메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue 1, 2005, Pages 148-177

History and pattern

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 12344316938     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052505041063     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (11)

References (87)
  • 2
    • 84860082200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Overview" of Rawls spanning
    • 133 pages, Jon Mandle, (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books)
    • A recent book on liberalism by Jon Mandle offers an "overview" of Rawls spanning 133 pages, indicating how hard it would be to summarize Rawls in a few paragraphs. Jon Mandle, What's Left of Liberalism? (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2000).
    • (2000) What's Left of Liberalism?
    • Mandle, J.1
  • 3
    • 12344258738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Communitarianism, 'Social constitution', and autonomy
    • How separate are persons, exactly? Does Rawls presume that individuals are self-contained Robinson Crusoes, as he is sometimes accused of doing by communitarians and feminists? See Andrew Jason Cohen, "Communitarianism, 'Social Constitution', and Autonomy," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 80, no. 2 (1999): 121-35.
    • (1999) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.80 , Issue.2 , pp. 121-135
    • Cohen, A.J.1
  • 4
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971), 4.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 4
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 6
    • 12344273276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In passing, what is an "allotment"? Does the sun have an allotment of planets, or are we reserving "allotment" to refer to (potentially blameworthy) allocation decisions? On the one hand, if we use the term's broader sense - allotment as simply the fact of how things are distributed - it becomes true that there is an allotment of advantages, just as there is an allotment of planets, but it becomes false that the concept of justice applies whenever there is an allotment. (It does not apply to the allotment of planets.) On the other hand, if we use the term's narrower sense - allotting as deliberately assigning - it becomes at least arguably true that the concept of justice applies, but then it becomes false that the natural lottery of talent is an allotment, and it is this natural lottery that Rawls wants his theory of justice to cover.
  • 7
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 19. In passing, is it enough that none are known to be advantaged or disadvantaged? What if some of us have disadvantages none of us know about? Does not knowing about a disadvantage suffice to make it fair?
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 19
    • Rawls1
  • 8
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 302. The full statement of the principle is: Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are (a) to the greatest advantage of the least advantaged, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity. Part (a) is the notorious "difference principle."
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 302
  • 9
    • 12344329371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One frustrating thing about reading Rawls is that he systematically takes initially bold, clear, inspiring, unambiguous positions, then later reworks and retracts these statements so as to make them consistent with (or in technical terms, in reflective equilibrium with) his second principle.
  • 11
    • 12344321475 scopus 로고
    • Distributive justice
    • ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • John Rawls, "Distributive Justice," in Philosophy, Politics, and Society, ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967), 58-82. Reprinted in John Rawls, Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 135. Page citations are to the latter.
    • (1967) Philosophy, Politics, and Society , pp. 58-82
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 12
    • 0004279940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 135. Page citations are to the latter)
    • John Rawls, "Distributive Justice," in Philosophy, Politics, and Society, ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967), 58-82. Reprinted in John Rawls, Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 135. Page citations are to the latter.
    • (1999) Collected Papers
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 16
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls acknowledges that we do not need a "complete" theory in the international arena. In fact, in that arena, we do not want a complete theory; we want instead to recognize that "peoples" have a right to self-determination. Interestingly, Rawls shows more willingness in the international arena to compromise liberties protected by the first principle than to compromise the economic protections of the difference principle. (The Rawlsian right to life that any minimally decent society has to respect includes a right to economic security.) See John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 65.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 65
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 17
    • 12344267749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • when we are targeting one particular group as the group whose prospects are to be maximized, it will be hard to characterize the process or the result as an implication of any principle of reciprocity. Reciprocity is a two-way street, not aimed at any particular group, not even the group we think ought to be most favored. It would seem reasonable to give up on saying that this theory has anything to do with reciprocity, but Rawls always insisted there was a connection. For example, see John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 123-24.
    • (2001) Justice as Fairness: a Restatement , pp. 123-124
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 19
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999), 83.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice, Rev. Ed. , pp. 83
    • Rawls1
  • 26
    • 12344283726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Do we really need veils of ignorance as devices for controlling bias? I shall suggest an answer to this question shortly below in the text.
  • 27
    • 12344335502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There are two ways to view the procedure. Bargainers are either deciding what is right or discovering an independent moral reality. If our bargainers are merely hypothetical, we had better be able to show that there is an independent moral reality we are tracking when we decide to imagine bargainers agreeing to one thing rather than another. Otherwise, all we are doing is putting our own prejudices in the mouths of imaginary friends. If real bargainers actually agree to live by a principle, then that is altogether different. In that case, they actually gave their word to each other, and if their word does not count for something, they will not be able to live good lives together.
  • 28
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, 98. I argued in "Rationality within Reason," Journal of Philosophy 89, no. 9 (1992): 445-66, that satisfying choice is genuinely a form of rational choice. In my Rational Choice and Moral Agency (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), I argued that this opens up possibilities for reconciling elements of rationality with elements of morality. However, I never envisioned defending a suboptimal political regime on the grounds that I would prefer it to intolerable alternatives.
    • Justice as Fairness: a Restatement , pp. 98
    • Rawls1
  • 29
    • 0041742789 scopus 로고
    • Rationality within reason
    • Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, 98. I argued in "Rationality within Reason," Journal of Philosophy 89, no. 9 (1992): 445-66, that satisfying choice is genuinely a form of rational choice. In my Rational Choice and Moral Agency (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), I argued that this opens up possibilities for reconciling elements of rationality with elements of morality. However, I never envisioned defending a suboptimal political regime on the grounds that I would prefer it to intolerable alternatives.
    • (1992) Journal of Philosophy , vol.89 , Issue.9 , pp. 445-466
  • 30
    • 0041742790 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, 98. I argued in "Rationality within Reason," Journal of Philosophy 89, no. 9 (1992): 445-66, that satisfying choice is genuinely a form of rational choice. In my Rational Choice and Moral Agency (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), I argued that this opens up possibilities for reconciling elements of rationality with elements of morality. However, I never envisioned defending a suboptimal political regime on the grounds that I would prefer it to intolerable alternatives.
    • (1995) Rational Choice and Moral Agency
  • 32
    • 84935547375 scopus 로고
    • Justice as fairness: Political not metaphysical
    • This view begins to emerge most clearly in John Rawls, "Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14, no. 3 (1985): 223-51, reprinted in Rawls, Collected Papers, 388-414.
    • (1985) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.14 , Issue.3 , pp. 223-251
  • 33
    • 0004279940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view begins to emerge most clearly in John Rawls, "Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14, no. 3 (1985): 223-51, reprinted in Rawls, Collected Papers, 388-414.
    • Collected Papers , pp. 388-414
    • Rawls1
  • 34
    • 12344318117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I thank Mark LeBar and John Simmons for encouraging me to be clearer about these distinctions, and I especially thank Richard Arneson for a proposal about how best to draw the distinctions. I follow Arneson's proposal to a significant degree, but not enough to make him accountable for the result.
  • 37
    • 3543061492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press
    • Richard Epstein, in as excellent a short discussion of Nozick as one will find, makes a related point: "Any system of property looks backward to determine the 'chain of title' that gives rise to present holdings. But this is not because of any fetish with the past but chiefly from the profound sense that stability in transactions is necessary for sensible forward-looking planning." See Epstein, Skepticism and Freedom: A Modern Case for Classical Liberalism (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2003), 130. As Epstein would agree, though, dwelling too much on the past would be as problematic as ignoring the past, and for the same reason: it would reduce stability in transactions. A routine title search when selling a house is one thing; going back as many thousands of years as the land has been held is another.
    • (2003) Skepticism and Freedom: a Modern Case for Classical Liberalism , pp. 130
    • Epstein1
  • 38
    • 84932635624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Making amends
    • forthcoming.
    • Nozick endorses the undoing of wrongful transfers, but the point of undoing a wrongful transfer is simply that: to undo a wrongful transfer, not to make current holdings match a favored pattern. Nozick has no solution (perhaps there is no solution) to the problem of how to rectify injustice committed not by people now living but by their ancestors. There are places where people have been evening the score for centuries, and it will not stop until people learn to forget the past. For a state-of-the-art argument that successful rectification is about victims and victimizers (or their descendants) getting together to repair damaged relationships and set the stage for a peaceful future, see Linda Radzik, "Making Amends" (American Philosophical Quarterly, forthcoming). I discuss Radzik and add my own thoughts on rectification issues in David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
    • American Philosophical Quarterly
    • Radzik, L.1
  • 39
    • 84924493781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Nozick endorses the undoing of wrongful transfers, but the point of undoing a wrongful transfer is simply that: to undo a wrongful transfer, not to make current holdings match a favored pattern. Nozick has no solution (perhaps there is no solution) to the problem of how to rectify injustice committed not by people now living but by their ancestors. There are places where people have been evening the score for centuries, and it will not stop until people learn to forget the past. For a state-of-the-art argument that successful rectification is about victims and victimizers (or their descendants) getting together to repair damaged relationships and set the stage for a peaceful future, see Linda Radzik, "Making Amends" (American Philosophical Quarterly, forthcoming). I discuss Radzik and add my own thoughts on rectification issues in David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
    • (2005) Elements of Justice
    • Schmidtz, D.1
  • 42
    • 12144262806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toronto: Wadsworth
    • I borrow the point from Edward Feser, On Nozick (Toronto: Wadsworth, 2004), 71.
    • (2004) On Nozick , pp. 71
    • Feser, E.1
  • 43
    • 85047372223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 167. Rawls's reply: "The objection that the difference principle enjoins continuous corrections of particular distributions and capricious interference with private transactions is based on a misunderstanding." On the next page, Rawls clarifies: "[E]ven if everyone acts fairly as defined by the rules that it is both reasonable and practicable to impose on individuals, the upshot of many separate transactions will eventually undermine background justice. This is obvious once we view society, as we must, as involving cooperation over generations. Thus, even in a well-ordered society, adjustments in the basic structure are always necessary." See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 283-84. Rawls's clarification makes it hard to see why Rawls thinks Nozick misunderstood him. (I thank Tom G. Palmer for this point.) In any case, this is a major challenge in constructing a well-ordered constitutional democracy: how to avoid "necessary adjustments" that tell citizens that ownership of their income is a political football, and they are, to that extent, governed by men, not law.
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 167
    • Nozick1
  • 44
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 167. Rawls's reply: "The objection that the difference principle enjoins continuous corrections of particular distributions and capricious interference with private transactions is based on a misunderstanding." On the next page, Rawls clarifies: "[E]ven if everyone acts fairly as defined by the rules that it is both reasonable and practicable to impose on individuals, the upshot of many separate transactions will eventually undermine background justice. This is obvious once we view society, as we must, as involving cooperation over generations. Thus, even in a well-ordered society, adjustments in the basic structure are always necessary." See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 283-84. Rawls's clarification makes it hard to see why Rawls thinks Nozick misunderstood him. (I thank Tom G. Palmer for this point.) In any case, this is a major challenge in constructing a well-ordered constitutional democracy: how to avoid "necessary adjustments" that tell citizens that ownership of their income is a political football, and they are, to that extent, governed by men, not law.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 283-284
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 46
    • 0001333853 scopus 로고
    • Outline of a decision procedure for ethics
    • Rawls, The article was originally published in
    • John Rawls, "Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics," in Rawls, Collected Papers, 14. The article was originally published in 1951.
    • (1951) Collected Papers , pp. 14
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 48
    • 12344299336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Alyssa Bernstein for her help with this point
    • I thank Alyssa Bernstein for her help with this point.
  • 49
    • 12344288201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In this example, a million basketball fans choose to pay twenty-five cents each directly to Wilt Chamberlain in exchange for seeing him play - thus upsetting a previously existing pattern of distribution.
  • 51
    • 0035579179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individuals are seen by Rawls as not deserving their initial endowment packages. Consequently, talents are, to some degree, socially owned
    • (approvingly) summarizes
    • As Steven R. Smith (approvingly) summarizes, "individuals are seen by Rawls as not deserving their initial endowment packages. Consequently, talents are, to some degree, socially owned." Consequently? How would we get from the premise that talents are undeserved to the conclusion that talents are community property? Also, which community would we be talking about? Why not the United Nations, or the Church of Scientology? See Steven R. Smith, "The Social Construction of Talent," Journal of Political Philosophy 9, no. 1 (2001): 31.
    • Consequently?
    • Smith, S.R.1
  • 52
    • 0035579179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The social construction of talent
    • As Steven R. Smith (approvingly) summarizes, "individuals are seen by Rawls as not deserving their initial endowment packages. Consequently, talents are, to some degree, socially owned." Consequently? How would we get from the premise that talents are undeserved to the conclusion that talents are community property? Also, which community would we be talking about? Why not the United Nations, or the Church of Scientology? See Steven R. Smith, "The Social Construction of Talent," Journal of Political Philosophy 9, no. 1 (2001): 31.
    • (2001) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.9 , Issue.1 , pp. 31
    • Smith, S.R.1
  • 55
    • 12344263698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, "Distributive Justice," 140. Strictly speaking, this consideration leads only to a precursor form of the difference principle, which specifies that arrangements ought to be mutually advantageous.
    • Distributive Justice , pp. 140
    • Rawls1
  • 56
  • 58
    • 12344255701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ph.D. dissertation, University of Arizona
    • Cara Nine argues that arbitrariness is an essentially theory-laden concept, so that X is arbitrary only if X is wrong by the lights of a given moral theory. In that case, if we want to argue for a theory, and want to start with premises about what is arbitrary, the argument is likely to be question-begging. See Nine, "Moral Arbitrariness" (Ph.D. dissertation, University of Arizona, 2005).
    • (2005) Moral Arbitrariness
    • Nine1
  • 59
    • 12344321474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • When we call a choice arbitrary, we are implying not only that it is unjustified, and not only that it is wrong, but also that it exhibits a certain arrogance: there is nothing a person could say, or would even be inclined to say, to justify his or her choice. A person might say, "I can do whatever I want."
  • 61
    • 12344335499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In any system, the main way in which the talented share their talent is precisely by going as far as their talent can take them. What people pay in taxes normally will be trivial by comparison. To take an obvious case, how much did Thomas Edison pay in taxes? The answer is that we do not need to know, because we know that no matter how many millions Edison might have paid, the good done by his taxes was nothing compared to the good done by his inventions.
  • 62
    • 12344318116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even the most self-reliant bakers, of course, cooperate
    • Even the most self-reliant bakers, of course, cooperate.
  • 63
    • 12344285887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not to deny that the assumption is at some level intuitively compelling, or that it tacitly informs a lot of political theorizing.
  • 65
    • 84870749118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 33. See also A. R. Lacey, Robert Nozick (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 25ff.
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 33
  • 66
    • 4243066693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press) 25ff
    • Ibid., 33. See also A. R. Lacey, Robert Nozick (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 25ff.
    • (2001) Robert Nozick
    • Lacey, A.R.1
  • 67
    • 12344281015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this volume
    • For a cogent critique of the retreat from the first principle's original maximalist formulation, see Loren Lomasky, "Libertarianism at Twin Harvard," in this volume.
    • Libertarianism at Twin Harvard
    • Lomasky, L.1
  • 69
    • 0004895420 scopus 로고
    • Rawls on justice
    • ed. Norman Daniels (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press)
    • Thomas Nagel, "Rawls on Justice," in Reading Rawls, ed. Norman Daniels (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989), 13.
    • (1989) Reading Rawls , pp. 13
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 70
    • 84904518585 scopus 로고
    • The right to be rich or poor
    • ed. Jeffrey Paul (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Peter Singer, "The Right to Be Rich or Poor," in Reading Nozick, ed. Jeffrey Paul (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981), 48. Rawls likely would reply that utilitarianism is cavalier in its willingness to benefit some at the expense of others, so long as total utility thereby increases. Rawls's theory requires that transfers be justified to each individual. Singer probably would say that if that means the well-off have a veto, then Rawls's theory has all the problems of Nozick's; if not, the distinction between Rawls's theory and utilitarianism has not yet been made.
    • (1981) Reading Nozick , pp. 48
    • Singer, P.1
  • 71
    • 0041742788 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For excellent discussions of how the separateness of persons issue relates to issues of personal autonomy and agent-relative values, see chap. 5 of Horacio Specter's Autonomy and Rights: The Moral Foundations of Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992); Eric Mack, "Moral Individualism: Agent-Relativity and Deontic Restraints," Social Philosophy and Policy 7, no. 1 (1989): 81-111; and Eric Mack, "Self-Ownership, Marxism, and Egalitarianism," Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 1 (2002): 75-108.
    • (1992) Autonomy and Rights: The Moral Foundations of Liberalism
  • 72
    • 84928850584 scopus 로고
    • Moral individualism: Agent-relativity and deontic restraints
    • For excellent discussions of how the separateness of persons issue relates to issues of personal autonomy and agent-relative values, see chap. 5 of Horacio Specter's Autonomy and Rights: The Moral Foundations of Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992); Eric Mack, "Moral Individualism: Agent-Relativity and Deontic Restraints," Social Philosophy and Policy 7, no. 1 (1989): 81-111; and Eric Mack, "Self-Ownership, Marxism, and Egalitarianism," Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 1 (2002): 75-108.
    • (1989) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.7 , Issue.1 , pp. 81-111
    • Mack, E.1
  • 73
    • 85004489571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-ownership, marxism, and egalitarianism
    • For excellent discussions of how the separateness of persons issue relates to issues of personal autonomy and agent-relative values, see chap. 5 of Horacio Specter's Autonomy and Rights: The Moral Foundations of Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992); Eric Mack, "Moral Individualism: Agent-Relativity and Deontic Restraints," Social Philosophy and Policy 7, no. 1 (1989): 81-111; and Eric Mack, "Self-Ownership, Marxism, and Egalitarianism," Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 1 (2002): 75-108.
    • (2002) Politics, Philosophy, and Economics , vol.1 , pp. 75-108
    • Mack, E.1
  • 74
    • 12344268814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • American Philosophical Association
    • One difference, explored by Matt Zwolinski in his "The Separateness of Persons" (American Philosophical Association, 2003), is that while Nozick thinks of separateness as implying restrictions on how people may be treated, Rawls thinks of separateness as a meta-level desideratum. It does not restrict what we can do to people; instead, it restricts what we can offer as a justification for what we do.
    • (2003) The Separateness of Persons
    • Zwolinski, M.1
  • 75
    • 12344268814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls in effect holds that the sole implication of separateness is to require a basic structure to justify to each person the assigning of a consumption bundle to that person. See Zwolinski, "The Separateness of Persons," for more on the distinction between respecting separateness in the sense that rules out involuntary transfers from one to another and respecting separateness in the sense of involuntary transfers having to be justified to each individual. (But I note here that Rawls and his followers are not saying each individual has to agree that the transfers are justified; it is enough that "reasonable" people agree.)
    • The Separateness of Persons
    • Zwolinski1
  • 76
    • 0003696616 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Robert Paul Wolff, Understanding Rawls (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977), 201.
    • (1977) Understanding Rawls , pp. 201
    • Wolff, R.P.1
  • 79
    • 84870749118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis in original
    • Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 43 (emphasis in original). See also David Schmidtz, "The Meanings of Life," in Robert Nozick, ed. David Schmidtz (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 199-216.
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 43
    • Nozick1
  • 80
    • 12344286936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The meanings of life
    • ed. David Schmidtz (New York: Cambridge University Press)
    • Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 43 (emphasis in original). See also David Schmidtz, "The Meanings of Life," in Robert Nozick, ed. David Schmidtz (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 199-216.
    • (2002) Robert Nozick , pp. 199-216
    • Schmidtz, D.1
  • 82
    • 12344274284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nozick asks us, how would Rawlsian bargainers assign grades? Nozick says Rawlsian bargainers cannot even consider letting grades track performance. Bargainers want to make the lowest grade as high as possible. They do not care (or do not know they care) about the difference between giving the best grade to the best student and giving the best grade to the worst. It would be easy to overstate Nozick's point. In a zero-sum game, as where an average grade is fixed, Nozick would be right, but when we speak of positive-sum games, as in real market societies, everything changes. In a positive-sum game, Rawls can rule out giving the best grade to the worst student on strategic grounds, allowing that rewards can be used to manipulate the talented into performing in a way that enlarges the pie (maximizing the smallest slice). Nozick's complaint is not that such rewards would be too small, but rather that their rationale is brutally disrespectful.
  • 83
    • 0036436351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How to deserve
    • For an argument that we can deserve X in virtue of what we do after receiving X, see David Schmidtz, "How to Deserve," Political Theory 30, no. 6 (2002): 774-99. I thank Dan Russell for reminding me of this argument's relevance.
    • (2002) Political Theory , vol.30 , Issue.6 , pp. 774-799
    • Schmidtz, D.1
  • 86
    • 12344278949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Thomas Nagel worries, "Keeping in mind that the parties in the original position do not know the stage of development of their society, and therefore do not know what minimum will be guaranteed by a maximin strategy, it is difficult to understand how an individual can know that he 'cares very little, if anything, for what he might gain above the minimum'." See Nagel, "Rawls on Justice," 12.
    • Rawls on Justice , pp. 12
    • Nagel1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.