-
1
-
-
0141848921
-
-
trans. Rodney Livingston (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press)
-
Problems of Moral Philosophy, ed. Thomas Schröder, trans. Rodney Livingston (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001), 169.
-
(2001)
Problems of Moral Philosophy
, pp. 169
-
-
Schröder, T.1
-
2
-
-
0001778060
-
Conditions of an unforced consensus on human rights
-
ed. Joanne Bauer and Daniel Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
Another, perhaps less contentious, way of making the same point is that a human right is poised between a "soft right" and a "hard right." A soft right is a right that is supported by plausible arguments but not backed up with means of enforcement, perhaps not even conceived in terms of enforcement. A hard right, by contrast, is a right that is enforced or implemented by one kind of institutional means or another. Thus understood, a hard right need not be a legal right, strictly speaking, although legal codification is arguably the most dependable way of making a right hard, other things equal. For "alternative legal forms" of human rights implementation, see, for example, Charles Taylor, "Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights," in The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, ed. Joanne Bauer and Daniel Bell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 129-33.
-
(1999)
The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights
, pp. 129-133
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
3
-
-
0037577788
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
In this connection, I have found Raymond Geuss's analysis of the concept of human rights relevant and helpful. See, especially, his History and Illusion in Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 138-46.
-
(2001)
History and Illusion in Politics
, pp. 138-146
-
-
-
5
-
-
0004188742
-
-
ed. Walter Kaufmann, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Random House) aphorism 481.
-
See Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, ed. Walter Kaufmann, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Random House, 1967), aphorism 481. For excellent discussion of Nietzsche on this point, see Mark Warren, Nietzsche and Political Thought (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988), 115, 128.
-
(1967)
The Will to Power
-
-
Nietzsche, F.1
-
6
-
-
0004193221
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
See Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, ed. Walter Kaufmann, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Random House, 1967), aphorism 481. For excellent discussion of Nietzsche on this point, see Mark Warren, Nietzsche and Political Thought (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988), 115, 128.
-
(1988)
Nietzsche and Political Thought
, pp. 115
-
-
Warren, M.1
-
7
-
-
16344396359
-
-
note
-
This does not mean that we can interpret our experience in terms of agency just as we please. On the contrary, such interpretation is subject to material and social conditions of possibility, for there are conditions under which it is relatively easy to interpret our experience in terms of agency and other conditions under which such interpretation is difficult or even impossible. Further discussion of this issue is beyond the scope of this essay.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
84924989922
-
Introduction
-
ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
-
Michael Ignatieff et al., in Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), "Introduction," xviii-xix.
-
(2001)
Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry
-
-
Ignatieff, M.1
-
10
-
-
0004024838
-
-
Oxford; Oxford University Press
-
This line of argument takes further the suggestion, pursued by Ronald Dworkin and Will Kymlicka, that all plausible political theories, including all plausible justifications for human rights, share the ultimate value of equality even if they do not all invoke it explicitly; see Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Oxford; Oxford University Press, 2002), 3-4. As I see it, the value of equality in turn must make or imply some appeal to human agency as the deepest consideration. Thus, when Dworkin argues that all persons matter equally, the fuller, or underlying, idea must be that they all matter equally as agents, for only the idea of people mattering equally as agents is sufficient to generate not only his principle of equal importance but also his principle of special responsibility; see Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), 5-6.
-
(2002)
Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction, 2nd Ed.
, pp. 3-4
-
-
Kymlicka1
-
11
-
-
0004223708
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
This line of argument takes further the suggestion, pursued by Ronald Dworkin and Will Kymlicka, that all plausible political theories, including all plausible justifications for human rights, share the ultimate value of equality even if they do not all invoke it explicitly; see Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction, 2nd ed. (Oxford; Oxford University Press, 2002), 3-4. As I see it, the value of equality in turn must make or imply some appeal to human agency as the deepest consideration. Thus, when Dworkin argues that all persons matter equally, the fuller, or underlying, idea must be that they all matter equally as agents, for only the idea of people mattering equally as agents is sufficient to generate not only his principle of equal importance but also his principle of special responsibility; see Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), 5-6.
-
(2000)
Sovereign Virtue
, pp. 5-6
-
-
Dworkin1
-
12
-
-
16344373856
-
-
I borrowed this expression from Warren, Nietzsche and Political Thought, 59, and have learned much from Warren's discussion of agency.
-
Nietzsche and Political Thought
, pp. 59
-
-
-
13
-
-
16344376314
-
-
note
-
The distinction between freedom and identification is not a hard and fast one. In every society where agency through freedom is dominant, there also exists to some degree agency through identification: for example, identification with one's community, race, country, and so on. Likewise, in every society in which agency through identification is dominant, there must exist a minimal degree of agency through freedom; that is, attribution of power to oneself, even if this takes place within a framework of identification. Nevertheless, we can distinguish between an individualistic society (agency through freedom) and a collectivistic one (agency through identification) in terms of their respective dominant tendencies.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
84884042444
-
-
Michael Ignatieff's account of human rights, which treats the basis for human rights as the need to validate and enhance human agency and yet reduces human rights to negative liberties, seems to me a clear example of an implausible account of respect for individual agency or an implausible account of what such respect should mean in terms of human rights. If we take respect for human agency seriously, such respect clearly seems to require action to reduce to a minimum, at least significantly, those adverse effects on each individual's well-being that do not issue from his or her exercise of agency. Ignatieff stops well short of such a requirement. See Ignatieff, Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, esp. 55-57.
-
Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry
, pp. 55-57
-
-
Ignatieff1
-
16
-
-
16344395077
-
Henry Shue's well-known arguments against the drawing of such a distinction
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
See also Henry Shue's well-known arguments against the drawing of such a distinction, in Basic Rights (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980).
-
(1980)
Basic Rights
-
-
-
17
-
-
16344389471
-
-
note
-
In this sense, the conditions of agency include the conditions of subsistence but not the other way around, just as, say, Nietzsche's concept of the will to power encompasses Schopenhauer's concept of the will to live but not the other way around.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
16344365212
-
-
note
-
I owe the raising of this important question to one of the anonymous reviewers.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 386.
-
(1999)
A Theory of Justice, Rev. Ed.
, pp. 386
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
25
-
-
0012145190
-
-
Cambridge: Polity Press
-
On global inequality, I have learned a great deal from the writings of Thomas Pogge, especially his World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002). I believe most of what he has to say can be said as effectively or more so without using the concept of human rights.
-
(2002)
World Poverty and Human Rights
-
-
|