메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 64, Issue 1, 2002, Pages 27-56

Aristotle's great-souled man

(1)  Howland, Jacob a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 1442326222     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500031600     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (30)

References (58)
  • 1
    • 77954074826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless otherwise indicated, all parenthetical citations refer to book, chapter, and line numbers in theNicomachean Ethics (EN), and all translations are my own
    • Unless otherwise indicated, all parenthetical citations refer to book, chapter, and line numbers in theNicomachean Ethics (EN), and all translations are my own.
  • 2
    • 77952089305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris: Librarie Philosophique J. Vrin
    • See R. A. Gauthier, Magnanimite (Paris: Librarie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1951).
    • (1951) Magnanimite
    • Gauthier, R.A.1
  • 3
    • 77954079554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EN 4.3 is the fourth longest of the book's 116 chapters (as measured by number of lines in the Bekker collation); only 10.9,5.5, and 4.1 are longer
    • EN 4.3 is the fourth longest of the book's 116 chapters (as measured by number of lines in the Bekker collation); only 10.9,5.5, and 4.1 are longer.
  • 5
    • 77954078522 scopus 로고
    • Louvain: Publications Universitaires
    • and R. A. Gauthier and J. Y. Joit,L'Ethique a Nicomaque (Louvain: Publications Universitaires, 1970), vol. 2., pt. 1, pp. 272-98.
    • (1970) L'Ethique A Nicomaque , vol.2 , Issue.PART 1 , pp. 272-298
    • Gauthier, R.A.1    Joit, J.Y.2
  • 6
    • 77954053759 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, Gauthier and Jolif follow an interpretative tradition going back to the Greek philosopher Aspasius (L'tthique a Nicomaque, pp. 272-73)
    • Cf. J. A. Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1892), 1: 334-346 Gauthier and Jolif follow an interpretative tradition going back to the Greek philosopher Aspasius (L'tthique a Nicomaque, pp. 272-73).
    • (1892) Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle , vol.1 , pp. 334-346
    • Stewart, J.A.1
  • 7
    • 84965981739 scopus 로고
    • 'Magnanimity' in Aristotle's ethics
    • W. F. R. Hardie, "'Magnanimity' in Aristotle's Ethics," Phronesis 23 (1978): 63-79;
    • (1978) Phronesis , vol.23 , pp. 63-79
    • Hardie, W.F.R.1
  • 8
    • 84985316787 scopus 로고
    • Common sense and uncommon virtue
    • Nancy Sherman, "Common Sense and Uncommon Virtue," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1988): 97-114.
    • (1988) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.13 , pp. 97-114
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 9
    • 0004296635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province, New York: Benziger Bros.
    • St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Bros., 1948), II-II.129-133
    • (1948) Summa Theologica
    • St. Thomas Aquinas1
  • 10
    • 77954063034 scopus 로고
    • trans. C. I. Litzinger, Chicago: Henry Regnery, lectures 8-11
    • and Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics, trans. C. I. Litzinger (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1964), vol.1, lectures 8-11;
    • (1964) Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics , vol.1
  • 12
    • 77954050087 scopus 로고
    • Coriolanus and Aristotle's magnanimous man reconsidered
    • John Alvis, "Coriolanus and Aristotle's Magnanimous Man Reconsidered," Interpretation 7.3 (1978): 4-28;
    • (1978) Interpretation , pp. 4-28
    • Alvis, J.1
  • 13
    • 10644287265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christianity, magnanimity, and statesmanship
    • Holloway follows Thomas in arguing that Aristotelian megalopsuchia is not incompatible with Christianity (cf. Summa Theologica, II-II.129.3 with 161.2)
    • Carson Holloway, "Christianity, Magnanimity, and Statesmanship," Review of Politics 61 (1999): 581-604. Holloway follows Thomas in arguing that Aristotelian megalopsuchia is not incompatible with Christianity (cf. Summa Theologica, II-II.129.3 with 161.2).
    • (1999) Review of Politics , vol.61 , pp. 581-604
    • Holloway, C.1
  • 14
    • 77954053492 scopus 로고
    • The former group includes Sherman, Hardie, and Harry V. Jaffa, Thomism and Aristotelianism, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sir David Ross, however, states that EN 4.3 "simply betrays somewhat nakedly the self-absorption which is the bad side of Aristotle's ethics" (Aristotle [London: Methuen and Co., 1977], p. 208
    • The former group includes Sherman, Hardie, and Harry V. Jaffa, Thomism and Aristotelianism: A Study of the Commentary by Thomas Aquinas on the Nicomachean Ethics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952). Sir David Ross, however, states that EN 4.3 "simply betrays somewhat nakedly the self-absorption which is the bad side of Aristotle's ethics" (Aristotle [London: Methuen and Co., 1977], p. 208);
    • (1952) A Study of the Commentary by Thomas Aquinas on the Nicomachean Ethics
  • 15
    • 77954077324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the critical remarks by Maclntyre and Russell cited
    • cf. the critical remarks by Maclntyre and Russell cited by Hardie, "Magnanimity," p. 65.
    • Magnanimity , pp. 65
    • Hardie1
  • 17
    • 0003749789 scopus 로고
    • Phronesis, which makes its possessors "able to contemplate the good for themselves and for human beings in general" (1140b9-10), involves the capacity imaginatively to "re-enact the agent's point of view and to consider what it is like for the agent to do that action in that context", Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Phronesis, which makes its possessors "able to contemplate the good for themselves and for human beings in general" (1140b9-10), involves the capacity imaginatively to "re-enact the agent's point of view and to consider what it is like for the agent to do that action in that context" (Nancy Sherman, The Fabric of Character: Aristotle's Theory of Virtue [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989], p. 36).
    • (1989) The Fabric of Character: Aristotle's Theory of Virtue , pp. 36
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 18
    • 0004240798 scopus 로고
    • An. Post. 97bl6-25, trans. Jonathan Barnes, Oxford: Clarendon Press, slightly modified
    • An. Post. 97bl6-25, trans. Jonathan Barnes, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), slightly modified.
    • (1975) Aristotle's Posterior Analytics
  • 19
    • 0041135915 scopus 로고
    • 1328a8-16, translation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, slightly modified
    • 1328a8-16, translation of Carnes Lord, Aristotle: The Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), slightly modified.
    • (1984) Aristotle: The Politics
    • Lord, C.1
  • 20
    • 77954043645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first is from Euripides, and the second from an unknown author, n. 23
    • The first is from Euripides, and the second from an unknown author (Lord, Politics, p. 267 n. 23).
    • Politics , pp. 267
    • Lord1
  • 22
    • 77954070512 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's crowning virtue
    • This consideration does not deter Neil Cooper, who proposes that Aristotle was engaged in "a vain attempt to produce an impossible unitary account of megalopsuchia"
    • This consideration does not deter Neil Cooper, who proposes that Aristotle was engaged in "a vain attempt to produce an impossible unitary account of megalopsuchia" ("Aristotle's Crowning Virtue" Apeiron 22 [1989]: 192).
    • (1989) Apeiron , vol.22 , pp. 192
  • 23
    • 77954061511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On his love of honor, see Plutarch Lysander 18.1-5, 19.1, 23.5; on his intolerance of insult (hubris), 6.5-7; on his emulous nature, 34.3-5
    • On his love of honor, see Plutarch Lysander 18.1-5, 19.1, 23.5; on his intolerance of insult (hubris), 6.5-7; on his emulous nature, 34.3-5
  • 24
    • 77954043172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plutarch Lys. 30.1-2; cf. Plato/lpo/. 23b-c, 31b-c, 36d, with XenophonMem. 1.6
    • Plutarch Lys. 30.1-2; cf. Plato/lpo/. 23b-c, 31b-c, 36d, with XenophonMem. 1.6.
  • 25
    • 0003548526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Plato's Gorgias, where Socrates is criticized by Callicles for his lack of concern with what others think of him (484c-486d). Socrates' tolerance of insult becomes legendary in the later tradition, 35-36
    • Cf. Plato's Gorgias, where Socrates is criticized by Callicles for his lack of concern with what others think of him (484c-486d). Socrates' tolerance of insult becomes legendary in the later tradition; cf. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 11.21, 35-36.
    • Lives of Eminent Philosophers , pp. 11-21
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 26
    • 77954048514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ajax's duel with Hector in book 7 of the Iliad suggests that he would have been a match for the Trojan hero after the death of Achilles. At Sophocles' Ajax 1340-1341, Odysseus calls Ajax "the best [ariston] of the Greeks who came to Troy, except Achilles
    • Ajax's duel with Hector in book 7 of the Iliad suggests that he would have been a match for the Trojan hero after the death of Achilles. At Sophocles' Ajax 1340-1341, Odysseus calls Ajax "the best [ariston] of the Greeks who came to Troy, except Achilles.
  • 27
    • 77954082041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plutarch Ale. 36.4-5
    • Plutarch Ale. 36.4-5;
  • 28
    • 77954079316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lys. 11.6-7. At Aegospotami, Lysander accomplished "the greatest deed [ergon megiston] with the least labor" (Lys. 11.6)
    • Lys. 11.6-7. At Aegospotami, Lysander accomplished "the greatest deed [ergon megiston] with the least labor" (Lys. 11.6).
  • 29
    • 0004314751 scopus 로고
    • Axioun, "to deem oneself worthy," implies both rating one's deserts high and asserting one's claims, trans. H. Rackham, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, note on Eudetnian Ethics 1233a3
    • Axioun, "to deem oneself worthy," implies both rating one's deserts high and asserting one's claims. Aristotle: Athenian Constitution, Eudemian Ethics, Virtues and Vices, trans. H. Rackham (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981), p. 343, note on Eudetnian Ethics 1233a3.
    • (1981) Athenian Constitution, Eudemian Ethics, Virtues and Vicesx , pp. 343
    • Aristotle1
  • 31
    • 60950539236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This observation helps to connect megalopsuchia and mikropsuchia with our ordinary understanding of magnanimity and pusillanimity: the great-souled man unstintingly does what he can for the good of the whole, whereas the small-souled man ungenerously withholds himself in doing less than he can. 22.1 am indebted here to Jaffa, Thomism and Aristotelianism, pp. 116-23
    • White, Sovereign Virtue, p. 256. This observation helps to connect megalopsuchia and mikropsuchia with our ordinary understanding of magnanimity and pusillanimity: the great-souled man unstintingly does what he can for the good of the whole, whereas the small-souled man ungenerously withholds himself in doing less than he can. 22.1 am indebted here to Jaffa, Thomism and Aristotelianism, pp. 116-23.
    • Sovereign Virtue , pp. 256
    • White1
  • 32
    • 77954049593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. 4.3.1123b34-1124al: "And he would not be worthy of honor if he were worthless. For honor is the prize of virtue, and it is given as tribute to the good
    • Cf. 4.3.1123b34-1124al: "And he would not be worthy of honor if he were worthless. For honor is the prize of virtue, and it is given as tribute to the good.
  • 33
    • 77952089305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 116-17. On this view, Aristotle's megalopsuchos directly anticipates the Stoic sage by achieving equanimity through theoretical perfection (Magnanimite, p. 118). While I shall argue below that Aristotle does regard Socrates as the true megalopsuchos, Gauthier and Jolif are able to identify Socrates with the great-souled man of EN 4.3 only by ignoring the ways in which they differ both from each other and from the sage or wise man
    • Gauthier, Magnanimite, pp. 63, 116-17. On this view, Aristotle's megalopsuchos directly anticipates the Stoic sage by achieving equanimity through theoretical perfection (Magnanimite, p. 118). While I shall argue below that Aristotle does regard Socrates as the true megalopsuchos, Gauthier and Jolif are able to identify Socrates with the great-souled man of EN 4.3 only by ignoring the ways in which they differ both from each other and from the sage or wise man.
    • Magnanimite , pp. 63
    • Gauthier1
  • 34
    • 77952089305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.. Gauthier and Jolif follow Aspasius in assimilating the godlike philosophers of the Republic and Theaetetus to the great-souled man (L'Ethique a Nicomaque, pp. 295-96)
    • Gauthier, Magnanimite, Ibid., pp. 104-109. Gauthier and Jolif follow Aspasius in assimilating the godlike philosophers of the Republic and Theaetetus to the great-souled man (L'Ethique a Nicomaque, pp. 295-96).
    • Magnanimite , pp. 104-109
    • Gauthier1
  • 36
    • 70349852255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Additional criticisms of Gauthier are advanced by Hardie, "Magnanimity," pp. 67-69. Jaffa maintains that "there is no suggestion of any philosophic attributes in the description of the magnanimous man"
    • Additional criticisms of Gauthier are advanced by Hardie, "Magnanimity," pp. 67-69. Jaffa maintains that "there is no suggestion of any philosophic attributes in the description of the magnanimous man" (Thomism and Aristotelianism, p. 121).
    • Thomism and Aristotelianism , pp. 121
  • 38
    • 0037958548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle states that reason is "what is most of all [malista] a human being," and that we ought to make ourselves immortal "as far as possible" (10.7.1178a7, 1177b33), thereby implying that theoretical reason "is not exclusively us, nor its activity exclusively our happiness," and that "there are constraints on how contemplative activity must be pursued: not as a god would, but as a human would, within the boundaries of our social and moral lives"
    • Aristotle states that reason is "what is most of all [malista] a human being," and that we ought to make ourselves immortal "as far as possible" (10.7.1178a7, 1177b33), thereby implying that theoretical reason "is not exclusively us, nor its activity exclusively our happiness," and that "there are constraints on how contemplative activity must be pursued: not as a god would, but as a human would, within the boundaries of our social and moral lives" (Sherman, Fabric of Character, p. 101).
    • Fabric of Character , pp. 101
    • Sherman1
  • 39
    • 77954079535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The great-souled man's forgetfulness of his dependence on others argues against Holloway's claim that "both the magnanimous man and the Christian can recognize that their virtues are not simply due to themselves, that in fact their virtues are for the most part due to someone else"
    • The great-souled man's forgetfulness of his dependence on others argues against Holloway's claim that "both the magnanimous man and the Christian can recognize that their virtues are not simply due to themselves, that in fact their virtues are for the most part due to someone else" ("Christianity, Magnanimity, and Statesmanship," p. 595).
    • Christianity, Magnanimity, and Statesmanship , pp. 595
  • 40
    • 77954041046 scopus 로고
    • Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, that "the formula for a 'tragic error'" is "to mistake a spurious whole for a whole"
    • Thus Michael Davis writes in Aristotle's Poetics: The Poetry of Philosophy (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992) that "the formula for a 'tragic error'" is "to mistake a spurious whole for a whole" (p. 60).
    • (1992) Thus Michael Davis Writes in Aristotle's Poetics: The Poetry of Philosophy , pp. 60
  • 41
    • 77953972462 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on tragedy: Rediscovering the poetics
    • Davis's development of this idea is echoed in other recent scholarship on the Poetics
    • Davis's development of this idea is echoed in other recent scholarship on the Poetics; see Jacob Howland, "Aristotle on Tragedy: Rediscovering the Poetics," Interpretation 22 (1995): 359-403.
    • (1995) Interpretation , vol.22 , pp. 359-403
    • Howland, J.1
  • 42
    • 31144432801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The reference to the Spartans is opaque
    • The reference to the Spartans is opaque; see Gauthier and Jolif, L'Ethique a Nicomaque, p. 287.
    • L'Ethique A Nicomaque , pp. 287
    • Gauthier1    Jolif2
  • 43
    • 60950259426 scopus 로고
    • That this limitation is the flip side of the great-souled man's frankness is hinted at by Montaigne, who claims to follow the megalopsuchos in "speak[ing] with entire freedom" but subsequently admits that "there may be some touch of pride and self-will in holding oneself so without reserve and candid as I do", trans. George B. Ives [New York: The Heritage Press], 878
    • That this limitation is the flip side of the great-souled man's frankness is hinted at by Montaigne, who claims to follow the megalopsuchos in "speak[ing] with entire freedom" but subsequently admits that "there may be some touch of pride and self-will in holding oneself so without reserve and candid as I do" (The Essays of Michel de Montaigne, trans. George B. Ives [New York: The Heritage Press, 1946], pp. 876, 878).
    • (1946) The Essays of Michel de Montaigne , pp. 876
  • 44
    • 0347854089 scopus 로고
    • Translation, New York: Anchor Books
    • Translation of Robert Fitzgerald, The Iliad (New York: Anchor Books, 1989).
    • (1989) The Iliad
    • Fitzgerald, R.1
  • 45
    • 77954049344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The question of whether one is a member of the first or the third Hesiodic class seems analogous to the question of whether he who is without a polis is a beast or a god (Pol. 1.1.1253a28-29). Cf. EN 7.1.1145al5-27, where Aristotle's observation that virtue and vice exist neither in beasts nor in gods is introduced immediately after he mentions Hector's heroic and godlike virtue
    • The question of whether one is a member of the first or the third Hesiodic class seems analogous to the question of whether he who is without a polis is a beast or a god (Pol. 1.1.1253a28-29). Cf. EN 7.1.1145al5-27, where Aristotle's observation that virtue and vice exist neither in beasts nor in gods is introduced immediately after he mentions Hector's heroic and godlike virtue.
  • 46
    • 78650715016 scopus 로고
    • Ehre und Tugend: Zur Megalopsychia der aristotelischen Ethik
    • Ernst A. Schmidt, "Ehre und Tugend: Zur Megalopsychia der aristotelischen Ethik," Archivfur Geschichte der Philosophic 49 (1967): 149-68;
    • (1967) Archivfur Geschichte der Philosophic , vol.49 , pp. 149-168
    • Schmidt, E.A.1
  • 47
    • 77954079790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see esp. pp. 164-168
    • see esp. pp. 164-168
  • 48
    • 77954037102 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle
    • Lord claims that the great-souled man's situation is "not inherently tragic," insofar as "friendship affords the great-souled man the satisfaction of his need for honor and community without compromising his attachment to virtue." , 3rd ed., ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Lord claims that the great-souled man's situation is "not inherently tragic," insofar as "friendship affords the great-souled man the satisfaction of his need for honor and community without compromising his attachment to virtue." "Aristotle," in History of Political Philosophy, 3rd ed., ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), p. 130.
    • (1987) History of Political Philosophy , pp. 130
  • 49
    • 77954057107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The latter qualification is necessary given the implied belief that to adjust one's life to an inferior is slavish, together with Aristotle's suggestion that friend is someone to whom the great-souled man is willing to adjust his life (4.3.1124b31-1125al)
    • The latter qualification is necessary given the implied belief that to adjust one's life to an inferior is slavish, together with Aristotle's suggestion that friend is someone to whom the great-souled man is willing to adjust his life (4.3.1124b31-1125al).
  • 50
    • 77954050795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Poetics 1448a26-27,1449b9-10. In the definition of tragic drama at 1449b24-28, tragedy is said to be "the imitation of a serious [spoudaias] action"; note also Aristotle's assertion that tragedy is an "imitation of men who are better than us" (1454b8-9)
    • Poetics 1448a26-27,1449b9-10. In the definition of tragic drama at 1449b24-28, tragedy is said to be "the imitation of a serious [spoudaias] action"; note also Aristotle's assertion that tragedy is an "imitation of men who are better than us" (1454b8-9).
  • 51
    • 77954044618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At Iliad 7.302, Ajax and Hector, having dueled, part "in friendship." Hector gives Ajax his sword, and receives a belt in exchange. In Sophocles' Ajax, Ajax kills himself by falling on Hector's sword. This gesture points toward the death he should have died-death at the hands of his only equal, who is paradoxically both friend and enemy
    • At Iliad 7.302, Ajax and Hector, having dueled, part "in friendship." Hector gives Ajax his sword, and receives a belt in exchange. In Sophocles' Ajax, Ajax kills himself by falling on Hector's sword. This gesture points toward the death he should have died-death at the hands of his only equal, who is paradoxically both friend and enemy.
  • 53
    • 77954074321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He states explicitly that no friendship is possible between gods and men (8.7.1158b33-36, 1159a5-8). The plain implication of his argument that the sole activity of the gods is contemplation (10.8.1178b8-23) is that there is also no friendship between gods and gods
    • He states explicitly that no friendship is possible between gods and men (8.7.1158b33-36, 1159a5-8). The plain implication of his argument that the sole activity of the gods is contemplation (10.8.1178b8-23) is that there is also no friendship between gods and gods.
  • 54
    • 77954078014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's references in this context to acting and to the sorrows of Niobe (7.3.1147a22-23,7.4.1147b33) suggest that tragedy may be a subtext of this discussion of hamartia. For further reflection on this passage see Howland, "Aristotle on Tragedy" p. 382
    • Aristotle's references in this context to acting and to the sorrows of Niobe (7.3.1147a22-23,7.4.1147b33) suggest that tragedy may be a subtext of this discussion of hamartia. For further reflection on this passage see Howland, "Aristotle on Tragedy" p. 382.
  • 55
    • 77954073316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Bolotin notes that "no beings are friends simply because they are good," for "our human friendships [are] a sign of neediness or imperfection as well as of our worth" (Plato's Dialogue on Friendship [Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1979], pp. 135,134). EN 9.9 obscures Aristotle's agreement with this point because it asks whether fully virtuous human beings need friends, but does not ask how such human beings could have become virtuous in the first place. So, too, Aristotle's silence about the origins of the great-souled man's virtue creates a misleading impression of his self-sufficiency. 45.1 owe these observations to Mary Nichols. Cf. 1124b24, where the greatsouled man is said to be "idle" and "given to delay." His inflexibility is reminiscent of that of Ajax, who chooses suicide to preserve his nobility, and whose anger endures even after his death (cf. Odyssey 11.553-567)
    • David Bolotin notes that "no beings are friends simply because they are good," for "our human friendships [are] a sign of neediness or imperfection as well as of our worth" (Plato's Dialogue on Friendship [Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1979], pp. 135,134). EN 9.9 obscures Aristotle's agreement with this point because it asks whether fully virtuous human beings need friends, but does not ask how such human beings could have become virtuous in the first place. So, too, Aristotle's silence about the origins of the great-souled man's virtue creates a misleading impression of his self-sufficiency. 45.1 owe these observations to Mary Nichols. Cf. 1124b24, where the greatsouled man is said to be "idle" and "given to delay." His inflexibility is reminiscent of that of Ajax, who chooses suicide to preserve his nobility, and whose anger endures even after his death (cf. Odyssey 11.553-567).
  • 56
    • 77954053252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ronna Burger discerns a similar subtext in the Ethics. In "Health of Soul and Psychic Medicine: on the Psychology of Aristotle's Ethics," an unpublished lecture delivered at St. John's College in April of 1997, Burger argues that "the true peak of the argument of the Ethics" is the emergence in book 9 of the Socratic soul as "the dialogic self" (p. 18)
    • Ronna Burger discerns a similar subtext in the Ethics. In "Health of Soul and Psychic Medicine: on the Psychology of Aristotle's Ethics," an unpublished lecture delivered at St. John's College in April of 1997, Burger argues that "the true peak of the argument of the Ethics" is the emergence in book 9 of the Socratic soul as "the dialogic self" (p. 18).
  • 57
    • 77954059125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not the only place in theNicomachean Ethics where Aristotle follows Plato in suggesting that what appears to be second best absolutely is in fact best of all for human beings. Cf. his reference to a "second sailing" at 2.9.1109a34-35 with Plato, Phaedo 99c-e and Statesman 300c
    • This is not the only place in theNicomachean Ethics where Aristotle follows Plato in suggesting that what appears to be second best absolutely is in fact best of all for human beings. Cf. his reference to a "second sailing" at 2.9.1109a34-35 with Plato, Phaedo 99c-e and Statesman 300c.
  • 58
    • 0004324469 scopus 로고
    • Philosophical fragments
    • Johannes Climacus, ed. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 11
    • S. Kierkegaard, Philosophical Fragments, in Philosophical Fragments, Johannes Climacus, ed. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), pp. 10,11.
    • (1985) Philosophical Fragments , pp. 10
    • Kierkegaard, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.