메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 33, Issue 2, 2005, Pages 158-188

"We feel our freedom" imagination and judgment in the thought of Hannah Arendt

Author keywords

Critique of Judgment; Hannah Arendt; Political freedom; Political judgment; Rhetoric

Indexed keywords


EID: 16244380508     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591704272958     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (126)

References (62)
  • 1
    • 2442502445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lanham, MD: Lexington Books
    • For accounts of politics as an aesthetic practice, see Kennan Ferguson, The Politics of Judgment: Aesthetics, Identity, and Political Theory (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 1999); and F. R. Ankersmit, Aesthetic Politics: Political Philosophy beyond Fact and Value (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1996).
    • (1999) The Politics of Judgment: Aesthetics, Identity, and Political Theory
    • Ferguson, K.1
  • 2
    • 0006949048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
    • For accounts of politics as an aesthetic practice, see Kennan Ferguson, The Politics of Judgment: Aesthetics, Identity, and Political Theory (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 1999); and F. R. Ankersmit, Aesthetic Politics: Political Philosophy beyond Fact and Value (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Aesthetic Politics: Political Philosophy Beyond Fact and Value
    • Ankersmit, F.R.1
  • 3
    • 0003949072 scopus 로고
    • trans. Werner S. Pluhar [Indianapolis, IN; Hackett], §8
    • The same point applies in reverse: For example, I may look at a rose and make a judgment of taste declaring it to be beautiful. But if I compare many singular roses and so arrive at the judgment, Roses in general are beautiful, then my judgment is not longer merely aesthetic but is a logical judgment based on an aesthetic one. (Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar [Indianapolis, IN; Hackett, 1987], §8, 59. Hereafter cited in the text as CJ with section and page numbers.)
    • (1987) Critique of Judgment , pp. 59
    • Kant, I.1
  • 4
    • 0009083852 scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt's communications concept of power
    • ed. by Lewis Hinchman and Sandra Hinchman (Albany: State University of New York Press)
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Hannah Arendt's Communications Concept of Power," Hannah Arendt, Critical Essays, ed. by Lewis Hinchman and Sandra Hinchman (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), 225. For a similar argument, see Albrecht Wellmer, "Hannah Arendt on Judgment: The Unwritten Doctrine of Reason," Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt, ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), 165-181; quotation is from p. 169.
    • (1994) Hannah Arendt, Critical Essays , pp. 225
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 5
    • 16244401525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt on judgment: The unwritten doctrine of reason
    • ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield)
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Hannah Arendt's Communications Concept of Power," Hannah Arendt, Critical Essays, ed. by Lewis Hinchman and Sandra Hinchman (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), 225. For a similar argument, see Albrecht Wellmer, "Hannah Arendt on Judgment: The Unwritten Doctrine of Reason," Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt, ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), 165-181; quotation is from p. 169.
    • (2001) Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt , pp. 165-181
    • Wellmer, A.1
  • 6
    • 0001807516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretive essay: Hannah Arendt on judging
    • Hannah Arendt, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • Ronald Beiner, "Interpretive Essay: Hannah Arendt on Judging," in Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. by Ronald Beiner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), 36.
    • (1982) Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy , pp. 36
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 7
    • 0004130019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Dana Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 72. For another defense of Arendt contra Habermas, see Lisa Jane Disch, Hannah Arendt and the Limits of Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994).
    • (1996) Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political , pp. 72
    • Villa, D.1
  • 8
    • 0004318989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • See Dana Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 72. For another defense of Arendt contra Habermas, see Lisa Jane Disch, Hannah Arendt and the Limits of Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994).
    • (1994) Hannah Arendt and the Limits of Philosophy
    • Disch, L.J.1
  • 9
    • 16244390735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. by G. H. Wright, R. Rhees, and G. E. M. Anscombe (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), I. Hereafter cited as RFM
    • Ludwig Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, ed. by G. H. Wright, R. Rhees, and G. E. M. Anscombe (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), I, 121. Hereafter cited as RFM.
    • (1996) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics , pp. 121
    • Wittgenstein, L.1
  • 11
    • 33749417407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage
    • Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1996), 188-189. Benhabib finds a "normative lacuna in Arendt's thought" and the turn to the third, rather than the second, Critique to be one more "disturbing" example of Arendt's refusal or failure to provide the "normative dimension of the political" (Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism, 193, 194).
    • (1996) The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt , pp. 188-189
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 12
    • 66549096234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seyla Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1996), 188-189. Benhabib finds a "normative lacuna in Arendt's thought" and the turn to the third, rather than the second, Critique to be one more "disturbing" example of Arendt's refusal or failure to provide the "normative dimension of the political" (Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism, 193, 194).
    • The Reluctant Modernism , pp. 193
    • Benhabib1
  • 14
    • 0001807516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Wellmer, "Hannah Arendt on Judgment," 166; and Beiner, "Interpretative Essay," 134.
    • Interpretative Essay , pp. 134
    • Beiner1
  • 15
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고
    • trans. and ed. by Paul Guyer and Alan W. Wood (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press)
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. by Paul Guyer and Alan W. Wood (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1977), B171.
    • (1977) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 16
    • 16244417372 scopus 로고
    • Willing
    • New York: Harcourt Brace
    • Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind, 1-vol. ed., vol. 2, "Willing" (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1978), 28-34.
    • (1978) The Life of the Mind, 1-vol. Ed. , vol.2 , pp. 28-34
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 17
    • 0002967558 scopus 로고
    • Understanding and politics
    • ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace), quotation is from p. 325, n7
    • Hannah Arendt, "Understanding and Politics," Essays in Understanding, 1930-1954, ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1994), 307-327; quotation is from p. 325, n7. "The loss of [inherited] standards," Arendt observes, "is only a catastrophe for the moral [and political] world when one assumes that individuals are not capable of judging things in themselves [...] one cannot expect of them anything more than the application of known rules," Hannah Arendt, Was ist Politik? ed. by Ursula Ludz (Munich: Piper Verlag, 1993), 22. Hereafter, this is cited in the text as WIP. All translations are my own.
    • (1994) Essays in Understanding, 1930-1954 , pp. 307-327
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 18
    • 16244386728 scopus 로고
    • ed. by Ursula Ludz (Munich: Piper Verlag), Hereafter, this is cited in the text as WIP. All translations are my own
    • Hannah Arendt, "Understanding and Politics," Essays in Understanding, 1930-1954, ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1994), 307-327; quotation is from p. 325, n7. "The loss of [inherited] standards," Arendt observes, "is only a catastrophe for the moral [and political] world when one assumes that individuals are not capable of judging things in themselves [...] one cannot expect of them anything more than the application of known rules," Hannah Arendt, Was ist Politik? ed. by Ursula Ludz (Munich: Piper Verlag, 1993), 22. Hereafter, this is cited in the text as WIP. All translations are my own.
    • (1993) Was Ist Politik? , pp. 22
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 19
    • 16244376061 scopus 로고
    • Thinking and moral considerations
    • Autumn see especially p. 436
    • In Arendt's view, totalitarianism is the paradigmatic event that strains our faculty of judgment, for "the death factories erected in the heart of Europe" confront us with an unprecedented sense of meaninglessness. How are we to judge an event that reveals the ruin of "our categories of thought and standards of judgment?" (Arendt, "Understanding and Politics," 313). If we stubbornly cling to rules that no longer speak to our experience, she argues, it is because what we have gotten used to is not so much the substance of any particular rule, but the fact of having rules with which to judge. Hannah Arendt, "Thinking and Moral Considerations," Social Research: Fiftieth Anniversary Issue 38, no. 3 (Autumn 1971): 416-446; see especially p. 436.
    • (1971) Social Research: Fiftieth Anniversary Issue , vol.38 , Issue.3 , pp. 416-446
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 20
    • 16244402155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the relationship of judgments (Urteile) to prejudices (Vorurteile), see WIP, 17-23.
    • WIP , pp. 17-23
  • 21
    • 6344259915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • This point is emphasized in Samuel Fleischacker, A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999). Fleischaker, too, sees freedom as deeply connected to the development of the judging faculty. In contrast to Arendt, however, he develops a theory of judgment from within the liberal tradition.
    • (1999) A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith
    • Fleischacker, S.1
  • 22
    • 2542637441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Arendt, the development of a freedom-affirming faculty of judgment requires more than an acknowledgment of contingency. Although she fiercely defends contingency against the Western philosophical tradition's equally fierce defense of necessity, she is adamant that we need to be able to judge new political objects and events. We need to be able to judge them in their freedom, that is, produce a sense of coherence that is neither given in our pre-understanding nor exhausted by the application of known concepts. Merely affirming the contingency of objects and events does not address the quest for meaning that is at the heart of the judging faculty. And it does not take seriously the ever-present temptation, when confronted with "the haphazard character of the particular," to assume a stance devoid of care for the world, as if "any order, any necessity, any meaning you wish to impose will do" (Arendt, "The Concept of History," 89).
    • The Concept of History , pp. 89
    • Arendt1
  • 23
    • 0003861944 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • "The limits of a decisionistic treatment of practical questions are overcome as soon as argumentation is expected to test the generalizability of interests, instead of being resigned to an impenetrable pluralism of apparently ultimate value orientations," writes Habermas. "It is not the fact of this pluralism that is here disputed, but the assertion that it is impossible to separate by argumentation generalizable interests from those that remain particular." Citing this passage, Richard Bernstein finds a parallel in Arendt's claim that "judgment must liberate itself from 'subjective private conditions'." Richard Bernstein, Between Objectivism and Relativism: Science Hermeneutics and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983), 220. But Arendt's approach to the plurality of opinions is different from that of Habermas. For her, this plurality is something to preserve, not overcome, in the exercise of judgment. I examine this difference in Linda M. G. Zerilli, Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005), chap. 4.
    • (1983) Between Objectivism and Relativism: Science Hermeneutics and Praxis , pp. 220
    • Bernstein, R.1
  • 24
    • 16244413111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Chicago: Chicago University Press), chap. 4
    • "The limits of a decisionistic treatment of practical questions are overcome as soon as argumentation is expected to test the generalizability of interests, instead of being resigned to an impenetrable pluralism of apparently ultimate value orientations," writes Habermas. "It is not the fact of this pluralism that is here disputed, but the assertion that it is impossible to separate by argumentation generalizable interests from those that remain particular." Citing this passage, Richard Bernstein finds a parallel in Arendt's claim that "judgment must liberate itself from 'subjective private conditions'." Richard Bernstein, Between Objectivism and Relativism: Science Hermeneutics and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983), 220. But Arendt's approach to the plurality of opinions is different from that of Habermas. For her, this plurality is something to preserve, not overcome, in the exercise of judgment. I examine this difference in Linda M. G. Zerilli, Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005), chap. 4.
    • (2005) Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom
    • Zerilli, M.G.1
  • 26
    • 0004152399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: Chicago University Press
    • Who someone is, by contrast with what she is (e.g., a white middle-class American woman, qualities she necessarily shares with others like her), is the unique disclosure of human action that emerges in the stories and other human artifacts that speak of it. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1989), 181, 182.
    • (1989) The Human Condition , pp. 181
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 27
    • 0012220806 scopus 로고
    • The concept of history
    • [New York: Penguin], quotation is from p. 51. Hereafter cited in the text as CH
    • This Homeric impartiality is still the highest type of objectivity we know. Not only does it leave behind the common interest in one's side and one's own people which, up to our own days, characterizes almost all national historiography, but it also discards the alternative of victory or defeat, which moderns have felt expresses the 'objective' judgment of history itself. (Hannah Arendt, "The Concept of History," Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought [New York: Penguin, 1993], 41-90; quotation is from p. 51. Hereafter cited in the text as CH.)
    • (1993) Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought , pp. 41-90
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 28
    • 84855694086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Julie Rose (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press)
    • Jacques Rancière, Dis-agreement: Politics and Philosophy, trans. Julie Rose (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999), 56.
    • (1999) Dis-agreement: Politics and Philosophy , pp. 56
    • Rancière, J.1
  • 29
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)
    • Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms; Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), 20; and Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), 204. Habermas accuses Derrida, among other "postmodern" thinkers, of foregrounding the rhetorical capacity of language over its problem-solving capacity.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms; Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy , pp. 20
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 30
    • 0003976110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms; Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), 20; and Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), 204. Habermas accuses Derrida, among other "postmodern" thinkers, of foregrounding the rhetorical capacity of language over its problem-solving capacity.
    • (1987) The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures , pp. 204
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 31
    • 0007634481 scopus 로고
    • (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press), Hereafter cited in the text as RP
    • Emesto Grassi, Rhetoric as Philosophy: The Humanist Tradition (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1980), 26. Hereafter cited in the text as RP.
    • (1980) Rhetoric as Philosophy: The Humanist Tradition , pp. 26
    • Grassi, E.1
  • 33
    • 84860093516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §14
    • "The picture forces itself on us. [...]' It is very interesting that pictures do force themselves on us. And if that were not so, how could such a sentence as 'What's done cannot be undone' mean anything to us?" (RFM, I §14). Wittgenstein gives a close reading of the picture of "the machine as symbol," which lies at the origin of the language game of logical necessity, our sense of the "logical must" (ibid., I, §§121-122).
    • RFM , vol.1
  • 34
    • 84860099517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §§121-122
    • "The picture forces itself on us. [...]' It is very interesting that pictures do force themselves on us. And if that were not so, how could such a sentence as 'What's done cannot be undone' mean anything to us?" (RFM, I §14). Wittgenstein gives a close reading of the picture of "the machine as symbol," which lies at the origin of the language game of logical necessity, our sense of the "logical must" (ibid., I, §§121-122).
    • RFM , vol.1
  • 35
    • 16244417961 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Anton Hain
    • Ernesto Grassi, Die unerhörte Metapher (Frankfurt am Main: Anton Hain, 1992), 29.
    • (1992) Die Unerhörte Metapher , pp. 29
    • Grassi, E.1
  • 36
    • 84883594428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §18
    • This necessity is of a special kind. It is not a theoretical objective necessity, allowing us to cognize a priori that everyone will feel this liking for the object I call beautiful. Nor is it a practical objective necessity, where, through concepts of a pure rational will that serves freely acting beings as a rule, this liking is the necessary consequence of an objective law and means nothing other than that one absolutely (without any further aim) ought to act in a certain way. (Kant, CJ, §18, p. 85)
    • CJ , pp. 85
    • Kant1
  • 38
    • 84883594428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §34
    • See Kant, CJ, §34, p. 149, See also Stanley Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), 88.
    • CJ , pp. 149
    • Kant1
  • 39
    • 0004000126 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Kant, CJ, §34, p. 149, See also Stanley Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), 88.
    • (1976) Must We Mean What We Say? , pp. 88
    • Cavell, S.1
  • 40
    • 0004284697 scopus 로고
    • trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press)
    • Jean-François Lyotard, Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime (Kant's "Critique of Judgment," §§23-29), trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994). Lyotard finds in Kantian judgments of taste a resistance to reaching consensus through the giving of proofs. Although this is correct, Lyotard tends to exclude the possibility of coming to any agreement whatsoever. He thus turns to the aesthetic of the sublime, in which the faculties of imagination and reason are caught in a Wiederstreit, a quarrel with no possible resolution.
    • (1994) Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime (Kant's "Critique of Judgment," §§;23-29)
    • Lyotard, J.-F.1
  • 41
    • 84883594428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §32
    • Kant excludes community standards as the basis for judgment. [W]henever a subject offers a judgment as proof of his taste [concerning some object], we demand that he judge for himself; he should not have to grope about among other people's judgments. [...] [T]o make other people's judgments the basis determining one's own would be heteronomy. (Kant, CJ, §32, pp. 145-146) This is the basis for Hans-George Gadamer's controversial claim that the Kantian sensus communis marks an unfortunate departure from the tradition of Cicero, Vico, and Shaftesbury, for whom common sense is a way of knowing based in the moral and civic community. Hans-George Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 1989), pt. 1, chap. 2. See also Ernesto Grassi, "The Priority of Common Sense and Imagination: Vico's Philosophical Relevance Today," Social Research 43 (1976): 553-580; quotation is from p. 560. For a critique of the Gadamerian view, see Lyotard, Lessons. Arendt's compressed discussion in LKPP (pp. 70-72) understands common sense neither as an a priori principle (Kant) nor as a communal mode of knowledge (Gadamer), but simply as a way of marking what is public and communicable rather than private.
    • CJ , pp. 145-146
    • Kant1
  • 42
    • 0004225610 scopus 로고
    • trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum), pt. 1, chap. 2
    • Kant excludes community standards as the basis for judgment. [W]henever a subject offers a judgment as proof of his taste [concerning some object], we demand that he judge for himself; he should not have to grope about among other people's judgments. [...] [T]o make other people's judgments the basis determining one's own would be heteronomy. (Kant, CJ, §32, pp. 145-146) This is the basis for Hans-George Gadamer's controversial claim that the Kantian sensus communis marks an unfortunate departure from the tradition of Cicero, Vico, and Shaftesbury, for whom common sense is a way of knowing based in the moral and civic community. Hans-George Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 1989), pt. 1, chap. 2. See also Ernesto Grassi, "The Priority of Common Sense and Imagination: Vico's Philosophical Relevance Today," Social Research 43 (1976): 553-580; quotation is from p. 560. For a critique of the Gadamerian view, see Lyotard, Lessons. Arendt's compressed discussion in LKPP (pp. 70-72) understands common sense neither as an a priori principle (Kant) nor as a communal mode of knowledge (Gadamer), but simply as a way of marking what is public and communicable rather than private.
    • (1989) Truth and Method
    • Gadamer, H.-G.1
  • 43
    • 84925906838 scopus 로고
    • The priority of common sense and imagination: Vico's philosophical relevance today
    • quotation is from p. 560
    • Kant excludes community standards as the basis for judgment. [W]henever a subject offers a judgment as proof of his taste [concerning some object], we demand that he judge for himself; he should not have to grope about among other people's judgments. [...] [T]o make other people's judgments the basis determining one's own would be heteronomy. (Kant, CJ, §32, pp. 145-146) This is the basis for Hans-George Gadamer's controversial claim that the Kantian sensus communis marks an unfortunate departure from the tradition of Cicero, Vico, and Shaftesbury, for whom common sense is a way of knowing based in the moral and civic community. Hans-George Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 1989), pt. 1, chap. 2. See also Ernesto Grassi, "The Priority of Common Sense and Imagination: Vico's Philosophical Relevance Today," Social Research 43 (1976): 553-580; quotation is from p. 560. For a critique of the Gadamerian view, see Lyotard, Lessons. Arendt's compressed discussion in LKPP (pp. 70-72) understands common sense neither as an a priori principle (Kant) nor as a communal mode of knowledge (Gadamer), but simply as a way of marking what is public and communicable rather than private.
    • (1976) Social Research , vol.43 , pp. 553-580
    • Grassi, E.1
  • 44
    • 16244414186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant excludes community standards as the basis for judgment. [W]henever a subject offers a judgment as proof of his taste [concerning some object], we demand that he judge for himself; he should not have to grope about among other people's judgments. [...] [T]o make other people's judgments the basis determining one's own would be heteronomy. (Kant, CJ, §32, pp. 145-146) This is the basis for Hans-George Gadamer's controversial claim that the Kantian sensus communis marks an unfortunate departure from the tradition of Cicero, Vico, and Shaftesbury, for whom common sense is a way of knowing based in the moral and civic community. Hans-George Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 1989), pt. 1, chap. 2. See also Ernesto Grassi, "The Priority of Common Sense and Imagination: Vico's Philosophical Relevance Today," Social Research 43 (1976): 553-580; quotation is from p. 560. For a critique of the Gadamerian view, see Lyotard, Lessons. Arendt's compressed discussion in LKPP (pp. 70-72) understands common sense neither as an a priori principle (Kant) nor as a communal mode of knowledge (Gadamer), but simply as a way of marking what is public and communicable rather than private.
    • Lessons
    • Lyotard1
  • 45
    • 16244368990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judging human action
    • ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield), quotation is from p. 154. Dostal accuses Arendt of losing sight of the importance of rationality in Kant's thought
    • Kant quoted in Robert J. Dostal, "Judging Human Action," Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt, ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), 139-164; quotation is from p. 154. Dostal accuses Arendt of losing sight of the importance of rationality in Kant's thought.
    • (2001) Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt , pp. 139-164
    • Dostal, R.J.1
  • 47
    • 16244421893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The task of aesthetic and teleological judgment, as Kant explains, is to judge without a concept and thus the notion of a "purpose" (end [Zweck]). But judgment is only possible if we assume that nature has an order that we can discern and could potentially cognize, hence a purposiveness (finality [Zweckmässigkeit]). Thus aesthetic judgments have "finality without an end" or "purposiveness without a purpose" (Zweckmässigkeit ohne Zweck).
  • 49
    • 84883594428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §40
    • This process is the "enlargement of the mind," in which "we compare our judgment not so much with the actual as rather with the merely possible judgments of others, and [thus] put ourselves in the position of everyone else" (Kant, CJ, §40, p. 160). Like Kant, Arendt does not exclude the role that the actual judgments of other people might play in our own. But neither does she dispute his claim that enlarged thought is not based on re-presenting to oneself opinions one has heard or of transposing oneself into the place of another person. See LKPP, 43.
    • CJ , pp. 160
    • Kant1
  • 50
    • 16244398530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This process is the "enlargement of the mind," in which "we compare our judgment not so much with the actual as rather with the merely possible judgments of others, and [thus] put ourselves in the position of everyone else" (Kant, CJ, §40, p. 160). Like Kant, Arendt does not exclude the role that the actual judgments of other people might play in our own. But neither does she dispute his claim that enlarged thought is not based on re-presenting to oneself opinions one has heard or of transposing oneself into the place of another person. See LKPP, 43.
    • LKPP , pp. 43
  • 52
    • 16244385498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Asymmetrical reciprocity: On moral respect, wonder, and enlarged thought
    • ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedelsky (New York: Rowman & Littlefield), quotation is from p. 225
    • Iris Marion Young, "Asymmetrical Reciprocity: On Moral Respect, Wonder, and Enlarged Thought," Judgment, Imagination, and Politics, ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedelsky (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), 205-228; quotation is from p. 225.
    • (2001) Judgment, Imagination, and Politics , pp. 205-228
    • Young, I.M.1
  • 54
    • 16244395979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rereading Hannah Arendt's Kant lectures
    • ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield), quotation is from p. 97
    • Ronald Beiner, "Rereading Hannah Arendt's Kant Lectures," Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt, ed. by Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedlesky (Boston: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), 91-102; quotation is from p. 97. Beiner, Young, and Disch share the view that Arendt was mistaken to turn to Kant, for she is really interested in empirical sociability as the basis for judgment and he is not. I find it misleading to ascribe to Arendt an empirical conception of sensus communis, as if the universal voice were the result of a vote, and it is conversely misleading to assert that, for Kant's transcendental conception of sensus communis, nothing empirical matters. Kant makes numerous gestures toward the actual social practices of judgment, not to dismiss these as totally irrelevant to what an aesthetic judgment is, but to discern the existence of our mutual attunement.
    • (2001) Judgment, Imagination, and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt , pp. 91-102
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 55
    • 16244412794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This limited view of imagination as empirical and reproductive is tied to certain suppositions about the status of normative political claims and the kind of rationality that is proper to politics, both of which are central to Habermas's discourse ethics: (1) that political claims are cognitive and can be treated like claims to truth; and (2) that the justification of claims requires that speakers engage in an actual practice of argumentative justification. Even defenders of Arendt's noncognitive account of political judgment against Habermas's charge of incoherence (e.g., Lisa Disch) take for granted (2) because they never really find a way to counter (1), beholden as they are to the validity problematic that defines our understanding of politics.
  • 56
    • 0010050303 scopus 로고
    • What remains? The language remains
    • ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace), quotation is from p. 20
    • Hannah Arendt, "What Remains? The Language Remains," Essays in Understanding, 1930-1954, ed. by Jerome Kohn (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1994), 1-23; quotation is from p. 20.
    • (1994) Essays in Understanding, 1930-1954 , pp. 1-23
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 57
  • 58
    • 16244419257 scopus 로고
    • Rephrasing the political with Kant and Lyotard: From aesthetic to political judgments
    • (Autumn) quotation is from p. 82
    • David Carroll, "Rephrasing the Political with Kant and Lyotard: From Aesthetic to Political Judgments," Diacritics 14, no. 3 (Autumn 1984): 73-88; quotation is from p. 82.
    • (1984) Diacritics , vol.14 , Issue.3 , pp. 73-88
    • Carroll, D.1
  • 60
    • 0004337106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beiner argues that Arendt's earliest writings on judgment (e.g., "The Crisis in Culture" and "Truth and Politics") reflect her concern with the actual dialogic activity of judging citizens. In her later work, Arendt describes a solitary judging subject, who "weighs the possible judgments of an imagined Other, not the actual judgments of real interlocutors" (ibid., 92).
    • Interpretive Essay , pp. 92
  • 61
    • 16244414186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lyotard, Lessons, 18. For a similar critique, see David Carroll, "Community after Devastation: Culture, Politics, and the 'Public Space'," Politics, Theory, and Contemporary Culture, ed. by Mark Poster (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 159-196.
    • Lessons , pp. 18
    • Lyotard1
  • 62
    • 85021929124 scopus 로고
    • Community after devastation: Culture, politics, and the 'public space'
    • ed. by Mark Poster (New York: Columbia University Press)
    • Lyotard, Lessons, 18. For a similar critique, see David Carroll, "Community after Devastation: Culture, Politics, and the 'Public Space'," Politics, Theory, and Contemporary Culture, ed. by Mark Poster (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 159-196.
    • (1993) Politics, Theory, and Contemporary Culture , pp. 159-196
    • Carroll, D.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.