메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 1, 1997, Pages 401-432

Cause and some positive causal impact

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 15244359043     PISSN: 15208583     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (8)

References (28)
  • 1
    • 0004271399 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press
    • David Lewis, Counterfactuals, Harvard University Press, 1973
    • (1973) Counterfactuals
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 2
    • 0000738885 scopus 로고
    • Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow
    • David Lewis, "Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow", Nous 13 (1979), 418-46
    • (1979) Nous , vol.13 , pp. 418-446
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 5
    • 34249767330 scopus 로고
    • my approach regarding backtracking, compare my Counterfactual Ambiguities, True Premises and Knowledge
    • For my approach regarding backtracking, compare my "Counterfactual Ambiguities, True Premises and Knowledge", Synthese 100 (1994), 133-164
    • (1994) Synthese , vol.100 , pp. 133-164
  • 6
    • 79958635506 scopus 로고
    • See Lewis 1986, p. 176-7
    • (1986) Lewis , pp. 176-177
  • 7
    • 0002183731 scopus 로고
    • his Causality Without Counterfactuals
    • I limit my discussion here to Salmon's book. Salmon recently changed his position by abandoning the counterfactual component of his process theory and adopting a conserved quantities account; see his "Causality Without Counterfactuals", Philosophy of Science 61 (1994) 297-312
    • (1994) Philosophy of Science , vol.61 , pp. 297-312
  • 8
    • 0000795862 scopus 로고
    • Wesley Salmon's Process Theory of Causality and the Conserved Quantity Theory
    • Salmon was responding to a constructive (as well as critical) rejoinder by Dowe (and earlier critiques). Dowe's account replaces Salmon's definitions of MT and CI by concise definitions which appeal to the notion of a conserved quantity and do not invoke counterfactuals. See Phil Dowe, "Wesley Salmon's Process Theory of Causality and the Conserved Quantity Theory", Philosophy of Science 59 (1992), 195-216
    • (1992) Philosophy of Science , vol.59 , pp. 195-216
    • Dowe, P.1
  • 10
    • 79958652389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For my analysis of the Bizet-Verdi example, see
    • For my analysis of the Bizet-Verdi example, see ATC, p. 237
    • , vol.237
    • ATC, P.1
  • 11
    • 84928458315 scopus 로고
    • Critical Notice: Wesley Salmon's Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World
    • Cf. also J. Fetzer, "Critical Notice: Wesley Salmon's Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World", Philosophy of Science, 54: 597-610, 1987
    • (1987) Philosophy of Science , vol.54 , pp. 597-610
    • Fetzer, J.1
  • 15
    • 79958502304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 2, sec. VIII
    • Cf. ATC, ch. 2, sec. VIII
    • ATC, C.1
  • 19
    • 29144457807 scopus 로고
    • We need to require causal relevance for the relation of some positive causal impact since otherwise, even if there is a strict increaser for A and C (see below), there may still be a causal cutter, i.e., an event that cuts off the would-be causal connection between A and C and renders A causally irrelevant to C. Here I rely on the probabilistic analysis I offered for the notion of causal irrelevance; see my "Transitivity and Preemption of Causal Impact", Philosophical Studies, 64 (1991), pp. 125-160
    • (1991) Philosophical Studies , vol.64 , pp. 125-160
    • Impact, C.1
  • 24
    • 84954746802 scopus 로고
    • p. 220
    • The extension of the definition of strict increaser here (and of strict decreaser as per the previous note) constitutes a change in the terminology I used in earlier writings, where I suggested the notion of a clincher (increaser-clincher and decreaser-clincher, respectively). Though the current usage is simpler for my purposes here, the difference is merely terminological. Cf. my "Overall Positive Causal Impact", Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (1994), pp. 205-228, especially p. 220
    • (1994) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.24 , pp. 205-228
    • Impact, C.1
  • 25
    • 79958549630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, Lewis, op. cit., p. 179
    • Lewis1
  • 26
    • 61149697359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lewis's related observation
    • Cf. Lewis's related observation, Philosophical Papers, vol. II, p. 176
    • Philosophical Papers , vol.2 , pp. 176
    • Cf1
  • 27
    • 79958507798 scopus 로고
    • The reasoning underlying this comment was expanded on in my "Counterfactuals and Causal Relevance
    • featuring in particular the possibility of causal breakers
    • The reasoning underlying this comment was expanded on in my "Counterfactuals and Causal Relevance", Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 72, 4 (1991), 314-337 (featuring in particular the possibility of causal breakers)
    • (1991) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.72 , Issue.4 , pp. 314-337
  • 28
    • 79958609669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g, on my approach
    • E.g., aipi or aipd, on my approach
    • aipi or aipd


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.