carlton: Melbourne University Press
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1972)
The Making of the Australian Constitution
-
-
La Nauze, J.A.1
-
37
-
-
0012041539
-
-
Melbourne: Oxford University Press
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1979)
A Constitutional History of Australia
-
-
McMinn, W.G.1
-
38
-
-
0011650322
-
-
Melbourne: Oxford University Press
-
Jack P. Greene discusses imperial and confederate examples in Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United States 1607-1788 (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1986). Jack N. Rakove, in The Beginnings of National Politics: an Interpretive History of the Continental Congress (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979) discusses the experience of confederacy. Gordon S. Wood, in The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) shows, inter alia, how natural the solution of a constitutional convention seemed Peter S. Onuf, "Reflections on the Founding: Constitutional Historiography in Bicentennial Perspective," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 47:3 July 1990, 341-75, suggests that continuities with state constitutions and political language were important in promoting the ratification of the Constitution. For previous attempts and precedents in Australian federation, see C. D. Allin, The Early Federation Movement of Australia, (Kingston, ON: Press of the British Whig Publishing Co., 1907); L. F. Crisp, The Later Australian Federation Movement 1883-1901: Outline and Bibliography (Canberra: Australian National University Research School of Social Sciences, 1979); J. A. La Nauze, The Making of the Australian Constitution (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1972); W. G. McMinn, A Constitutional History of Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1979); and Nationalism and Federalism in Australia (Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 1994).
-
(1994)
Nationalism and Federalism in Australia
-
-
-
39
-
-
0004152551
-
-
Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press,
-
(1985)
Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution
, pp. 166
-
-
McDonald, F.1
-
40
-
-
5844323763
-
A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation
-
Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1986)
Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli
, pp. 243-261
-
-
Greene, J.P.1
-
41
-
-
0004335526
-
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
Peripheries and Center
, pp. 162-163
-
-
Greene1
-
42
-
-
37949032337
-
Identity in British America. Unease in Eden
-
Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1987)
Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800
, pp. 115-157
-
-
Zuckerman, M.1
-
43
-
-
0003766728
-
-
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1966)
Symbols of American Community 1735-1775
-
-
Merrett, R.L.1
-
44
-
-
84962995456
-
The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1987)
Journal of Social History
, vol.21
, pp. 659-681
-
-
Hackett, D.G.1
-
45
-
-
5844371920
-
Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America
-
Spring
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1970)
Journal of Social History
, vol.3
, pp. 189-220
-
-
Greene, J.P.1
-
46
-
-
0010153024
-
A Roof Without Walls: The Dilemma of American National Identity
-
Richard Beeman et al., eds., Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1987)
Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity
, pp. 333-348
-
-
Murrin, J.M.1
-
47
-
-
5844419805
-
Introduction
-
Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1992)
Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason
, pp. 1-23
-
-
Pacheco, J.F.1
-
48
-
-
85050173615
-
Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution
-
July
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1962)
American Historical Review
, vol.67
, pp. 901-923
-
-
Savelle, M.1
-
49
-
-
0009906581
-
-
New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1922, ch. 2
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1960)
The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas
-
-
Becker, C.1
-
50
-
-
0003651959
-
-
Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1967)
The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution
-
-
Bailyn, B.1
-
51
-
-
0007365069
-
-
New York: Alfred A. Knopf
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1970)
The Origins of American Politics
-
-
-
52
-
-
5844349302
-
The American Revolution: The Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War
-
Kurtz and Hutson
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
American Revolution
, pp. 121-156
-
-
Shy, J.1
-
53
-
-
0004022114
-
-
New York: Russell and Russell
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1967)
The Roots of American Loyalty
-
-
Curti, M.1
-
54
-
-
0007077102
-
-
New York: Vintage Books
-
Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 166; Jack P. Greene, "A Fortuitous Convergence: Culture, Circumstance, and Contingency in the Emergence of the American Nation," in Religion, Ideology and Nationalism in Europe and America: Essays Presented in Honor of Yehoshua Arieli (Jerusalem: Historical Society for Israel and the Zalman Shazar Center for Jewish History, 1986), 243-61, at 259. See also Greene, Peripheries and Center, 162-3, and Michael Zuckerman, "Identity in British America. Unease in Eden," in Nicholas Canny and Anthony Pagden, eds., Colonial Identity in the Atlantic World 1500-1800 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 115-57. On the existence of an earlier sense of American national identity, see Richard L. Merrett, Symbols of American Community 1735-1775 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966); David G. Hackett, "The Social Origins of Nationalism: Albany, New York 1754-1835 "Journal of Social History, 21 (1987-88), 659-81; and Jack P. Greene, "Search for Identity: An Interpretation of the Meaning of Selected Patterns of Social Response in Eighteenth Century America," Journal of Social History, 3 (Spring 1970), 189-220 . On the predominance of state loyalties, see John M. Murrin, "A Roof Without Walls: the Dilemma of American National Identity," in Richard Beeman et al., eds., Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987), 333-48, and for a survey of significant colonial and regional differences militating against unity, see Josephine F. Pacheco, "Introduction," 1-23, in Josephine F. Pacheco, ed., Antifederalism: The Legacy of George Mason (Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1992). Among those who note the absence of nationalist claims in the Revolution are Max Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties in the American Revolution," American Historical Review, 67 (July 1962), 901-23; and Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960[1922]), ch. 2. Bernard Bailyn stresses the importance of ideas of the British political opposition in Revolutionary thinking, see his The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967) and The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1970). The weakness of eighteenth-century "national" identity is also implied by a number of arguments which attribute any perception of commonalities to the British, or to British influences. As Murrin argues, "America was a British idea" (p. 339), and it was the British who saw, and acted upon, the colonies as a whole. Merrett's study of contemporary newspapers shows, indeed, that British journalists used the collective term before the Americans did. Murrin, as well as Greene in "Search for Identity," argue, in a way that fits with the argument of this essay, the colonies shared an increasing Anglicization, if anything. Adding weight to the claim that American identity was weak and, to the extent that it existed, a British creation, is Shy's argument that the effects of British campaigning created, directly or indirectly, the beginnings of an American national identity. See John Shy, "The American Revolution: the Military Conflict Considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56. Among those who argue that national identity did not become generally salient until after reconstruction, see Merle Curti, The Roots of American Loyalty (New York: Russell and Russell, 1967); and Michael Kammen, A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1987).
-
(1987)
A Machine That Would Go of Itself : The Constitution in American Culture
-
-
Kammen, M.1
-
55
-
-
5844349304
-
-
passim
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in
-
Early Federation Movement
, pp. 58-417
-
-
Allin1
-
56
-
-
5844351168
-
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
Later Federation Movement
, pp. 1-8
-
-
Crisp1
-
57
-
-
5844403569
-
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
Constitutional History
, pp. 92-118
-
-
McMinn1
-
58
-
-
84873376327
-
-
chs. 1, and passim
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
Australian Constitution
, pp. 2
-
-
Nauze, L.1
-
59
-
-
5844339777
-
Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900
-
Gordon Greenwood, ed., Sydney: Angus and Robertson
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
(1955)
Australia: A Social and Political History
-
-
Gollan, R.A.1
-
60
-
-
79957327608
-
1890-1900
-
F. K. Crowley, ed., Melbourne: Heinemann
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
(1974)
A New History of Australia
-
-
De Garis, B.K.1
-
61
-
-
5844360399
-
'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914
-
April
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
(1971)
Historical Studies
, vol.14
, pp. 511-525
-
-
Cole, D.1
-
62
-
-
0003529635
-
-
London and New York: Longman
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
(1993)
British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914
, pp. 252
-
-
Cain, P.J.1
Hopkins, A.G.2
-
63
-
-
5844421619
-
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
Nationalism and Federalism
-
-
McMinn1
-
64
-
-
84881834372
-
-
Melbourne: Melbourne University Press
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
(1977)
Tocsin: Radical Comments Against Federation 1897-1900
-
-
Anderson, H.1
-
65
-
-
5844426666
-
Australian Nationality and Nationalism: The Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901
-
See Allin, Early Federation Movement, 58-417, passim; Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 1-8; McMinn, Constitutional History, 92-118; La Nauze, Australian Constitution, chs. 1, 2, 6, and passim; R. A. Gollan, "Nationalism, the Labour Movement and the Commonwealth 1880-1900," in Gordon Greenwood, ed., Australia: a Social and Political History (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1955); B. K. de Garis, "1890-1900," in F. K. Crowley, ed., A New History of Australia (Melbourne: Heinemann, 1974); Douglas Cole, "'The Crimson Thread of Kinship'; Ethnic Ideas in Australia 1870-1914," Historical Studies, 14 (April 1971), 511-25; and P, J. Cain and A. G. Hopkins, British Imperialism: Innovation and Expansion 1688-1914 (London and New York: Longman, 1993), 252. McMinn, in Nationalism and Federalism, provides the most recent overview of the story of Australian unification, see especially chapter 10. For a more radically nationalist line than appears in the conventions, see H. Anderson, ed., Tocsin: Radical Comments against Federation 1897-1900 (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1977); and for a more conservative line, see Charles Blackton, "Australian Nationality and Nationalism: the Imperial Federationist Interlude 1885-1901," Historical Studies, 7 (1955), 1-16.
-
(1955)
Historical Studies
, vol.7
, pp. 1-16
-
-
Blackton, C.1
-
66
-
-
84903661851
-
The Concept of Perpetual Union
-
June
-
On the legal ambiguity of the American union, see Kenneth M. Stampp, "The Concept of Perpetual Union," Journal of American History, 65 (June 1978), 5-33 . On the slow attenuation of the constitutional and legislative dependence on Britain in Australia, see W. J. Hudson and M. P. Sharpe, Australian Independence: Colony to Reluctant Kingdom (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1988).
-
(1978)
Journal of American History
, vol.65
, pp. 5-33
-
-
Stampp, K.M.1
-
67
-
-
84903661851
-
-
Carlton: Melbourne University Press
-
On the legal ambiguity of the American union, see Kenneth M. Stampp, "The Concept of Perpetual Union," Journal of American History, 65 (June 1978), 5-33 . On the slow attenuation of the constitutional and legislative dependence on Britain in Australia, see W. J. Hudson and M. P. Sharpe, Australian Independence: Colony to Reluctant Kingdom (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1988).
-
(1988)
Australian Independence: Colony to Reluctant Kingdom
-
-
Hudson, W.J.1
Sharpe, M.P.2
-
68
-
-
84898399534
-
The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View
-
July
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1976)
William and Mary Quarterly (3rd Ser.)
, vol.33
, pp. 466
-
-
Brown, R.1
-
69
-
-
0037744339
-
-
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, ch. 2
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1913)
The Framing of the Constitution of the United States
-
-
Farrand, M.1
-
70
-
-
5844358612
-
-
New York: Macmillan
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1966)
1787: The Grand Convention
, Issue.2 PART
-
-
Rossiter, C.1
-
71
-
-
0003432566
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1958)
We the People: The Economic Origins of the Constitution
-
-
McDonald, F.1
-
72
-
-
84903245978
-
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
Novus Ordo Seclorum
, pp. 217-224
-
-
-
73
-
-
1642330206
-
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
American Republic
-
-
Wood1
-
74
-
-
5844384433
-
Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention
-
Fall
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1987)
Political Science Reviewer
, vol.17
, pp. 131-174
-
-
Lloyd, G.1
-
75
-
-
0003903570
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1981)
What the AntiFederalists Were for
-
-
Storing, H.J.1
-
76
-
-
0011013313
-
Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1981)
William and Mary Quarterly (3rd Ser.)
, vol.38
, Issue.3
, pp. 339-368
-
-
Hutson, J.H.1
-
77
-
-
84963002176
-
Aristocracy Assailed. the Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism
-
March
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1990)
Journal of American History
, vol.76
, Issue.4
, pp. 1148-1172
-
-
Cornell, S.1
-
78
-
-
5844370325
-
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
AntiFederalism
-
-
Pacheco1
-
79
-
-
0007784243
-
-
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1993)
Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution
-
-
Brown, R.H.1
-
80
-
-
5844422107
-
-
Madison, WI: Madison House
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1990)
The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage
, pp. 8
-
-
Alexander, J.K.1
-
81
-
-
5844351168
-
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
Later Federation Movement
, pp. 19-23
-
-
Crisp, L.F.1
-
82
-
-
0012068894
-
-
John Hart, ed. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo
-
(1990)
Federation Fathers
-
-
Crisp1
-
83
-
-
5844422122
-
Who Are the Founding Fathers?
-
October
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1968)
Historical Studies
, vol.12
, pp. 333-352
-
-
La Nauze, J.A.1
-
84
-
-
0009227621
-
-
Carlton: Melbourne University Press
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1975)
The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910
, pp. 222-230
-
-
Norris, R.1
-
85
-
-
5844358613
-
-
Carlton: Melbourne University Press
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
(1964)
Historical Studies (1st Ser.)
, pp. 153-225
-
-
Eastwood, J.J.1
Smith, F.B.2
-
86
-
-
5844421619
-
-
Richard Brown, "The Founding Fathers of 1776 and 1787: A Collective View," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 33 (July 1976), 466. See also Max Farrand, The Framing of the Constitution of the United States (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1913), ch. 2; and Clinton Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: Macmillan, 1966), pt. 2. Forrest McDonald, in We the People: the Economic Origins of the Constitution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958) argues, against Beard's thesis, that delegates in Philadelphia did not act according to personal economic interest, but he does not contradict the claim that they were elites. See also his later description in Novus Ordo Seclorum, 217-24. For a sense of the range of political opinion beyond the convention, see Wood, American Republic: Gordon Lloyd, "Let Justice Be Our Guide: A Reconsideration of 'True Federalism' at the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 131-74; see also Herbert J. Storing, What the AntiFederalists Were For, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). Storing finds that antifederalists usually used the term "nation" to refer to the United States, as did their opponents: see pages 86-87 n.4. Their sense of identity does not appear to have been very different from that of the Federalists; however, they feared more an overemphasis on national glory. On analyses of federalist and antifederalist thought, see James H. Hutson in "Country, Court, and Constitution: Antifederalism and the Historians," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 38:3 (1981), 339-68; Saul Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed. The Ideology of Backcountry Anti-Federalism," Journal of American History, 76:4 (March 1990), 1148-72; and Pacheco, AntiFederalism. Federalist and anti-federalist projects are linked to social position by attitudes to the states' taxation weaknesses in Roger H. Brown, Redeeming the Republic: Federalists, Taxation, and the Origins of the Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993). The federalist cause was the better promoted: Most press coverage was Federalist and "a campaign was mounted to convince the people to accept whatever the delegates produced short of monarchy," and "essayists who cast doubt on the convention . . . rarely appeared in print . . . [and] . . . seldom got reprinted." See John K. Alexander, The Selling of the Constitutional Convention: A History of News Coverage (Madison, WI: Madison House, 1990), 8, 9. The social background of Australian convention delegates is summarized in L. F. Crisp, Later Federation Movement, 19-23; see also Crisp, Federation Fathers, John Hart, ed. (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1990); J. A. La Nauze, "Who Are The Founding Fathers?," Historical Studies, 12 (October 1968), 333-52; and R. Norris, The Emergent Commonwealth: Expectations and Fulfillment 1889-1910 (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1975), 222-30. Norris also discusses the Australian "protoBeardian" debate, between Geoffrey Blainey and R. S. Parker, pp. 165-71. Contributions to this debate can be found in J. J. Eastwood and F. B. Smith, comp., Historical Studies (1st ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1964), 153-225. See also McMinn, Nationalism and Federalism, 128-95.
-
Nationalism and Federalism
, pp. 128-195
-
-
McMinn1
-
87
-
-
5844410127
-
-
Adelaide: C. E. Bristow, Government Printer, hereafter, Debates
-
Official Report of the National Australian Convention Debates (Adelaide: C. E. Bristow, Government Printer, 1897), 193 [hereafter, Debates]. Francisco O. Ramirez, "Institutional Analysis," in George Thomas et al., Institutional Structure: Constituting State, Society, and the Individual (Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1987), 319, and Anderson, Imagined Communities, 63-64, note the importance of timing for constitutions and for nationalisms respectively. The difference of a century also has a methodological significance for this comparison, creating some incommensurability between Australian and American records. The proceedings of the Philadelphia convention were secret, and the existing records are notes, commentaries, and letters written privately by the delegates, most notably Madison. These records are extensive but are not verbatim, unlike the Australian records taken as Hansard under the system of the colonial parliaments. This means that the overall effect of the Philadelphia records, by comparison to those of Adelaide, may be skewed to the more nationalist of those involved in the debate (thus adding a second filter to the already nationalist tendencies of most of those who attended the convention). Neither convention is fully representative of its context, and the state of the records means there is an additional skew to the range that I include from Philadelphia. The comparison thus sacrifices representative range for the direct comparability of the institutional context in which talk of the nation is evoked. For the United States, representative range would require further examination of the claims here in Merrill Jensen et al., eds., The Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution, 16 vols, to date (Madison, WI: State Historical Society of Wisconsin, 1976-). For Australia, complete coverage would require analysis of records from later conventions, as well as press commentary: The Australian constitutional conventions were held in three cities over two years and run to four volumes of 1,500 pages each. I have used only the records of the first convention, in Adelaide. The later conventions, in Sydney and Melbourne, dealt only with some of the important issues or painstakingly reviewed suggestions from the colonies on revisions to the draft produced in Adelaide.
-
(1897)
Official Report of the National Australian Convention Debates
, pp. 193
-
-
-
88
-
-
4043179299
-
Institutional Analysis
-
George Thomas et al., Newbury Park, CA: Sage
-
Official Report of the National Australian Convention Debates (Adelaide: C. E. Bristow, Government Printer, 1897), 193 [hereafter, Debates]. Francisco O. Ramirez, "Institutional Analysis," in George Thomas et al., Institutional Structure: Constituting State, Society, and the Individual (Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1987), 319, and Anderson, Imagined Communities, 63-64, note the importance of timing for constitutions and for nationalisms respectively. The difference of a century also has a methodological significance for this comparison, creating some incommensurability between Australian and American records. The proceedings of the Philadelphia convention were secret, and the existing records are notes, commentaries, and letters written privately by the delegates, most notably Madison. These records are extensive but are not verbatim, unlike the Australian records taken as Hansard under the system of the colonial parliaments. This means that the overall effect of the Philadelphia records, by comparison to those of Adelaide, may be skewed to the more nationalist of those involved in the debate (thus adding a second filter to the already nationalist tendencies of most of those who attended the convention). Neither convention is fully representative of its context, and the state of the records means there is an additional skew to the range that I include from Philadelphia. The comparison thus sacrifices representative range for the direct comparability of the institutional context in which talk of the nation is evoked. For the United States, representative range would require further examination of the claims here in Merrill Jensen et al., eds., The Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution, 16 vols, to date (Madison, WI: State Historical Society of Wisconsin, 1976-). For Australia, complete coverage would require analysis of records from later conventions, as well as press commentary: The Australian constitutional conventions were held in three cities over two years and run to four volumes of 1,500 pages each. I have used only the records of the first convention, in Adelaide. The later conventions, in Sydney and Melbourne, dealt only with some of the important issues or painstakingly reviewed suggestions from the colonies on revisions to the draft produced in Adelaide.
-
(1987)
Institutional Structure: Constituting State, Society, and the Individual
, pp. 319
-
-
Ramirez, F.O.1
-
89
-
-
0004135073
-
-
Official Report of the National Australian Convention Debates (Adelaide: C. E. Bristow, Government Printer, 1897), 193 [hereafter, Debates]. Francisco O. Ramirez, "Institutional Analysis," in George Thomas et al., Institutional Structure: Constituting State, Society, and the Individual (Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1987), 319, and Anderson, Imagined Communities, 63-64, note the importance of timing for constitutions and for nationalisms respectively. The difference of a century also has a methodological significance for this comparison, creating some incommensurability between Australian and American records. The proceedings of the Philadelphia convention were secret, and the existing records are notes, commentaries, and letters written privately by the delegates, most notably Madison. These records are extensive but are not verbatim, unlike the Australian records taken as Hansard under the system of the colonial parliaments. This means that the overall effect of the Philadelphia records, by comparison to those of Adelaide, may be skewed to the more nationalist of those involved in the debate (thus adding a second filter to the already nationalist tendencies of most of those who attended the convention). Neither convention is fully representative of its context, and the state of the records means there is an additional skew to the range that I include from Philadelphia. The comparison thus sacrifices representative range for the direct comparability of the institutional context in which talk of the nation is evoked. For the United States, representative range would require further examination of the claims here in Merrill Jensen et al., eds., The Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution, 16 vols, to date (Madison, WI: State Historical Society of Wisconsin, 1976-). For Australia, complete coverage would require analysis of records from later conventions, as well as press commentary: The Australian constitutional conventions were held in three cities over two years and run to four volumes of 1,500 pages each. I have used only the records of the first convention, in Adelaide. The later conventions, in Sydney and Melbourne, dealt only with some of the important issues or painstakingly reviewed suggestions from the colonies on revisions to the draft produced in Adelaide.
-
Imagined Communities
, pp. 63-64
-
-
Anderson1
-
90
-
-
0039335151
-
-
16 vols, to date Madison, WI: State Historical Society of Wisconsin
-
Official Report of the National Australian Convention Debates (Adelaide: C. E. Bristow, Government Printer, 1897), 193 [hereafter, Debates]. Francisco O. Ramirez, "Institutional Analysis," in George Thomas et al., Institutional Structure: Constituting State, Society, and the Individual (Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1987), 319, and Anderson, Imagined Communities, 63-64, note the importance of timing for constitutions and for nationalisms respectively. The difference of a century also has a methodological significance for this comparison, creating some incommensurability between Australian and American records. The proceedings of the Philadelphia convention were secret, and the existing records are notes, commentaries, and letters written privately by the delegates, most notably Madison. These records are extensive but are not verbatim, unlike the Australian records taken as Hansard under the system of the colonial parliaments. This means that the overall effect of the Philadelphia records, by comparison to those of Adelaide, may be skewed to the more nationalist of those involved in the debate (thus adding a second filter to the already nationalist tendencies of most of those who attended the convention). Neither convention is fully representative of its context, and the state of the records means there is an additional skew to the range that I include from Philadelphia. The comparison thus sacrifices representative range for the direct comparability of the institutional context in which talk of the nation is evoked. For the United States, representative range would require further examination of the claims here in Merrill Jensen et al., eds., The Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution, 16 vols, to date (Madison, WI: State Historical Society of Wisconsin, 1976-). For Australia, complete coverage would require analysis of records from later conventions, as well as press commentary: The Australian constitutional conventions were held in three cities over two years and run to four volumes of 1,500 pages each. I have used only the records of the first convention, in Adelaide. The later conventions, in Sydney and Melbourne, dealt only with some of the important issues or painstakingly reviewed suggestions from the colonies on revisions to the draft produced in Adelaide.
-
(1976)
The Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution
-
-
Jensen, M.1
-
91
-
-
84933488648
-
Constitutions and the Struggle for Political Order: A Study in the Modernization of Political Traditions
-
Said Amir Arjomand, "Constitutions and the Struggle for Political Order: A Study in the Modernization of Political Traditions," European Journal of Sociology, 33:1 (1992), 75; E. M. Hunt, in American Precedents in Australian Federation (New York: A. M. S. Press, 1968[1930]), 254.
-
(1992)
European Journal of Sociology
, vol.33
, Issue.1
, pp. 75
-
-
Arjomand, S.A.1
-
92
-
-
84933488648
-
-
New York: A. M. S. Press, 1930
-
Said Amir Arjomand, "Constitutions and the Struggle for Political Order: A Study in the Modernization of Political Traditions," European Journal of Sociology, 33:1 (1992), 75; E. M. Hunt, in American Precedents in Australian Federation (New York: A. M. S. Press, 1968[1930]), 254.
-
(1968)
American Precedents in Australian Federation
, pp. 254
-
-
Hunt, E.M.1
-
93
-
-
84911054379
-
Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method
-
June
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
(1990)
American Sociological Review
, vol.55
, pp. 392
-
-
McMichael, P.1
-
94
-
-
5844403569
-
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
Constitutional History
, pp. 90
-
-
McMinn1
-
95
-
-
5844370326
-
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
Nationalism and Other Loyalties
, pp. 902
-
-
Savelle1
-
96
-
-
0040981218
-
-
March 22
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
(1775)
Speech on Conciliation with America
, pp. 40-43
-
-
Burke, E.1
-
97
-
-
5844422111
-
-
1765-1875, New York: Vintage Books
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
(1958)
Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record
, vol.1
-
-
Hofstadter, R.1
-
98
-
-
5844421629
-
The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill
-
A. W. Martin, ed., Carlton: Melbourne University Press
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
(1969)
Essays in Australian Federation
, pp. 94-121
-
-
De Garis, B.K.1
-
99
-
-
84953064925
-
'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience
-
January
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
(1984)
Comparative Studies in Society and History
, vol.26
, Issue.1
, pp. 7
-
-
Hind, R.J.1
-
100
-
-
0007247144
-
State Formation and the Construction of the World Market
-
Philip McMichael, "Incorporating Comparison within a World-Historical Perspective: An Alternative Comparative Method," American Sociological Review, 55 (June 1990), 392; McMinn, Constitutional History, 90; Burke is quoted by Savelle, in "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 902; see also Edmund Burke, "Speech on Conciliation with America" (March 22 1775), 40-43, in 1765-1875, vol. 1 of Great Issues in American History: A Documentary Record, Richard Hofstadter, ed. (New York: Vintage Books, 1958); B. K. de Garis, "The Colonial Office and the Commonwealth Constitution Bill," in A. W. Martin, ed., Essays in Australian Federation (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1969), 94-121; and Robert J. Hind, "'We Have No Colonies'-Similarities within the British Imperial Experience," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 26:1 (January 1984), 7. McMichael, in "State Formation and the Construction of the World Market, "Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual, no. 6 (1987), 187-237, analyzes changes in international political economy in the nineteenth century with special reference to Australia. Although his focus is on structural context rather than cultural repertoire, his analysis provides important background for the differences in interpretation of national identity between American and Australian conventions. And his point that world historical context is "not an external dimension so much as immanent dimension" of state formation fits with the argument here about repertoires of national identity claims.
-
(1987)
Political Power and Social Theory: A Research Annual
, vol.6
, pp. 187-237
-
-
McMichael1
-
101
-
-
5844381804
-
-
4 vols. New Haven: Yale University Press
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
(1966)
The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, Rev. Ed.
-
-
Farrand, M.1
-
102
-
-
5844339778
-
-
June 20
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, Rev. Ed.
, vol.1
, Issue.343
-
-
-
103
-
-
5844371905
-
-
June 18
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, Rev. Ed.
, vol.1
, Issue.301
-
-
-
104
-
-
5844347949
-
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
Debates
, pp. 301
-
-
-
105
-
-
5844426670
-
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
Grand Convention
, pp. 186
-
-
Rossiter1
-
106
-
-
0004152551
-
-
ch. 7
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
Novus Ordo Seclorum
-
-
McDonald1
-
107
-
-
0009227621
-
-
Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, rev. ed., 4 vols. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), I:343 (June 20), I:301 (June 18), Debates, 301 [the Farrand edition of the Philadelphia convention will be cited hereafter as Records]. On the various aspects of the "Grand Compromise," see Rossiter, Grand Convention, 186; and McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 7. On the Australians' expectations that Federal government would not overshadow that of the states, see Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 199-200.
-
Emergent Commonwealth
, pp. 199-200
-
-
Norris1
-
108
-
-
5844339783
-
-
June 16
-
Records, I:258 (June 16); I:340 (June 20). There is much discussion of the positions of delegates, but Lansing and Martin represent state against nationalist interests however the range of positions is described. Forrest McDonald calls these two "state particularists." See "Ne Philosophos Audiamus: The Middle Delegates in the Constitutional Convention," The Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 177-8. For the Australian claims later in the paragraph, see Debates, 430, 1163.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.258
-
-
-
109
-
-
5844321389
-
-
June 20
-
Records, I:258 (June 16); I:340 (June 20). There is much discussion of the positions of delegates, but Lansing and Martin represent state against nationalist interests however the range of positions is described. Forrest McDonald calls these two "state particularists." See "Ne Philosophos Audiamus: The Middle Delegates in the Constitutional Convention," The Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 177-8. For the Australian claims later in the paragraph, see Debates, 430, 1163.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.340
-
-
-
110
-
-
5844312952
-
Ne Philosophos Audiamus: The Middle Delegates in the Constitutional Convention
-
Fall
-
Records, I:258 (June 16); I:340 (June 20). There is much discussion of the positions of delegates, but Lansing and Martin represent state against nationalist interests however the range of positions is described. Forrest McDonald calls these two "state particularists." See "Ne Philosophos Audiamus: The Middle Delegates in the Constitutional Convention," The Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 177-8. For the Australian claims later in the paragraph, see Debates, 430, 1163.
-
(1987)
The Political Science Reviewer
, vol.17
, pp. 177-178
-
-
-
111
-
-
5844386241
-
-
Records, I:258 (June 16); I:340 (June 20). There is much discussion of the positions of delegates, but Lansing and Martin represent state against nationalist interests however the range of positions is described. Forrest McDonald calls these two "state particularists." See "Ne Philosophos Audiamus: The Middle Delegates in the Constitutional Convention," The Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987), 177-8. For the Australian claims later in the paragraph, see Debates, 430, 1163.
-
Debates
, pp. 430
-
-
-
112
-
-
5844395123
-
-
June 1
-
Records, I:66 (June 1); I:186 (June 9); Debates, 381.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.66
-
-
-
113
-
-
5844360411
-
-
June 9
-
Records, I:66 (June 1); I:186 (June 9); Debates, 381.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.186
-
-
-
114
-
-
5844321380
-
-
Records, I:66 (June 1); I:186 (June 9); Debates, 381.
-
Debates
, pp. 381
-
-
-
115
-
-
5844421628
-
-
June 7
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.161
-
-
-
116
-
-
5844389599
-
-
June 7
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.153
-
-
-
117
-
-
5844376629
-
-
June 1
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.66
-
-
-
118
-
-
5844410128
-
-
June 28
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.451
-
-
-
119
-
-
1642330206
-
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond
-
American Republic
, pp. 499-500
-
-
Wood1
-
120
-
-
5844349309
-
The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom
-
Paper presented University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
(1989)
General Aspects of Law Series
-
-
Pocock, J.G.A.1
-
121
-
-
77957837866
-
James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective
-
Beeman
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Beyond Confederation
, pp. 226-258
-
-
McCoy, D.1
-
122
-
-
5844389593
-
Continental Congress
-
Kurtz and Hutson
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
American Revolution
, pp. 157-196
-
-
Henderson1
-
123
-
-
5844421616
-
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Debates
, pp. 52
-
-
-
124
-
-
5844378060
-
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Debates
, pp. 928
-
-
-
125
-
-
5844410124
-
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
Debates
, pp. 647
-
-
-
126
-
-
0040037621
-
Comparative Frontier History
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
Records, I:161 (June 7), I:153 (June 7), I:66 (June 1). Wilson was expressing here what was, in the thought of the time, something of an extended oxymoron: It was generally believed that republican theory applied to small, intimate polities and would not work in large areas. There are frequent references to this problem of "extent" in the convention. Land is viewed through this lens: as providing various sorts of political threats. At the height of the deadlock on representation, Franklin introduced the idea of empire that would become a resolution to the contradiction between extent and republican principles: God governs in the affairs of men. And if a sparrow cannot fall to the ground without his notice, is it probable that an empire can rise without his aid? (Records I:451 [June 28], emphasis in original.) See Wood, American Republic, 499-500. Pocock has argued that it was the occupation of new territory which actually generated the new sovereignty, in the sense that this power grounds the unification impulse and, thus, that "empire" is from the beginning "part of the rhetoric of American nationality" (see J. G. A. Pocock, "The Politics of Extent and the Problems of Freedom" [Paper presented in the General Aspects of Law Series, University of California Berkeley Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, March 18, 1989]). More specifically, McCoy has argued that Madison uses the popular belief that population in the Southwest would grow to counter fears of Eastern dominance. See Drew McCoy, "James Madison and Visions of American Nationality in the Confederation Period: A Regional Perspective," in Beeman, Beyond Confederation, 226-58. The importance of the Western lands issue in the Confederation period has been widely noted: See, for example, Henderson, "Continental Congress," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 157-96. Both countries here differ from other more standard examples of nationalism because for both the land was assured before state formation and for both the land was extensive. The occupation of the land was not much contested with other political centers, as in irredentist and modern ethnic nationalisms. What is of interest here is the way in which the references to land as part of American identity, which occur frequently, were always phrased politically. For the Australians, the continent was also an uncontested national attribute. For example, O'Connor could claim that "we all feel that no federal union can be complete which does not embrace the people of the whole continent" (Debates, 52). But in Adelaide, the talk of the continent was framed in a different way. It did not represent political but rather economic constraint. It occurred mostly in the context of debates about infrastructure - about the sharing of precious river water, and about railways - "the arteries of our continent" (Debates, 928). Debates about how to deal with water in a river passing through several states were as involving to the delegates as any of the tense American debates over foreign influence. The much-debated frontier thesis is one of the ways by which similarities have been drawn between "settler colonies" like the United States and Australia. But it is clear that the existence of land to be occupied by white settlers needs to be understood in terms of the pre-existing polity: "We cannot get new States except by subdivision. In America they were able to get states by aggregation, by addition," as Higgins, one of the few to express admiration for the United States, pointed out (Debates, 647). See Leonard Thompson and Howard Lamarr, "Comparative Frontier History," in The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 3-13.
-
(1981)
The Frontier in History: North America and Southern Africa Compared
, pp. 3-13
-
-
Thompson, L.1
Lamarr, H.2
-
127
-
-
5844366304
-
-
June 20
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.339
-
-
-
128
-
-
5844371907
-
-
June 26
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.432
-
-
-
129
-
-
5844422112
-
-
June 11
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.206
-
-
-
130
-
-
1642330206
-
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
American Republic
, pp. 47
-
-
Wood1
-
131
-
-
84975953918
-
Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution
-
July
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
(1989)
Comparative Studies in Society and History
, vol.31
, Issue.3
, pp. 584
-
-
Howe, D.W.1
-
132
-
-
1642330206
-
-
chs. 2 and 3
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
American Republic
-
-
Wood1
-
133
-
-
84884110947
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
(1975)
The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition
-
-
Pocock, J.G.A.1
-
134
-
-
84935816997
-
-
New York: Basic Books
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
(1984)
The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism
, pp. 13
-
-
Diggins, J.P.1
-
135
-
-
0004152551
-
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
Novus Ordo Seclorum
, pp. 235
-
-
McDonald1
-
136
-
-
0040136971
-
The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787
-
January
-
Records, I:339 (June 20), I:432 (June 26), I:206 (June 11). Of course, delegates had long been committed to republicanism: Many historians have identified classical republicanism as a major source of ideas for the political innovation of 1776-87. Representative government and the absence of monarchy were overlaid with notions of public virtue, public good, and fear of corruption, to give a "moral dimension, a utopian depth . . . that involved the very character of their society" (Wood, American Republic, 47). Here I am concerned with what the delegates think is distinctive about the nation, rather than their political values per se; but it is not unexpected that national identity was associated with republicanism. It is important to note, though, that this political commitment was selected as characteristic of the nation rather than other available political, religious, or social symbols. It could have been otherwise: Scottish moral philosophy, also an important part of founders' political language, leaves its mark in characterizations of the people more indirectly, for example, in an unwillingness to trust good government to public virtue, and in the "concern with unintended outcomes" in constitutional design. See Daniel Walker Howe, "Why the Scottish Enlightenment Was Useful to the Framers of the American Constitution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 31:3 (July 1989), 584. On republicanism, see Wood, American Republic, chs. 2 and 3; and J. G. A. Pocock, The Macchiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975). For an argument that classical republicanism was "an idea whose time had come and gone by 1787," see John Patrick Diggins, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984), 13. Diggins argues that language and rhetoric, replete with republican claims, do not represent realities (Appendix I). He also conflates republican government and republican virtue in denying the influence of republicanism and rejects the Constitution's representativeness of "America's first principles" (p. 7). But Forrest McDonald points out that "the Framers were politically multilingual." What is significant here is the appeal to republican practices as distinctive of the people. See McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 235. On four distinguishable political idioms used in 1787, see Isaac Kramnick, "The 'Great National Discussion': The Discourse of Politics in 1787," William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3), 45:1 (January 1988), 3-32.
-
(1988)
William and Mary Quarterly (Ser. 3)
, vol.45
, Issue.1
, pp. 3-32
-
-
Kramnick, I.1
-
137
-
-
84924670810
-
-
n. 19
-
On the distinction between democracy and republicanism for the founders, Storing concludes that "both the Federalists and the Anti-Federalists used the term 'popular government' " to refer to "a range of ideas from simple, direct popular rule to a regulated, checked, mitigated rule of the people." Both sides tended to use "the term 'democracy' for the former end of the scale and 'republic' for the latter" (see Storing, Anti-Federalists, 90, n. 19, and Wood, American Republic, 222-6, 586). Saul Cornell, in "Aristocracy Assailed," argues that elite and populist antifederalists also differed in this way in their interpretations of democracy and that grass-roots antifederalists espoused a version of representative democracy against a concept of natural aristocracy that is also more evident in the convention.
-
Anti-Federalists
, pp. 90
-
-
Storing1
-
138
-
-
1642330206
-
-
On the distinction between democracy and republicanism for the founders, Storing concludes that "both the Federalists and the Anti-Federalists used the term 'popular government' " to refer to "a range of ideas from simple, direct popular rule to a regulated, checked, mitigated rule of the people." Both sides tended to use "the term 'democracy' for the former end of the scale and 'republic' for the latter" (see Storing, Anti-Federalists, 90, n. 19, and Wood, American Republic, 222-6, 586). Saul Cornell, in "Aristocracy Assailed," argues that elite and populist antifederalists also differed in this way in their interpretations of democracy and that grass-roots antifederalists espoused a version of representative democracy against a concept of natural aristocracy that is also more evident in the convention.
-
American Republic
, pp. 222-226
-
-
Wood1
-
139
-
-
5844366309
-
-
On the distinction between democracy and republicanism for the founders, Storing concludes that "both the Federalists and the Anti-Federalists used the term 'popular government' " to refer to "a range of ideas from simple, direct popular rule to a regulated, checked, mitigated rule of the people." Both sides tended to use "the term 'democracy' for the former end of the scale and 'republic' for the latter" (see Storing, Anti-Federalists, 90, n. 19, and Wood, American Republic, 222-6, 586). Saul Cornell, in "Aristocracy Assailed," argues that elite and populist antifederalists also differed in this way in their interpretations of democracy and that grass-roots antifederalists espoused a version of representative democracy against a concept of natural aristocracy that is also more evident in the convention.
-
Aristocracy Assailed
-
-
Cornell, S.1
-
140
-
-
5844339792
-
-
June 18
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.288
-
-
-
141
-
-
5844312948
-
-
June 4
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.101
-
-
-
142
-
-
5844347969
-
-
August 8
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.225
-
-
-
143
-
-
5844323193
-
-
June 25
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.403
-
-
-
144
-
-
5844383695
-
-
May 31
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.51
-
-
-
145
-
-
5844321382
-
-
July 12
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.512
-
-
-
146
-
-
5844374729
-
-
May 31
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.56
-
-
-
147
-
-
0346860520
-
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Framing
, pp. 174
-
-
Farrand1
-
148
-
-
0004152551
-
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Novus Ordo Seclorum
, pp. 161-165
-
-
McDonald1
-
149
-
-
5844357179
-
Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium
-
September
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
(1988)
Radical History Review
, vol.42
, pp. 10
-
-
Smith, B.C.1
-
150
-
-
5844396948
-
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Reflections on the Founding
, pp. 368
-
-
Onuf1
-
151
-
-
5844366309
-
-
Records. I:288 (June 18); I:101 (June 4); II:225 (August 8); I:403 (June 25); I:51 (May 31); I:512 (July 12); I:56 (May 31). On Gorham, see Farrand, Framing, 174. On distance from "the people," see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, 161-5. But it also seems true that, as Alfred Young argued, "the people out of doors" were indirectly influential in forming the constitution. Delegates, in Adelaide as well as Philadelphia, were constantly imagining and responding to the constraints set by the opinions of the "people outside." They were constantly concerned in their formulations with the question of legitimacy. As Young argues, "conservatives recoiled from extreme proposals for which they knew they could not win popular support. "See Barbara Clark Smith et al., "Moving Beyond Beard: A Symposium," Radical History Review, no. 42 (September 1988), 10. Onuf, in "Reflections on the Founding," also notes that "the Antifederalists played a much more positive role than is customarily allowed" (p. 368) in their indirect influence on constitutional debate. For an example of popular resistance to constitutional ratification, see Cornell, "Aristocracy Assailed." But as several commentators have remarked, in qualification of Young's thesis, the "people out of doors" were mostly white men: There were people beyond the people out of doors, as I will note below.
-
Aristocracy Assailed
-
-
Cornell1
-
152
-
-
5844399329
-
-
June 25
-
Records, I:390 (June 25); I:402 (June 25); I:398 (June 25).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.390
-
-
-
153
-
-
5844374734
-
-
June 25
-
Records, I:390 (June 25); I:402 (June 25); I:398 (June 25).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.402
-
-
-
154
-
-
5844401245
-
-
June 25
-
Records, I:390 (June 25); I:402 (June 25); I:398 (June 25).
-
Records
, vol.1
, pp. 398
-
-
-
155
-
-
84963072175
-
-
June 26
-
Records, I:442 (June 26). Hartz identified a "liberal absolutism" in American political culture that abstracts liberalism from its context of opposition to feudalism and radicalism and makes it absolute and universal. He dismisses references to stratification by the convention delegates as "ideological smoke" obscuring a unique sort of equality and unity. Hartz is thus enthusiastic about Pinckney's assertion of equality, unlike most delegates, who did talk of stratifications, indeed clung to them, even while characterizing their nation as lacking some of the social distinctions of Europe. See Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 81-86. See also Stanley N. Katz, "The Strange Birth and Unlikely History of Constitutional Equality," Journal of American History, 75:2 (December 1988), 747-62.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.442
-
-
-
156
-
-
84963072175
-
-
Records, I:442 (June 26). Hartz identified a "liberal absolutism" in American political culture that abstracts liberalism from its context of opposition to feudalism and radicalism and makes it absolute and universal. He dismisses references to stratification by the convention delegates as "ideological smoke" obscuring a unique sort of equality and unity. Hartz is thus enthusiastic about Pinckney's assertion of equality, unlike most delegates, who did talk of stratifications, indeed clung to them, even while characterizing their nation as lacking some of the social distinctions of Europe. See Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 81-86. See also Stanley N. Katz, "The Strange Birth and Unlikely History of Constitutional Equality," Journal of American History, 75:2 (December 1988), 747-62.
-
Liberal Tradition
, pp. 81-86
-
-
Hartz1
-
157
-
-
84963072175
-
The Strange Birth and Unlikely History of Constitutional Equality
-
December
-
Records, I:442 (June 26). Hartz identified a "liberal absolutism" in American political culture that abstracts liberalism from its context of opposition to feudalism and radicalism and makes it absolute and universal. He dismisses references to stratification by the convention delegates as "ideological smoke" obscuring a unique sort of equality and unity. Hartz is thus enthusiastic about Pinckney's assertion of equality, unlike most delegates, who did talk of stratifications, indeed clung to them, even while characterizing their nation as lacking some of the social distinctions of Europe. See Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 81-86. See also Stanley N. Katz, "The Strange Birth and Unlikely History of Constitutional Equality," Journal of American History, 75:2 (December 1988), 747-62.
-
(1988)
Journal of American History
, vol.75
, Issue.2
, pp. 747-762
-
-
Katz, S.N.1
-
158
-
-
5844381812
-
-
August 13
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:123 (July 26), II:606 (September 13). See also Wood, American Republic, 421-3. For clarification of the significance of accusations of aristocracy in this context, see James L. Huston, "The American Revolutionaries, the Political Economy of Aristocracy, and the American Concept of the Distribution of Wealth 1765-1900," American Historical Review, 98:4 (October 1993), 1079-1105.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.268
-
-
-
159
-
-
5844373779
-
-
July 26
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:123 (July 26), II:606 (September 13). See also Wood, American Republic, 421-3. For clarification of the significance of accusations of aristocracy in this context, see James L. Huston, "The American Revolutionaries, the Political Economy of Aristocracy, and the American Concept of the Distribution of Wealth 1765-1900," American Historical Review, 98:4 (October 1993), 1079-1105.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.123
-
-
-
160
-
-
5844358629
-
-
September 13
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:123 (July 26), II:606 (September 13). See also Wood, American Republic, 421-3. For clarification of the significance of accusations of aristocracy in this context, see James L. Huston, "The American Revolutionaries, the Political Economy of Aristocracy, and the American Concept of the Distribution of Wealth 1765-1900," American Historical Review, 98:4 (October 1993), 1079-1105.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.606
-
-
-
161
-
-
1642330206
-
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:123 (July 26), II:606 (September 13). See also Wood, American Republic, 421-3. For clarification of the significance of accusations of aristocracy in this context, see James L. Huston, "The American Revolutionaries, the Political Economy of Aristocracy, and the American Concept of the Distribution of Wealth 1765-1900," American Historical Review, 98:4 (October 1993), 1079-1105.
-
American Republic
, pp. 421-423
-
-
Wood1
-
162
-
-
0001734705
-
The American Revolutionaries, the Political Economy of Aristocracy, and the American Concept of the Distribution of Wealth 1765-1900
-
October
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:123 (July 26), II:606 (September 13). See also Wood, American Republic, 421-3. For clarification of the significance of accusations of aristocracy in this context, see James L. Huston, "The American Revolutionaries, the Political Economy of Aristocracy, and the American Concept of the Distribution of Wealth 1765-1900," American Historical Review, 98:4 (October 1993), 1079-1105.
-
(1993)
American Historical Review
, vol.98
, Issue.4
, pp. 1079-1105
-
-
Huston, J.L.1
-
163
-
-
5844358623
-
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
Debates
, pp. 651
-
-
-
164
-
-
5844403569
-
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
Constitutional History
, pp. 40-91
-
-
McMinn1
-
165
-
-
5844349318
-
-
Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
(1980)
Responsible Government in Australia
-
-
Weiler, P.1
Jaensch, D.2
-
166
-
-
5844323749
-
Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892
-
Greenwood, ed.
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
Australia
, pp. 98-114
-
-
McNaughton, I.D.1
-
167
-
-
5844384424
-
Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854
-
Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Carlton: Melbourne University Press
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
(1967)
Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd Ser.)
, pp. 51-74
-
-
Main, J.M.1
-
168
-
-
5844395113
-
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
British Imperial Experience
, pp. 7-8
-
-
Hind1
-
169
-
-
0004352160
-
-
Debates, 651, 721, 1033, 382, 28, 51. On the development and meaning of responsible government, see McMinn, Constitutional History, 40-91; Patrick Weiler and Dean Jaensch, eds., Responsible Government in Australia (Richmond, Victoria: Drummond Publishers, 1980); I. D. McNaughton, "Colonial Liberalism, 1851-1892," in Greenwood, ed., Australia, 98-114; J. M. Main, "Making Constitutions in New South Wales and Victoria 1853-1854," in Margot Beever and F. B. Smith, Historical Studies: Selected Articles (2nd ser.) (Carlton: Melbourne University Press, 1967), 51-74; Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 7-8; and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, 234-43.
-
British Imperialism
, pp. 234-243
-
-
Cain1
Hopkins2
-
170
-
-
5844381799
-
-
Debates, 213, 997, 110.
-
Debates
, pp. 213
-
-
-
171
-
-
5844426667
-
-
Debates, 1163, 619, 629, 309.
-
Debates
, pp. 1163
-
-
-
172
-
-
5844362793
-
-
Debates, 293, 78.
-
Debates
, pp. 293
-
-
-
173
-
-
5844383683
-
-
Debates, 316, 618. Cole discusses an important "ethnocentric continuum" in Australian thinking about identity in this period. The continuum ranges from racism to Anglo-Saxon identity to ideas about a new Australian "type," linking racism to imperialism to nationalism. In fact, he argues, the ideological linkages to Anglo-Saxon and Caucasian identities weakened the nationalism in Australian identity (see Cole, "Crimson Thread," 511-25, and White, Inventing Australia, 63-84).
-
Debates
, pp. 316
-
-
-
174
-
-
5844325610
-
-
Debates, 316, 618. Cole discusses an important "ethnocentric continuum" in Australian thinking about identity in this period. The continuum ranges from racism to Anglo-Saxon identity to ideas about a new Australian "type," linking racism to imperialism to nationalism. In fact, he argues, the ideological linkages to Anglo-Saxon and Caucasian identities weakened the nationalism in Australian identity (see Cole, "Crimson Thread," 511-25, and White, Inventing Australia, 63-84).
-
Crimson Thread
, pp. 511-525
-
-
Cole1
-
175
-
-
0003440389
-
-
Debates, 316, 618. Cole discusses an important "ethnocentric continuum" in Australian thinking about identity in this period. The continuum ranges from racism to Anglo-Saxon identity to ideas about a new Australian "type," linking racism to imperialism to nationalism. In fact, he argues, the ideological linkages to Anglo-Saxon and Caucasian identities weakened the nationalism in Australian identity (see Cole, "Crimson Thread," 511-25, and White, Inventing Australia, 63-84).
-
Inventing Australia
, pp. 63-84
-
-
White1
-
176
-
-
5844393804
-
-
Debates, 353, 986, 987, 975. As in one colony a decade earlier, the colonists spoke as though "their common experiences were British, their common sense of identity was as Britons, not Australians." See Stephen P. Shortus, "'Colonial Nationalism': New South Welsh Identity in the mid-1880's," Journal of the Royal Australian Historical Society, 59 (March 1973), 38 (emphasis in the original). Greene argues that a similar identity existed in the American colonies: "Their incorporation into the larger Anglophone world was an essential component of colonial self-esteem: for the colonists a positive sense of identity prior to 1775 was dependent upon their bility to identify themselves as "free Englishmen" (Greene, "Fortuitous Convergence," 253.)
-
Debates
, pp. 353
-
-
-
177
-
-
5844347951
-
'Colonial Nationalism': New South Welsh Identity in the mid-1880's
-
March
-
Debates, 353, 986, 987, 975. As in one colony a decade earlier, the colonists spoke as though "their common experiences were British, their common sense of identity was as Britons, not Australians." See Stephen P. Shortus, "'Colonial Nationalism': New South Welsh Identity in the mid-1880's," Journal of the Royal Australian Historical Society, 59 (March 1973), 38 (emphasis in the original). Greene argues that a similar identity existed in the American colonies: "Their incorporation into the larger Anglophone world was an essential component of colonial self-esteem: for the colonists a positive sense of identity prior to 1775 was dependent upon their bility to identify themselves as "free Englishmen" (Greene, "Fortuitous Convergence," 253.)
-
(1973)
Journal of the Royal Australian Historical Society
, vol.59
, pp. 38
-
-
Shortus, S.P.1
-
178
-
-
5844391940
-
-
Debates, 353, 986, 987, 975. As in one colony a decade earlier, the colonists spoke as though "their common experiences were British, their common sense of identity was as Britons, not Australians." See Stephen P. Shortus, "'Colonial Nationalism': New South Welsh Identity in the mid-1880's," Journal of the Royal Australian Historical Society, 59 (March 1973), 38 (emphasis in the original). Greene argues that a similar identity existed in the American colonies: "Their incorporation into the larger Anglophone world was an essential component of colonial self-esteem: for the colonists a positive sense of identity prior to 1775 was dependent upon their bility to identify themselves as "free Englishmen" (Greene, "Fortuitous Convergence," 253.)
-
Fortuitous Convergence
, pp. 253
-
-
Greene1
-
179
-
-
5844410130
-
-
June 4
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.107
-
-
-
180
-
-
5844396947
-
-
June 11
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.206
-
-
-
181
-
-
5844331715
-
-
August 22
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.370
-
-
-
182
-
-
5844360405
-
-
August 21
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.364
-
-
-
183
-
-
5844371908
-
-
August 21
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.364
-
-
-
184
-
-
0003945278
-
-
Stanford: Stanford University Press
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
(1988)
The Sexual Contract
-
-
Pateman, C.1
-
185
-
-
5844405989
-
Liberal Society and the Indian Question
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
(1987)
Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology
-
-
Rogin, M.1
-
186
-
-
5844383684
-
Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes
-
ch. 10, Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press
-
Records, I:107 (June 4); I:206 (June 11); II:370 (August 22); II:364 (August 21); II:364 (August 21). See also, for instance, Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988); Michael Rogin, "Liberal Society and the Indian Question," in Ronald Reagan, the Movie and Other Episodes in Political Demonology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); and James H. Kettner, "Birthright Citizenship and the Status of Indians, Slaves, and Free Negroes," ch. 10, in The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1978).
-
(1978)
The Development of American Citizenship 1608-1870
-
-
Kettner, J.H.1
-
187
-
-
5844426671
-
-
Debates, 33. See also Audrey Oldfield, Woman Suffrage in Australia: A Gift or A Struggle? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). But on women in Australian nationalist mythology more generally, see Barham, "Conceptualisations of Women."
-
Debates
, pp. 33
-
-
-
188
-
-
0004293517
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Debates, 33. See also Audrey Oldfield, Woman Suffrage in Australia: A Gift or A Struggle? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). But on women in Australian nationalist mythology more generally, see Barham, "Conceptualisations of Women."
-
(1992)
Woman Suffrage in Australia: A Gift or a Struggle?
-
-
Oldfield, A.1
-
189
-
-
5844374720
-
-
Debates, 33. See also Audrey Oldfield, Woman Suffrage in Australia: A Gift or A Struggle? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). But on women in Australian nationalist mythology more generally, see Barham, "Conceptualisations of Women."
-
Conceptualisations of Women
-
-
Barham1
-
190
-
-
5844427134
-
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
Debates
, pp. 718
-
-
-
191
-
-
5844339784
-
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
Debates
, pp. 731
-
-
-
192
-
-
0009227621
-
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
Emergent Commonwealth
, pp. 43-65
-
-
Norris1
-
193
-
-
5844403550
-
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
Colonial Nationalism
, pp. 135
-
-
Eddy1
Schreuder2
-
194
-
-
5844325610
-
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
Crimson Thread
-
-
Cole1
-
195
-
-
0003440389
-
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
Inventing Australia
-
-
White1
-
196
-
-
80054324267
-
Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise
-
October
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
(1993)
Australian Historical Studies
, vol.25
, Issue.101
, pp. 521-535
-
-
Stretton, P.1
Finnimore, C.2
-
197
-
-
0009739475
-
-
North Ryde: Methuen Australia, ch. 10
-
Debates, 718; Debates, 731. See Norris, Emergent Commonwealth, 43-65. As Eddy and Schreuder among others suggest, colonial nationalism, in Australia as elsewhere, was intrinsically "exclusionist" and the attachment to the empire "connotes the defensive cooperation of white nations." See Eddy and Schreuder, Colonial Nationalism, 135. See also, for instance, Cole, "Crimson Thread"; White, Inventing Australia: Pat Stretton and Christine Finnimore, "Black Fellow Citizens: Aborigines and the Commonwealth Franchise," Australian Historical Studies, 25:101 (October 1993), 521-35; A. T. Yarwood and M. J. Knowling, Race Relations in Australia: A History (North Ryde: Methuen Australia, 1982), ch. 10.
-
(1982)
Race Relations in Australia: A History
-
-
Yarwood, A.T.1
Knowling, M.J.2
-
198
-
-
5844360406
-
-
May 25
-
Records, I: 18 (May 25); I: 133 (June 6). Greene examines the use of models in American identity formation, and claims that positive, normative models "exercise a more powerful influence in the process" than negative models. This does not appear to be the case in the convention debates (Greene, "Search for Identity," 191 n.4). Hartz also notices the use of comparative models and argues that, despite the erudition of the founders, they did not "learn how much they differed from the Greeks and modern Europeans" but "put themselves in a category with both" (see Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 82-83). The frequent use of comparisons at the convention as warnings, or (for Britain) as models, generally supports him: The English model is also often dismissed, however, as irrelevant, for the reasons concerned with social distinction mentioned earlier, in a way that contradicts Hartz's argument. Indeed, the use of this contrast with Britain arises precisely where delegates attempt to speak of the nation; they do show an awareness of the distinctiveness of their country, though it is with reference to Europe rather than with any fully developed analysis of their society in its own right. This awareness somewhat undermines Hartz's theses about national identity, if not political culture.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.18
-
-
-
199
-
-
5844325611
-
-
June 6
-
Records, I: 18 (May 25); I: 133 (June 6). Greene examines the use of models in American identity formation, and claims that positive, normative models "exercise a more powerful influence in the process" than negative models. This does not appear to be the case in the convention debates (Greene, "Search for Identity," 191 n.4). Hartz also notices the use of comparative models and argues that, despite the erudition of the founders, they did not "learn how much they differed from the Greeks and modern Europeans" but "put themselves in a category with both" (see Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 82-83). The frequent use of comparisons at the convention as warnings, or (for Britain) as models, generally supports him: The English model is also often dismissed, however, as irrelevant, for the reasons concerned with social distinction mentioned earlier, in a way that contradicts Hartz's argument. Indeed, the use of this contrast with Britain arises precisely where delegates attempt to speak of the nation; they do show an awareness of the distinctiveness of their country, though it is with reference to Europe rather than with any fully developed analysis of their society in its own right. This awareness somewhat undermines Hartz's theses about national identity, if not political culture.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.133
-
-
-
200
-
-
5844321374
-
-
Records, I: 18 (May 25); I: 133 (June 6). Greene examines the use of models in American identity formation, and claims that positive, normative models "exercise a more powerful influence in the process" than negative models. This does not appear to be the case in the convention debates (Greene, "Search for Identity," 191 n.4). Hartz also notices the use of comparative models and argues that, despite the erudition of the founders, they did not "learn how much they differed from the Greeks and modern Europeans" but "put themselves in a category with both" (see Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 82-83). The frequent use of comparisons at the convention as warnings, or (for Britain) as models, generally supports him: The English model is also often dismissed, however, as irrelevant, for the reasons concerned with social distinction mentioned earlier, in a way that contradicts Hartz's argument. Indeed, the use of this contrast with Britain arises precisely where delegates attempt to speak of the nation; they do show an awareness of the distinctiveness of their country, though it is with reference to Europe rather than with any fully developed analysis of their society in its own right. This awareness somewhat undermines Hartz's theses about national identity, if not political culture.
-
Search for Identity
, vol.191
, Issue.4
-
-
Greene1
-
201
-
-
0347253235
-
-
Records, I: 18 (May 25); I: 133 (June 6). Greene examines the use of models in American identity formation, and claims that positive, normative models "exercise a more powerful influence in the process" than negative models. This does not appear to be the case in the convention debates (Greene, "Search for Identity," 191 n.4). Hartz also notices the use of comparative models and argues that, despite the erudition of the founders, they did not "learn how much they differed from the Greeks and modern Europeans" but "put themselves in a category with both" (see Hartz, Liberal Tradition, 82-83). The frequent use of comparisons at the convention as warnings, or (for Britain) as models, generally supports him: The English model is also often dismissed, however, as irrelevant, for the reasons concerned with social distinction mentioned earlier, in a way that contradicts Hartz's argument. Indeed, the use of this contrast with Britain arises precisely where delegates attempt to speak of the nation; they do show an awareness of the distinctiveness of their country, though it is with reference to Europe rather than with any fully developed analysis of their society in its own right. This awareness somewhat undermines Hartz's theses about national identity, if not political culture.
-
Liberal Tradition
, pp. 82-83
-
-
Hartz1
-
202
-
-
5844381805
-
-
Debates, 87.
-
Debates
, pp. 87
-
-
-
203
-
-
5844426678
-
-
June 30
-
Records, I:492 (June 30); I:493 (June 30). Some historians have argued that weakness in foreign relations was an important motive for the convention. Marks has detailed a number of problems of trade and security and shown how they influenced the climate of opinion before the convention. See Frederick W. Marks III, Independence on Trial: Foreign Affairs and the Making of the Constitution (Wilmington: Scholarly Resources, 1986). Onuf ("Reflections on the Founding," 358) has also noted the neglected influence of foreign affairs for convention issues, suggesting that "no neat distinction between domestic and foreign politics could then or should now be drawn." It is part of the argument of this essay that this is true for discussions of national identity too.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.492
-
-
-
204
-
-
5844405990
-
-
June 30
-
Records, I:492 (June 30); I:493 (June 30). Some historians have argued that weakness in foreign relations was an important motive for the convention. Marks has detailed a number of problems of trade and security and shown how they influenced the climate of opinion before the convention. See Frederick W. Marks III, Independence on Trial: Foreign Affairs and the Making of the Constitution (Wilmington: Scholarly Resources, 1986). Onuf ("Reflections on the Founding," 358) has also noted the neglected influence of foreign affairs for convention issues, suggesting that "no neat distinction between domestic and foreign politics could then or should now be drawn." It is part of the argument of this essay that this is true for discussions of national identity too.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.493
-
-
-
205
-
-
0347508509
-
-
Wilmington: Scholarly Resources
-
Records, I:492 (June 30); I:493 (June 30). Some historians have argued that weakness in foreign relations was an important motive for the convention. Marks has detailed a number of problems of trade and security and shown how they influenced the climate of opinion before the convention. See Frederick W. Marks III, Independence on Trial: Foreign Affairs and the Making of the Constitution (Wilmington: Scholarly Resources, 1986). Onuf ("Reflections on the Founding," 358) has also noted the neglected influence of foreign affairs for convention issues, suggesting that "no neat distinction between domestic and foreign politics could then or should now be drawn." It is part of the argument of this essay that this is true for discussions of national identity too.
-
(1986)
Independence on Trial: Foreign Affairs and the Making of the Constitution
-
-
Marks III, F.W.1
-
206
-
-
5844396948
-
-
Records, I:492 (June 30); I:493 (June 30). Some historians have argued that weakness in foreign relations was an important motive for the convention. Marks has detailed a number of problems of trade and security and shown how they influenced the climate of opinion before the convention. See Frederick W. Marks III, Independence on Trial: Foreign Affairs and the Making of the Constitution (Wilmington: Scholarly Resources, 1986). Onuf ("Reflections on the Founding," 358) has also noted the neglected influence of foreign affairs for convention issues, suggesting that "no neat distinction between domestic and foreign politics could then or should now be drawn." It is part of the argument of this essay that this is true for discussions of national identity too.
-
Reflections on the Founding
, pp. 358
-
-
Onuf1
-
207
-
-
5844378066
-
-
June 8
-
Records, I:172 (June 8); I:285 (June 18); I:473 (June 29).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.172
-
-
-
208
-
-
5844312938
-
-
June 18
-
Records, I:172 (June 8); I:285 (June 18); I:473 (June 29).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.285
-
-
-
209
-
-
5844339790
-
-
June 29
-
Records, I:172 (June 8); I:285 (June 18); I:473 (June 29).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.473
-
-
-
210
-
-
5844339785
-
-
July 20
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.68
-
-
-
211
-
-
5844341552
-
-
August 8
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.216
-
-
-
212
-
-
5844339791
-
-
August 13
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.268
-
-
-
213
-
-
5844401244
-
-
August 9
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.238
-
-
-
214
-
-
1642330206
-
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
American Republic
, pp. 107-114
-
-
Wood1
-
215
-
-
5844396940
-
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
Continental Congress
, pp. 249-255
-
-
Rakove, J.1
-
216
-
-
5844349310
-
An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution
-
Kurtz and Hutson
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
American Revolution
, pp. 79
-
-
Greene, J.P.1
-
217
-
-
0002255759
-
-
note to ch. 4
-
Records, II:68 (July 20); II:216 (August 8); II:268 (August 13); II:238 (August 9). The characterization of English government as corrupt and the fear of American corruption was a common theme in the political thought of the time. See for example Wood, American Republic, 107-14. Superficially, there seems little ground for the strength of the suspicion of foreign corruption. Although foreign policy had been a weakness of the Continental Congress, Jack Rakove, in Continental Congress, 249-55 and 342-52, describes little that is the direct result of foreign corruption in his recounting of the problems of the Congress. However, Greene shows how latent tensions and a changing structure of expectations in the pre-revolutionary relation with Britain might account for the conspiracy theme, concluding: Clearly, the kind of conspiracy many colonists thought existed did not. . . . Since 1748 however, there had been an unmistakable and continuing effort . . . to bring the colonies under tighter regulation. . . . Given the colonists' customary expectations . . . this effort, and its many specific components seemed to the colonists - and was in fact - a fundamental attack upon the extant moral order within the empire as they conceived of that order. See Jack P. Greene, "An Uneasy Connection: An Analysis of the Preconditions of the American Revolution," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 79 (emphasis in original). See also Bernard Bailyn, ideological Origins, note to ch. 4.
-
Ideological Origins
-
-
Bailyn, B.1
-
218
-
-
5844341551
-
-
June 8
-
Records, I:172 (June 8); II:236 (August 9).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.172
-
-
-
219
-
-
5844410136
-
-
August 9
-
Records, I:172 (June 8); II:236 (August 9).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.236
-
-
-
220
-
-
5844413122
-
-
August 13
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:236 (August 9); II:237 (August 9).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.268
-
-
-
221
-
-
5844386247
-
-
August 9
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:236 (August 9); II:237 (August 9).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.236
-
-
-
222
-
-
5844368569
-
-
August 9
-
Records, II:268 (August 13), II:236 (August 9); II:237 (August 9).
-
Records
, vol.2
, Issue.237
-
-
-
223
-
-
84972957658
-
The Creation of American National Identity 1774-1796
-
Heidi Tarver, "The Creation of American National Identity 1774-1796," Berkeley Journal of Sociology, 37 (1992), 91. On the revolutionary war as a process of political education, see Shy, "The American Revolution: The Military Conflict considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56; see also Lipset, First New Nation.
-
(1992)
Berkeley Journal of Sociology
, vol.37
, pp. 91
-
-
Tarver, H.1
-
224
-
-
5844349302
-
The American Revolution: The Military Conflict considered as a Revolutionary War
-
Kurtz and Hutson
-
Heidi Tarver, "The Creation of American National Identity 1774-1796," Berkeley Journal of Sociology, 37 (1992), 91. On the revolutionary war as a process of political education, see Shy, "The American Revolution: The Military Conflict considered as a Revolutionary
-
American Revolution
, pp. 121-156
-
-
Shy1
-
225
-
-
0004087165
-
-
Heidi Tarver, "The Creation of American National Identity 1774-1796," Berkeley Journal of Sociology, 37 (1992), 91. On the revolutionary war as a process of political education, see Shy, "The American Revolution: The Military Conflict considered as a Revolutionary War," in Kurtz and Hutson, American Revolution, 121-56; see also Lipset, First New Nation.
-
First New Nation
-
-
Lipset1
-
226
-
-
5844331718
-
-
July 2
-
Records, I:519 (July 2), I:108 (June 4); I:426 (June 26); I:332 (June 19); I:424 (June 26). Olson, in his study of revolutionary images, found that "all major motifs of the period displayed pervasive concerns about whether Americans held the same status as the English. To judge from the pictorial record, these concerns were as fundamental in Britain and America as any apprehensions of conspiracy" (see Olson, Emblems, xv).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.519
-
-
-
227
-
-
5844410138
-
-
June 4
-
Records, I:519 (July 2), I:108 (June 4); I:426 (June 26); I:332 (June 19); I:424 (June 26). Olson, in his study of revolutionary images, found that "all major motifs of the period displayed pervasive concerns about whether Americans held the same status as the English. To judge from the pictorial record, these concerns were as fundamental in Britain and America as any apprehensions of conspiracy" (see Olson, Emblems, xv).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.108
-
-
-
228
-
-
5844403561
-
-
June 26
-
Records, I:519 (July 2), I:108 (June 4); I:426 (June 26); I:332 (June 19); I:424 (June 26). Olson, in his study of revolutionary images, found that "all major motifs of the period displayed pervasive concerns about whether Americans held the same status as the English. To judge from the pictorial record, these concerns were as fundamental in Britain and America as any apprehensions of conspiracy" (see Olson, Emblems, xv).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.426
-
-
-
229
-
-
5844419802
-
-
June 19
-
Records, I:519 (July 2), I:108 (June 4); I:426 (June 26); I:332 (June 19); I:424 (June 26). Olson, in his study of revolutionary images, found that "all major motifs of the period displayed pervasive concerns about whether Americans held the same status as the English. To judge from the pictorial record, these concerns were as fundamental in Britain and America as any apprehensions of conspiracy" (see Olson, Emblems, xv).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.332
-
-
-
230
-
-
5844426676
-
-
June 26
-
Records, I:519 (July 2), I:108 (June 4); I:426 (June 26); I:332 (June 19); I:424 (June 26). Olson, in his study of revolutionary images, found that "all major motifs of the period displayed pervasive concerns about whether Americans held the same status as the English. To judge from the pictorial record, these concerns were as fundamental in Britain and America as any apprehensions of conspiracy" (see Olson, Emblems, xv).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.424
-
-
-
231
-
-
5844360407
-
-
Records, I:519 (July 2), I:108 (June 4); I:426 (June 26); I:332 (June 19); I:424 (June 26). Olson, in his study of revolutionary images, found that "all major motifs of the period displayed pervasive concerns about whether Americans held the same status as the English. To judge from the pictorial record, these concerns were as fundamental in Britain and America as any apprehensions of conspiracy" (see Olson, Emblems, xv).
-
Emblems
-
-
Olson1
-
232
-
-
5844357178
-
-
June 30
-
Records, I:485 (June 30).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.485
-
-
-
233
-
-
5844362796
-
-
June 30
-
Records, I:484 (June 30); I:254 (June 16); I:66 (June 1). On the English model in the thought of the founders, see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 2, passim.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.484
-
-
-
234
-
-
5844422118
-
-
June 16
-
Records, I:484 (June 30); I:254 (June 16); I:66 (June 1). On the English model in the thought of the founders, see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 2, passim.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.254
-
-
-
235
-
-
5844370334
-
-
June 1
-
Records, I:484 (June 30); I:254 (June 16); I:66 (June 1). On the English model in the thought of the founders, see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 2, passim.
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.66
-
-
-
236
-
-
0004152551
-
-
ch. 2, passim
-
Records, I:484 (June 30); I:254 (June 16); I:66 (June 1). On the English model in the thought of the founders, see McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum, ch. 2, passim.
-
Novus Ordo Seclorum
-
-
McDonald1
-
237
-
-
0003440389
-
-
White, in Inventing Australia, 47-62, describes how much Australia likened itself to America throughout the later nineteenth century, identifying as a "newer" new society. However, from the 1850s a distinction between British-Australian and American democracy developed. It is this more ambivalent aspect of the perceived similarity to the United States that dominates the convention and is probably an aspect of the bias to elites, as Higgins, one of the more radical delegates, is the only participant to speak admiringly of the American democratic example. See also Hunt, American Precedents, ch. 6.
-
Inventing Australia
, pp. 47-62
-
-
White1
-
238
-
-
5844371913
-
-
ch. 6
-
White, in Inventing Australia, 47-62, describes how much Australia likened itself to America throughout the later nineteenth century, identifying as a "newer" new society. However, from the 1850s a distinction between British-Australian and American democracy developed. It is this more ambivalent aspect of the perceived similarity to the United States that dominates the convention and is probably an aspect of the bias to elites, as Higgins, one of the more radical delegates, is the only participant to speak admiringly of the American democratic example. See also Hunt, American Precedents, ch. 6.
-
American Precedents
-
-
Hunt1
-
239
-
-
5844370333
-
-
Debates, 382, 118.
-
Debates
, pp. 382
-
-
-
240
-
-
5844323755
-
-
Debates, 662. Hopes of future international glory, while rare in Adelaide, were more commonly expressed than in the recorded Philadelphia debates. However, Kramnick, in "National Discussion" suggests that Hamilton, especially, imagined a "powerful state in the world of states" (p. 27) and drew on a generally intelligible language of state power.
-
Debates
, pp. 662
-
-
-
241
-
-
84971803727
-
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
Debates
, pp. 568
-
-
-
242
-
-
84971803727
-
1870-1890
-
Crowley
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
New History
, pp. 199-203
-
-
Buxton, G.L.1
-
243
-
-
84971803727
-
The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889
-
Martin
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
Australian Federation
, pp. 1-56
-
-
Serie, G.1
-
244
-
-
84971803727
-
-
Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
(1973)
External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900
-
-
Luk, G.1
-
245
-
-
84971803727
-
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
Colonial Nationalism
, pp. 34-35
-
-
Shortus1
-
246
-
-
84971803727
-
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
Nationalism and Other Loyalties
, pp. 901-923
-
-
Savelle1
-
247
-
-
84971803727
-
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
Uneasy Connection
, pp. 33-35
-
-
Greene1
-
248
-
-
84971803727
-
-
ch. 3
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
Emblems
-
-
Olson1
-
249
-
-
84971803727
-
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
British Imperial Experience
, pp. 25
-
-
Hind1
-
250
-
-
84971803727
-
Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution
-
January
-
Debates, 568, 1177, 353, 393. Concern that Australian interests were not properly considered in London was especially salient in the 1880s and was a major motive for moves to federate at the time, although the motivation had receded and been overtaken by the benefits of economic unification in the 1890s. See G. L. Buxton, "1870-1890," in Crowley, New History, 199-203; Geoffrey Serie, "The Victorian Government's Campaign for Federation 1883-1889," in Martin, Australian Federation, 1-56; and G. Luk, "External Threats as a Factor in Australian Politics 1870-1900," (Ph.D. disser., University of Sydney, 1973). Shortus, in "Colonial Nationalism," 34-35, discusses family metaphors for the relations of New South Wales to the empire. Family metaphors were often used to describe the relationship, as well as the nature of the tensions between, the American colonies and England. See Savelle, "Nationalism and Other Loyalties," 901-23, and Greene, "Uneasy Connection," 33-35. Olson, Emblems, ch. 3, finds that the image of the American colonies as child was one of the three most common images used from 1754 to 1784 and that "during the Revolution, the image of America's stature was redefined in that the child attained adulthood" (p. xv). From the imperial point of view, the colonized were also frequently viewed as children (see Hind, "British Imperial Experience," 25). Mary Lowenthal Felstiner analyzes familial metaphors in the Chilean colonial context, and her conclusions offer many insights for comparative analysis (see "Family Metaphors: The Language of an Independence Revolution," Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25:1 (January 1983), 154-80.
-
(1983)
Comparative Studies in Society and History
, vol.25
, Issue.1
, pp. 154-180
-
-
-
251
-
-
5844427133
-
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
Debates
, pp. 318
-
-
-
252
-
-
5844421626
-
-
June 26
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.426
-
-
-
253
-
-
5844347965
-
James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783
-
April
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
(1983)
William and Mary Quarterly (3rd Ser.)
, vol.40
, pp. 227-255
-
-
Banning1
-
254
-
-
84965495027
-
-
passim
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
Foreign Affairs
-
-
Marks1
-
255
-
-
0039335159
-
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
Redeeming the Republic
, pp. 21
-
-
Brown1
-
256
-
-
5844331719
-
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
Debates
, pp. 374
-
-
-
257
-
-
0142189589
-
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
State Formation
-
-
McMichael1
-
258
-
-
0004352160
-
-
Debates, 318, 374. Only rarely were international economic issues addressed directly in Philadelphia. Madison did mention a fear that Britain would not make a commercial treaty because it believed the country to be unstable. See Records, I:426 (June 26). Lance Banning argues that Madison was preoccupied with strengthening unified action to counter British navigation laws, which were having marked economic effects; and Marks suggests that international economic problems were highly significant to a range of groups in creating the demand for a stronger union. See Banning, "James Madison and the Nationalists 1780-1783," William and Mary Quarterly (3rd ser.), 40 (April 1983), 227-55; and Marks, Foreign Affairs, passim. Brown, in Redeeming the Republic, 21, 143-6, argues that foreign issues were the result of states' taxation failures. But economic insecurity is little expressed in the Philadelphia convention by comparison with the talk in Adelaide. Indeed, the economic dimension of federation seems much more important to the Australians than the Philadelphia delegates. Whereas the national "power of regulating commerce" is not given much comment by the Americans at this time, for the Australians, intercolonial tariffs had long been a matter of dispute and standardizing the gauge of railways was important. In one of the pithier statements of an oft-repeated claim (Debates, 374), Barton said that "intercolonial trade must be free or Federation is a mockery." See McMichael, "State Formation," and Cain and Hopkins, British Imperialism, for the background explaining this difference in the importance of economic issues in constitutional talk. Cain and Hopkins note that "the dependence of Australian prosperity after 1850 upon the international economy, and upon links with Britain in particular, was very marked" (p. 254) and that federation "was shaped in important particulars by the need to soothe the fears of British investors" (p. 253 n.85).
-
British Imperialism
-
-
Cain1
Hopkins2
-
259
-
-
5844312935
-
-
Debates, 671. The responses to Dobson's conservative political analysis might be said to define the range of political opinion of the time. Trenwith, the labour representative turned politician, asks quickly, "Does not bone and sinew represent wealth?" Deakin, the pre-eminent liberal, responds just as quickly and more assertively: "The mass of the people with us have a good deal of property."
-
Debates
, pp. 671
-
-
-
260
-
-
0004135073
-
-
Benedict Anderson, for example, notes the importance of blocked "creole pilgrimages" as "meaning-creating experiences" for nation-formation in colonies (imagined Communities, 53). Reinhard Bendix early stressed the importance of extra-national politics for early nationformation in Europe (see Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 266, 273. Studies of anti-colonial nationalisms in the twentieth century also, of course, treat them as primarily relational (see, for example Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse, 2nd ed. [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993]). For an extended argument for the importance of the world polity in generating the authority of the nation-state, see Thomas, Institutional Structure. By contrast, Smith, in an important claim which is challenged, at least for the settler colonies, by the evidence here, asserts that "the differentiating aspect follows from the integrative one" in identity formation (see Ethnic Origins, 97, and passim). I suggest here that nationality in settler colonies illustrates that what might be nationally integrative might be situational differentiation.
-
Imagined Communities
, pp. 53
-
-
Anderson, B.1
-
261
-
-
0003819419
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
Benedict Anderson, for example, notes the importance of blocked "creole pilgrimages" as "meaning-creating experiences" for nation-formation in colonies (imagined Communities, 53). Reinhard Bendix early stressed the importance of extra-national politics for early nationformation in Europe (see Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 266, 273. Studies of anti-colonial nationalisms in the twentieth century also, of course, treat them as primarily relational (see, for example Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse, 2nd ed. [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993]). For an extended argument for the importance of the world polity in generating the authority of the nation-state, see Thomas, Institutional Structure. By contrast, Smith, in an important claim which is challenged, at least for the settler colonies, by the evidence here, asserts that "the differentiating aspect follows from the integrative one" in identity formation (see Ethnic Origins, 97, and passim). I suggest here that nationality in settler colonies illustrates that what might be nationally integrative might be situational differentiation.
-
(1978)
Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule
, pp. 266
-
-
Bendix, R.1
-
262
-
-
0003921222
-
-
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
-
Benedict Anderson, for example, notes the importance of blocked "creole pilgrimages" as "meaning-creating experiences" for nation-formation in colonies (imagined Communities, 53). Reinhard Bendix early stressed the importance of extra-national politics for early nationformation in Europe (see Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 266, 273. Studies of anti-colonial nationalisms in the twentieth century also, of course, treat them as primarily relational (see, for example Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse, 2nd ed. [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993]). For an extended argument for the importance of the world polity in generating the authority of the nation-state, see Thomas, Institutional Structure. By contrast, Smith, in an important claim which is challenged, at least for the settler colonies, by the evidence here, asserts that "the differentiating aspect follows from the integrative one" in identity formation (see Ethnic Origins, 97, and passim). I suggest here that nationality in settler colonies illustrates that what might be nationally integrative might be situational differentiation.
-
(1993)
Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse, 2nd Ed.
-
-
Chatterjee, P.1
-
263
-
-
84935156360
-
-
Benedict Anderson, for example, notes the importance of blocked "creole pilgrimages" as "meaning-creating experiences" for nation-formation in colonies (imagined Communities, 53). Reinhard Bendix early stressed the importance of extra-national politics for early nationformation in Europe (see Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 266, 273. Studies of anti-colonial nationalisms in the twentieth century also, of course, treat them as primarily relational (see, for example Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse, 2nd ed. [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993]). For an extended argument for the importance of the world polity in generating the authority of the nation-state, see Thomas, Institutional Structure. By contrast, Smith, in an important claim which is challenged, at least for the settler colonies, by the evidence here, asserts that "the differentiating aspect follows from the integrative one" in identity formation (see Ethnic Origins, 97, and passim). I suggest here that nationality in settler colonies illustrates that what might be nationally integrative might be situational differentiation.
-
Institutional Structure
-
-
Thomas1
-
264
-
-
0040796694
-
-
and passim
-
Benedict Anderson, for example, notes the importance of blocked "creole pilgrimages" as "meaning-creating experiences" for nation-formation in colonies (imagined Communities, 53). Reinhard Bendix early stressed the importance of extra-national politics for early nationformation in Europe (see Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 266, 273. Studies of anti-colonial nationalisms in the twentieth century also, of course, treat them as primarily relational (see, for example Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse, 2nd ed. [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993]). For an extended argument for the importance of the world polity in generating the authority of the nation-state, see Thomas, Institutional Structure. By contrast, Smith, in an important claim which is challenged, at least for the settler colonies, by the evidence here, asserts that "the differentiating aspect follows from the integrative one" in identity formation (see Ethnic Origins, 97, and passim). I suggest here that nationality in settler colonies illustrates that what might be nationally integrative might be situational differentiation.
-
Ethnic Origins
, pp. 97
-
-
-
266
-
-
5844399327
-
-
Debates, 970, 971, 973, 977, 979.
-
Debates
, pp. 970
-
-
-
267
-
-
5844323757
-
-
July 5
-
Records, I:552 (July 5).
-
Records
, vol.1
, Issue.552
-
-
|